From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
Buddhist logico-epistemology is a term used in Western scholarship for pramāṇa-vāda (doctrine of proof) and Hetu-vidya (science of causes). Pramāṇa-vāda is an epistemological study of the nature of knowledge; Hetu-vidya is a system of logic. These models developed in India during the 5th through 7th centuries.
The early Buddhist texts show that the historical Buddha was
familiar with certain rules of reasoning used for debating purposes and
made use of these against his opponents. He also seems to have held
certain ideas about epistemology and reasoning, though he did not put
forth a logico-epistemological system. The structure of debating rules
and processes can be seen in the early Theravada text the Kathāvatthu.
The first Buddhist thinker to discuss logical and epistemic issues systematically was Vasubandhu in his Vāda-vidhi ("A Method for Argumentation"), who was influenced by the Hindu work on reasoning, the Nyāya-sūtra.
A mature system of Buddhist logic and epistemology was founded by the Buddhist scholar Dignāga (c. 480–540 CE) in his magnum opus, the Pramāṇa-samuccaya. Dharmakirti further developed this system with several innovations. Dharmakirti's Pramanavarttika ('Commentary on Valid Cognition') became the main source of epistemology and reasoning in Tibetan Buddhism.
Definition
Scholars such as H.N. Randle and Fyodor Shcherbatskoy (1930s) initially employed terms such as “Indian Logic” and “Buddhist Logic” to refer to the Indian tradition of inference (anumana), epistemology (pramana) and 'science of causes' (hetu-vidya). This tradition developed in the orthodox Hindu tradition known as Nyaya as well as in Buddhist philosophy. Logic in classical India, writes Bimal Krishna Matilal,
is "the systematic study of informal inference-patterns, the rules of
debate, the identification of sound inference vis-à-vis sophistical
argument, and similar topics". As Matilal notes, this tradition developed out systematic debate theory (vadavidya):
Logic as the study of the form of correct arguments and
inference patterns, developed in India from the methodology of
philosophical debate. The art of conducting a philosophical debate was
prevalent probably as early as the time of the Buddha and the Mahavira (Jina), but it became more systematic and methodical a few hundred years later.
‘Indian Logic’ should be understood as being a different system of logic than modern classical logic (e.g. modern predicate calculus), but as anumāna-theory, a system in its own right.
‘Indian Logic’ was also influenced by the study of grammar, whereas
Classical Logic which principally informed modern Western Logic was
influenced by the study of mathematics.
A key difference between Western Logic and Indian Logic is that
certain epistemological issues are included within Indian Logic, whereas
in modern Western Logic they are deliberately excluded. Indian Logic
includes general questions regarding the ‘nature of the derivation of
knowledge’, epistemology, from information supplied by evidence, evidence which in turn may be another item of knowledge.
For this reason, other scholars use the term "logico-epistemology" to
refer to this tradition, emphasizing the centrality of the epistemic
project for Indian logical reasoning. According to Georges Dreyfus, while Western logic tends to be focused on formal validity and deduction:
The concern of Indian "logicians" is quite different.
They intend to provide a critical and systematic analysis of the diverse
means of correct cognition that we use practically in our quest for
knowledge. In this task, they discuss the nature and types of pramana.
Although Indian philosophers disagree on the types of cognition that can
be considered valid, most recognize perception and inference as valid.
Within this context, which is mostly epistemological and practically
oriented, topics such as the nature and types of correct reasoning that
pertain to logic in the large sense of the word are discussed.
Pramana
Pramāṇa (Tib. tshad ma)
is often translated as "valid cognition" or "instrument of knowledge"
and refers to epistemic ways of knowing. Decisive in distinguishing Buddhist pramana from what is generally understood as Orthodox Hindu philosophy is the issue of epistemological justification. All schools of Indian logic recognize various sets of 'valid justifications for knowledge' or pramana. Buddhist logico-epistemology was influenced by the Nyāya
school's methodology, but where the Nyaya recognised a set of four
pramanas—perception, inference, comparison and testimony—the Buddhists
(i.e. the school of Dignaga) only recognized two: perception and
inference. For Dignaga, comparison and testimony are just special forms
of inference.
