The stationary-action principle – also known as the principle of least action – is a variational principle that, when applied to the action of a mechanical system, yields the equations of motion for that system. The principle states that the trajectories (i.e. the solutions of the equations of motion) are stationary points of the system's action functional.
The term "least action" is a historical misnomer since the principle
has no minimality requirement: the value of the action functional need
not be minimal (even locally) on the trajectories.
The classical mechanics and electromagnetic expressions are a
consequence of quantum mechanics. The stationary action method helped in
the development of quantum mechanics. In 1933, the physicist Paul Dirac demonstrated how this principle can be used in quantum calculations by discerning the quantum mechanical underpinning of the principle in the quantum interference of amplitudes. Subsequently Julian Schwinger and Richard Feynman independently applied this principle in quantum electrodynamics.
Scholars often credit Pierre Louis Maupertuis for formulating the principle of least action because he wrote about it in 1744 and 1746. However, Leonhard Euler discussed the principle in 1744, and evidence shows that Gottfried Leibniz preceded both by 39 years.
General statement
As the system evolves, q traces a path through configuration space (only some are shown). The path taken by the system (red) has a stationary action (δS = 0) under small changes in the configuration of the system (δq).
The starting point is the action, denoted (calligraphic S), of a physical system. It is defined as the integral of the LagrangianL between two instants of timet1 and t2 – technically a functional of the Ngeneralized coordinatesq = (q1, q2, ... , qN) which are functions of time and define the configuration of the system:
where δ (lowercase Greek delta) means a small change. In words this reads:
The path taken by the system between times t1 and t2 and configurations q1 and q2 is the one for which the action is stationary (no change) to first order.
Stationary action is not always a minimum, despite the historical name of least action. It is a minimum principle for sufficiently short, finite segments in the path.
In applications the statement and definition of action are taken together:
The action and Lagrangian both contain the dynamics of the system for
all times. The term "path" simply refers to a curve traced out by the
system in terms of the coordinates in the configuration space, i.e. the curve q(t), parameterized by time (see also parametric equation for this concept).
In the 1600s, Pierre de Fermat postulated that "light travels between two given points along the path of shortest time," which is known as the principle of least time or Fermat's principle.
Credit for the formulation of the principle of least action is commonly given to Pierre Louis Maupertuis, who felt that "Nature is thrifty in all its actions", and applied the principle broadly:
The laws of movement and of rest
deduced from this principle being precisely the same as those observed
in nature, we can admire the application of it to all phenomena. The
movement of animals, the vegetative growth of plants ... are only its
consequences; and the spectacle of the universe becomes so much the
grander, so much more beautiful, the worthier of its Author, when one
knows that a small number of laws, most wisely established, suffice for
all movements.
— Pierre Louis Maupertuis
This notion of Maupertuis, although somewhat deterministic today, does capture much of the essence of mechanics.
In application to physics, Maupertuis suggested that the quantity
to be minimized was the product of the duration (time) of movement
within a system by the "vis viva",
Maupertuis' principle
which is the integral of twice what we now call the kinetic energyT of the system.
Euler
Leonhard Euler gave a formulation of the action principle in 1744, in very recognizable terms, in the Additamentum 2 to his Methodus Inveniendi Lineas Curvas Maximi Minive Proprietate Gaudentes. Beginning with the second paragraph:
Let the mass of the projectile be M, and let its speed be v while being moved over an infinitesimal distance ds. The body will have a momentum Mv that, when multiplied by the distance ds, will give Mvds, the momentum of the body integrated over the distance ds.
Now I assert that the curve thus described by the body to be the curve
(from among all other curves connecting the same