Most Indic pramanavada accept 'perception'
(Sanskrit: pratyakṣa) and 'inference' (Sanskrit: anumāna), but for some
schools of orthodox Hinduism the 'received textual tradition'
(Sanskrit: āgamāḥ) is an epistemological category equal to perception
and inference. The Buddhist logical tradition of Dignaga and Dharmakirti
accept scriptural tradition only if it accords with pratyakṣa and anumāna. This view is thus in line with the Buddha's injunction in the Kalama Sutta not to accept anything on mere tradition or scripture.
Early Buddhist background
Epistemology
The time of the Buddha Gautama was a lively intellectual culture with many differing philosophical theories. KN Jayatilleke,
in his "Early Buddhist Theory of Knowledge", uses the Pali Nikayas to
glean the possible epistemological views of the historical Buddha and
those of his contemporaries. According to his analysis of the Sangarava
Sutta, during the Buddha's time, Indian views were divided into three
major camps with regards to knowledge:
- The Traditionalists (Anussavika) who regarded knowledge as being
derived from scriptural sources (the Brahmins who upheld the Vedas).
- The Rationalists (Takki Vimamsi) who only used reasoning or takka (the skeptics and materialists).
- The "Experientialists" who held that besides reasoning, a kind of
supra-normal yogic insight was able to bring about unique forms of
knowledge (the Jains, the middle and late Upanishadic sages).
The Buddha rejected the first view in several texts such as the Kalama sutta, arguing that a claim to scriptural authority (sadda) was not a source of knowledge, as was claimed by the later Hindu Mimamsa school. The Buddha also seems to have criticized those who used reason (takka).
According to Jayatilleke, in the Pali Nikayas, this term refers
"primarily to denote the reasoning that was employed to construct and
defend metaphysical theories and perhaps meant the reasoning of sophists
and dialecticians only in a secondary sense". The Buddha rejected metaphysical speculations, and put aside certain questions which he named the unanswerables (avyakatas), including questions about the soul and if the universe is eternal or not.
The Buddha's epistemological view has been a subject of debate among modern scholars. Some such as David Kalupahana, have seen him first and foremost as an empiricist because of his teaching that knowledge required verification through the six sense fields (ayatanas). The Kalama sutta
states that verification through one's own personal experience (and the
experiences of the wise) is an important means of knowledge.
However, the Buddha's view of truth was also based on the
soteriological and therapeutic concern of ending suffering. In the
"Discourse to Prince Abhaya" (MN.I.392–4) the Buddha states that a
belief should only be accepted if it leads to wholesome consequences. has led scholars such as Mrs Rhys Davids and Vallée-Poussin to see the Buddha's view as a form of Pragmatism. This sense of truth as what is useful is also shown by the Buddha's parable of the arrow.
K. N. Jayatilleke sees Buddha's epistemological view as empirically-based which also includes a particular view of causation (dependent origination):
"inductive inferences in Buddhism are based on a theory of causation.
These inferences are made on the data of perception. What is considered
to constitute knowledge are direct inferences made on the basis of such
perceptions." Jayatilleke argues the Buddhas statements in the Nikayas tacitly imply an adherence to some form of correspondence theory, this is most explicit in the 'Apannaka Sutta'. He also notes that Coherentism
is also taken as a criterion for truth in the Nikayas, which contains
many instances of the Buddha debating opponents by showing how they have
contradicted themselves.
He also notes that the Buddha seems to have held that utility and truth
go hand in hand, and therefore something which is true is also useful
(and vice versa, something false is not useful for ending suffering). Echoing this view, Christian Coseru writes:
canonical sources make quite clear that several distinct
factors play a crucial role in the acquisition of knowledge. These are
variously identified with the testimony of sense experience,
introspective or intuitive experience, inferences drawn from these two
types of experience, and some form of coherentism, which demands that
truth claims remain consistent across the entire corpus of doctrine.
Thus, to the extent that Buddhists employ reason, they do so primarily
in order further to advance the empirical investigation of phenomena.
Debate and analysis
The Early Buddhist Texts show that during this period many different kinds of philosophers often engaged in public debates (vivada). The early texts also mention that there was a set procedure (patipada) for these debates and that if someone does not abide by it they are unsuitable to be debated.
There also seems to have been at least a basic conception of valid and
invalid reasoning, including, according to Jayatilleke, fallacies (hetvabhasah) such as petitio principii. Various fallacies were further covered under what were called nigrahasthana or "reasons for censure" by which one could lose the debate. Other nigrahasthanas included arthantaram or "shifting the topic", and not giving a coherent reply.
According to Jayatilleke, 'pure reasoning' or 'a priori' reasoning is rejected by the Buddha as a source of knowledge. While reason could be useful in deliberation, it could not establish truth on its own.
In contrast to his opponents, the Buddha termed himself a
defender of 'analysis' or 'vibhajjavada'. He held that after proper
rational analysis, assertions could be classified in the following way:
- Those which can be asserted or denied categorically (ekamsika)
- Those which cannot be asserted or denied categorically (anekamsika), which the Buddha further divided into:
- Those which after analysis (vibhajja-) could be known to be true or false.
- Those like the avyakata-theses, which could not be thus known.
This view of analysis differed from that of the Jains, which held that all views were anekamsika and also were relative, that is, they were true or false depending on the standpoint one viewed it from (anekantavada).
The early texts also mention that the Buddha held there to be 'four kinds of explanations of questions".
- a question which ought to be explained categorically
- a question which ought to be answered with a counter question
- a question which ought to be set aside (thapaniya)
- a question which ought to be explained analytically
The Buddha also made use of various terms which reveal some of his
views on meaning and language. For example, he held that many concepts
or designations (paññatti) could be used in conventional everyday
speech while at the same time not referring to anything that exists
ultimately (such as the pronouns like "I" and "Me"). Richard Hayes likewise points to the Potthapada sutta as an example of the Early Buddhist tendency towards a nominalist
perspective on language and meaning in contrast to the Brahmanical view
which tended to see language as reflecting real existents.
The Buddha also divided statements (bhasitam) into two types with
regards to their meaning: those which were intelligible, meaningful (sappatihirakatam) and those meaningless or incomprehensible (appatihirakatam). According to Jayatilleke, "in the Nikayas it is considered meaningless to make a
statement unless the speaker could attach a verifiable content to each of its terms."
This is why the Buddha held that statements about the existence of a
self or soul (atman) were ultimately meaningless, because they could not
be verified.
The Buddha, like his contemporaries, also made use of the "four corners" (catuṣkoṭi)
logical structure as a tool in argumentation. According to Jayatilleke,
these "four forms of predication" can be rendered thus:
- S is P, e.g. atthi paro loko (there is a next world).
- S is not P, e.g. natthi paro loko (there is no next world).
- S is and is not P, e.g. atthi ca natthi ca paro loko (there is and is no next world).
- S neither is nor is not P, e.g. n'ev'atthi na natthi paro loko (there neither is nor is there no next world)
The Buddha in the Nikayas seems to regard these as "'the four
possible positions' or logical alternatives that a proposition can
take".
Jayatilleke notes that the last two are clearly non-Aristotelian in
nature. The Buddhists in the Nikayas use this logical structure to
analyze the truth of statements and classify them. When all four were
denied regarding a statement or question, it was held to be meaningless
and thus set aside or rejected (but not negated).
Two levels of Truth
The early texts mention two modes of discourse used by the Buddha. Jayatilleke writes:
when he is speaking about things or persons we should
not presume that he is speaking about entities or substances;
to this extent his meaning is to be inferred (neyyattha-). But
when he is pointing out the misleading implications of speech
or using language without these implications, his meaning is
plain and direct and nothing is to be inferred (nitattha-). This
is a valid distinction which certainly holds good for the
Nikäyas at least, in the light of the above-statement.
The later commentarial and Abhidharma literature began to use this distinction as an epistemic one. They spoke of two levels of truth, the conventional (samutti), and the absolute (paramattha). This theory of double truth became very influential in later Buddhist epistemic discourse.
Kathāvatthu
The Theravada Kathāvatthu
(points of controversy) is a Pali Buddhist text which discusses the
proper method for critical discussions on doctrine. Its date is debated
by scholars but it might date to the time of Ashoka (C. 240 BC).
Western scholarship by St. Schayer and following him A. K. Warder, have
argued that there is an "anticipations of propositional logic" in the
text. However, according to Jonardon Ganeri "the leading concern of the text is with issues of balance and fairness
in the conduct of a dialogue and it recommends a strategy of
argumentation which guarantees that both parties to a point of
controversy have their arguments properly weighed and considered."
In the Kathāvatthu, a proper reasoned dialogue (vadayutti) is structured as follows: there is a point of contention – whether A is B; this is divided into several 'openings' (atthamukha):
- Is A B?
- Is A not B?
- Is A B everywhere?
- Is A B always?
- Is A B in everything?
- Is A not B everywhere?
- Is A not B always?
- Is A not B in everything?
These help clarify the attitude of someone towards their thesis in
the proceeding argumentative process. Jonardon Ganeri outlines the
process thus:
Each such ‘opening’ now proceeds as an independent
dialogue, and each is divided into five stages: the way forward
(anuloma), the way back (patikamma), the refutation (niggaha), the
application (upanayana) and the conclusion (niggamana). In the way
forward, the proponent solicits from the respondent the endorsement of a
thesis and then tries to argue against it. On the way back, the
respondent turns the tables, soliciting from the proponent the
endorsement of the counter-thesis, and then trying argue against it. In
the refutation, the respondent, continuing, seeks to refute the argument
that the proponent had advanced against the thesis. The application and
conclusion repeat and reaffirm that the proponent’s argument against
the respondent’s thesis is unsound, while the respondent’s argument
against the proponent’s counter-thesis is sound.
Milinda-panha
Another Buddhist text which depicts the standards for rational debate among Buddhists is the Milindapanha
("Questions of Menander", 1st century BCE) which is a dialogue between
the Buddhist monk Nagasena and an Indo-Greek King. In describing the art
of debate and dialogue, Nagasena states:
When scholars talk a matter over one with another, then
is there a winding up, an unravelling, one or other is convicted of
error, and he then acknowledges his mistake; distinctions are drawn, and
contra-distinctions; and yet thereby they are not angered.
The various elements outlined here make up the standard procedure of
Buddhist debate theory. There is an 'unravelling' or explication (nibbethanam) of one's thesis and stances and then there is also a 'winding up' ending in the censure (niggaho) of one side based on premises he has accepted and the rejoinders of his opponent.
Abhidharma views
The
Buddhist Abhidharma schools developed a classification of four types of
reasoning which became widely used in Buddhist thought. The Mahayana
philosopher Asanga in his Abhidharma-samuccaya, outlines these four reasons (yukti) that one may use to inquire about the nature of things. According to Cristian Coseru these are:
- The principle of dependence (apeksāyukti), which takes into
account the fact that conditioned things necessarily arise in dependence
upon conditions: it is a principle of reason, for instance, that
sprouts depend on seeds.
- The principle of causal efficacy (kāryakāranayukti), which accounts
for the difference between things in terms of the different causal
conditions for their apprehension: it is a principle of reason, thus,
that, in dependence upon form, a faculty of vision, and visual
awareness, one has visual rather than, say, auditory or tactile
experiences.
- The realization of evidence from experience
(sāksātkriyāsādhanayukti). We realize the presence of water from
moisture and of fire from smoke.
- The principle of natural reasoning, or the principle of reality
(dharmatāyukti), which concerns the phenomenal character of things as
perceived (for instance, the wetness and fluidity of water).
According to Coseru "what we have here are examples of natural
reasoning or of reasoning from experience, rather than attempts to use
deliberative modes of reasoning for the purpose of justifying a given
thesis or arguing for its conditions of satisfaction."
Nyaya influences
The
Nyaya school considers perception, inference, comparison/analogy, and
testimony from reliable sources as four means to correct knowledge,
holding that perception is the ultimate source of such knowledge.
The Nyāya Sūtras of Gotama (6th century BC – 2nd century CE)
is the founding text of the Nyaya school. The text systematically lays
out logical rules for argumentation in the form of a five-step schema
and also sets forth a theory of epistemology.
According to Jonardon Ganeri, the Nyaya sutra brought about a
transformation in Indian thinking about logic. First, it began a shift
away from interest in argumentation and debate towards the formal
properties of sound inference. Secondly, the Nyaya sutra led a shift to rule-governed forms of logical thinking.
BK Matilal outlines the five steps or limbs of the Nyaya method of reasoning as follows:
- There is fire on the hill. [thesis]
- For there is smoke. [reason]
- (Wherever there is smoke, there is fire), as in the kitchen. [example]
- This is such a case (smoke on the hill).
- Therefore, it is so, i.e., there is fire on the hill.
Later Buddhist thinkers like Vasubandhu would see several of these
steps as redundant and would affirm that only the first two or three
were necessary.
The Naiyayikas (the Nyaya scholars) also accepted four valid means (pramaṇa) of obtaining valid knowledge (pramana) - perception (pratyakṣa), inference (anumāna), comparison (upamāna) and word/testimony of reliable sources (śabda).
The systematic discussions of the Nyaya school influenced the
Medieval Buddhist philosophers who developed their own theories of
inferential reasoning and epistemic warrant (pramana). The Nyaya became
one of the main opponents of the Buddhists.
Mahayana Buddhist philosophy
Nagarjuna's Madhyamaka
Nagarjuna (c. 150 – c. 250 CE), one of the most influential Buddhist thinkers, defended the theory of the emptiness (shunyata) of phenomena and attacked theories that posited an essence or true existence (svabhava) to phenomena in his magnum opus The Fundamental Verses on the Middle Way. He used the Buddhist catuṣkoṭi ("four corners" or "four positions") to construct reductio ad absurdum
arguments against numerous theories which posited essences to certain
phenomena, such as causality and movement. In Nagarjuna's works and
those of his followers, the four positions on a particular thesis are
negated or ruled out (Sk. pratiṣedha) as exemplified by the first verse of Nagarjuna's Middle way verses which focuses on a critique of causation:
"Entities of any kind are not ever found anywhere
produced from themselves, from another, from both [themselves and
another], and also from no cause."
Nagarjuna also famously relied upon refutation based argumentation (vitanda) drawing out the consequences (prasanga) and presuppositions of his opponents' own theories and showing them to be self refuting. Because the vaitandika
only seeks to disprove his opponents arguments without putting forward a
thesis of his own, the Hindu Nyaya school philosophers such as Vatsyayana saw it as unfair and also irrational (because if you argue against P, you must have a thesis, mainly not P).
According to Matilal, Nagarjuna's position of not putting forth any
implied thesis through his refutations would be rational if seen as a
form of illocutionary act.
Nagarjuna's reductions and the structure of the catuṣkoṭi became very influential in the Buddhist Madhyamaka
school of philosophy which sees itself as a continuation of Nagarjuna's
thought. Nagarjuna also discusses the four modes of knowing of the
Nyaya school, but he is unwilling to accept that such epistemic means
bring us ultimate knowledge.
Nagarjuna's epistemic stance continues to be debated among modern
scholars, his skepticism of the ability of reason and language to
capture the nature of reality and his view of reality as being empty of
true existence have led some to see him as a skeptic, mystic, nihilist
or agnostic, while others interpret him as a Wittgensteinian analyst, an
anti-realist, or deconstructionist.
Nagarjuna is also said to be the author of the Upāyaśṛdaya one of the first Buddhist texts on proper reasoning and argumentation. He also developed the Buddhist theory of two truths, defending ultimate truth as the truth of emptiness.
Vasubandhu
Vasubandhu was one of the first Buddhist thinkers to write various works on sound reasoning and debate, including the Vādavidhi (Methods of Debate), and the Vādavidhāna (Rules of Debate).
Vasubandhu was influenced by the system of the Nyaya school. Vasubandhu introduced the concept of 'logical pervasion' (vyapti). He also introduced the Trairūpya (triple inferential sign).
The Trairūpya is a logical argument that contains three
constituents which a logical ‘sign’ or ‘mark’ (linga) must fulfill to be
'valid source of knowledge' (pramana):
- It should be present in the case or object under consideration, the ‘subject-locus' (pakṣa)
- It should be present in a ‘similar case’ or a homologue (sapakṣa)
- It should not be present in any ‘dissimilar case’ or heterologue (vipakṣa)
The Dignāga-Dharmakīrti tradition
Dignāga
Buddhist epistemology holds that perception and inference are the means to correct knowledge.
Dignāga
(c. 480 – 540 CE) is the founder of an influential tradition of
Buddhist logic and epistemology, which was widely influential in Indian
thought and brought about a turn to epistemological questions in Indian
philosophy. According to B.K. Matilal, "Dinnaga was perhaps the most creative logician in medieval (400-1100) India."
Dignāga's tradition of Buddhist logic is sometimes called the "School of Dignāga" or "The school of Dinnāga and Dharmakīrti". In Tibetan it is often called “those who follow reasoning” (Tibetan: rigs pa rjes su ‘brang ba); in modern literature it is sometimes known by the Sanskrit 'pramāṇavāda', often translated as "the Epistemological School" or "The logico-epistemological school."
Dignāga defended the validity of only two pramanas (instruments of knowledge, epistemic tools), perception and inference in his magnum opus, the Pramanasamuccaya.
As noted by Cristian Coseru, Dignāga's theory of knowledge is strongly
grounded on perception "as an epistemic modality for establishing a
cognitive event as knowledge".
His theory also does not "make a radical distinction between epistemology and the psychological processes of cognition."
For Dignāga, perception is never in error, for it is the most basic raw
sense data. It is only through mental construction and inferential
thinking that we err in the interpretation of perceptual particulars.
Dignāga also wrote on language and meaning. His "apoha"
(exclusion) theory of meaning was widely influential. For Dignāga, a
word can express its own meaning only by repudiating other meanings. The
word 'cow' gives its own meaning only by the exclusion of all those
things which are other than cow.
Dharmakīrti
Following Dignāga, Dharmakīrti (c. 7th century), contributed significantly to the development and application of Buddhist pramana theory. Dharmakīrti's Pramāṇavārttika, remains in Tibet as a central text on pramana and was widely commented on by various Indian and Tibetan scholars.
Dharmakīrti's theory of epistemology differed from Dignāga's by
introducing the idea that for something to be a valid cognition it must
"confirm causal efficacy" (arthakriyāsthiti) which "consists in [this cognition’s] compliance with [the object’s capacity to] perform a function" (Pramāṇavārttika 2.1ac).
He was also one of the primary theorists of Buddhist atomism,
according to which the only items considered to exist or be ultimately
real are momentary particulars (svalakṣaṇa) including material atoms and momentary states of consciousness (dharmas). Everything else is considered to be only conventional (saṃvṛtisat) and thus he has been seen as a nominalist, like Dignāga.
Vincent Eltschinger has argued that Buddhist epistemology, especially
Dharmakīrti's, was an apologetic response to attacks by hostile Hindu
opponents and thus was seen by Buddhists as "that which, by defeating
the outsiders, removes the obstacles to the path towards liberation."
Coseru meanwhile simply notes the inseparability of epistemic concerns
from spiritual praxis for Buddhist epistemologists such as Dharmakīrti:
It
is this praxis that leads a representative thinker such as Dharmakīrti
to claim that the Buddha, whose view he and his successors claim to
propound, is a true embodiment of the sources of knowledge. Thus, far
from seeing a tension between empirical scrutiny and the exercise of
reason, the Buddhist epistemological enterprise positions itself not
merely as a dialogical disputational method for avoiding unwarranted
beliefs, but as a practice aimed at achieving concrete, pragmatic ends.
As Dharmakīrti reminds his fellow Buddhists, the successful
accomplishment of any human goal is wholly dependent on having correct
knowledge.
Later figures of the tradition
The
Buddhist philosophers who are part of this pramana tradition include
numerous other figures who followed Dignāga and Dharmakīrti. They
developed their theories further, commented on their works and defended
their theories against Hindu and Buddhist opponents.
Fyodor Stcherbatsky divided the followers and commentators on Dharmakirti into three main groups:
- The philological school of commentators, these figures (such as Devendrabuddhi)
focused on "exactly rendering the direct meaning of the commented text
without losing oneself in its deeper implications". They all commented
on the Pramāṇavārttika.
- The Kashmiri school of philosophy, which sought to "disclose
the deep philosophic contents of the system of Dignāga and Dharmakīrti,
regarding it as a critical system of logic and epistemology." Its
founding figure was Dharmottara (8th century).
- The religious school of commentators, who sought to "disclose
the profound meaning of Dharmakirti's works and to reveal their
concealed ultimate tendency." Unlike the Kashmiri school, which saw
Dharmakīrti's work as primarily focused on epistemology and reasoning,
the "religious" school used Dharmakīrti in order to develop and comment
on the entirety of the metaphysics of Mahayana Buddhism. The founder of
this school was the layman Prajñakaragupta (740–800 C.E.), apparently a native of Bengal.
Some of the other figures of the epistemological school include:
- Īśvarasena, a disciple of Dignāga, and teacher of Dharmakīrti
- Śaṅkarasvāmin, wrote an introduction to Dignāga's logic
- Jinendrabuddhi (7th or 8th century), a commentator on Dignāga's Pramanasamuccaya
- Bāhuleya, a commentator on Dignāga's Nyāyamukha
- Śāntarakṣita (725–788), merged the pramana tradition with Madhyamaka
- Kamalaśīla, a student of Śāntarakṣita
- Śubhakara (650–750), was particularly noteworthy because he composed
a work which aimed at proving the objective reality of external things
and thus attempted to disprove Vijñānavāda (the doctrine of consciousness, idealism)
- Śākyabuddhi (ca. 700 C.E.), wrote a commentary on Dharmakīrti's Pramāṇavārttika
- Chandragomin, purported author of the *Nyāyasiddhyāloka
- Dharmottara (8th century), a philosopher from Kashmir who wrote some independent works and also a commentary on Dharmakīrti's Nyāyabindu and on his Pramanaviniscaya.
- Anandavardhana, wrote a sub commentary to Dharmottara's Pramana-viniscaya commentary.
- Vinītadeva (8th century), wrote a commentary on Dharmakīrti's Nyāyabindu
- Śāntabhadra, wrote a commentary on Dharmakīrti's Nyāyabindu
- Jinamitra, wrote a commentary on Dharmakīrti's Nyāyabindu
- Devendrabuddhi (7th century), wrote various commentaries, including one on Dharmakīrti's Pramāṇavārttika
- Karṇakagomin, wrote a commentary on Dharmakīrti's Pramāṇavārttika
- Manorathanandin, wrote a commentary on Dharmakīrti's Pramāṇavārttika
- Śakyamati, wrote a commentary on Dharmakīrti's Pramāṇavārttika
- Arcaṭa, wrote a commentary on Dharmakīrti's Hetubindu
- Prajñakaragupta (740–800 C.E.), author of the Pramāṇavārttikālaṅkāra ("Ornament of the Pramāṇavārttikā")
- Jina, a follower of Prajñakaragupta
- Ravigupta, a follower of Prajñakaragupta
- Yamari, a follower of Prajñakaragupta
- Śubhagupta (720–780), was a Vaibhāṣika writer on pramana, according to Kamalaśīla
- Śaṅkaranandana (10th century), a prolific author of at least 17 texts, known as "the second Dharmakīrti."
- Jñanasrimitra (975–1025), a "gate-scholar" at Vikramashila who wrote several original works
- Paṇḍita Aśoka (980–1040)
- Jñanasribhadra (1000–1100), wrote a commentary on the Pramāṇaviniścaya (Dharmakīrti)
- Jayanta (1020–1080), author of the Pramāṇavārttikālaṅkāraṭīkā, a commentary on Prajñakaragupta's text.
- Jitāri or Jetāri (940–1000), teacher of Atisha and author of numerous pramana texts.
- Durvekamiśra (970–1030), a disciple of Jitāri
- Ratnakīrti (11th century), a student of Jñanasrimitra
- Mokṣākaragupta (11th–12th centuries), author of the Tarkabhāṣā
- Vidyākaraśānti (1100–1200), author of the Tarkasopāna
- Śākyaśrībhadra, a Kashmiri pandita who was the teacher of the Tibetan Sakya Pandita
Influence and reception
Dignāga
also influenced non-Buddhist Sanskrit thinkers. According to Lawrence
J. McCrea, and Parimal G. Patil, Dignaga set in motion an "epistemic
turn" in Indian philosophy:
In the centuries following
Dignāga’s work, virtually all philosophical questions were reconfigured
as epistemological ones. That is, when making any claim at all, it came
to be seen as incumbent on a philosopher to situate that claim within a
fully developed theory of knowledge. The systematic articulation and
interrogation of the underlying presuppositions of all knowledge claims
thus became the central preoccupation of most Sanskrit philosophers.
The Hindu philosophers, especially those of the Nyāya, Vaiseshika and Vedanta schools, were in constant debate with the Buddhist epistemologists, developing arguments to defend their realist position against the nominalism of the Buddhists. Nyāya-Vaiseshika thinkers such as Uddyotakara and Prashastapada critiqued the views of Dignaga as they developed their own philosophy.
Vācaspati Miśra's Nyāya-vārtika-tātparya-tikā is almost entirely focused on outlining and defeating the arguments of the Buddhist epistemologists. Prabhākara
(active c. 6th century) meanwhile, may have been influenced by Buddhist
reasoning to move away from some of the realistic views of older Mīmāṃsā thought. The Vedanta scholar Śrīharṣa who attacked the realism of Nyāya may have been influenced by the Buddhists as well. Even the "New Reason" (Navya Nyāya) scholar Gaṅgeśa Upādhyāya shows an influence from the Buddhist epistemological school, in his arrangement of his Tattvacintāmaṇi.
Epistemology in the later Mādhyamaka school
Bhāvaviveka
Bhāvaviveka (c. 500 – c. 578) appears to be the first Buddhist logician to employ the 'formal syllogism' (Wylie: sbyor ba'i tshig; Sanskrit: prayoga-vākya) in expounding the Mādhyamaka view, which he employed to considerable effect in his commentary to Nagarjuna's Mūlamadhyamakakārikā entitled the Prajñāpradīpa.
To develop his arguments for emptiness, Bhāvaviveka drew on the work of
Dignāga which put forth a new way of presenting logical arguments.
Bhāvaviveka was later criticized by Chandrakirti (540-600) for his use of these positive logical arguments. For Chandrakirti, a true Mādhyamika only uses reductio ad absurdum
arguments and does not put forth positive arguments. Chandrakirti saw
in the logico-epistemic tradition a commitment to a foundationalist
epistemology and essentialist ontology. For Chandrakirti, a Mādhyamika's
job should be to just deconstruct concepts which presuppose an essence.
The Svātantrika Mādhyamikas
In
spite of Chandrakirti's critique, later Buddhist philosophers continued
to explain Madhyamaka philosophy through the use of formal syllogisms
as well as adopting the conceptual schemas of the Dignaga-Dharmakirti
school (and the closely related Yogacara school). These figures include Jñanagarbha (700–760), Śāntarakṣita (725–788), Kamalaśīla, Haribhadra and Ratnākaraśānti (c.1000). Another thinker who worked on both pramana and Madhyamaka was the Kashmiri pandita Parahitabhadra.
This tendency within Madhyamaka is termed Svātantrika, while Chandrakirti's stance is termed Prasangika. The Svatantrika-Prasaṅgika distinction is a central topic of debate in Tibetan Buddhist philosophy.
Probably the most influential figure in this tradition is Śāntarakṣita. According to James Blumenthal
Śāntarakṣita attempted to integrate the anti-essentialism of Nāgārjuna with the logico-epistemological thought of Dignāga (ca. 6th c.) and Dharmakīrti (ca. 7th c.) along with facets of Yogācāra/Cittamātra thought into one internally consistent, yet fundamentally Madhyamaka system.
This
synthesis is one of the last major developments in Indian Buddhist
thought, and has been influential on Tibetan Buddhist philosophy.
In the Tibetan tradition
Tom Tillemans,
in discussing the Tibetan translation and assimilation of the
logico-epistemological tradition, identifies two currents and
transmission streams:
The first is the tradition of the Kadampa
scholar Ngok Lodzawa Loden Shayrap (1059–1109) and Chapa Chögyi Sengge
(1109–69) and their disciples, mainly located at Sangpu Neutok. Chapa's Tshad ma’i bsdus pa
(English: 'Summaries of Epistemology and Logic') became the groundwork
for the ‘Collected Topics’ (Tibetan: Düra; Wylie: bsdus grwa)
literature, which in large part furnished the Gelugpa-based logical architecture and epistemology. These two scholars (whose works are now lost) strengthened the influence of Dharmakirti in Tibetan Buddhist scholarship.
There is also another tradition of interpretation founded by Sakya Pandita (1182–1251), who wrote the Tshad-ma rigs-gter (English: "Treasury of Logic on Valid Cognition"). Sakya pandita secured the place of Dharmakirti's pramanavarttika as the foundational text on epistemology in Tibet. Later thinkers of the Gelug
school such as Gyeltsap and Kaydrup attempted a synthesis of the two
traditions, with varying results. This is because the views of Chapa
were mostly that of Philosophical realism, while Sakya pandita was an anti-realist.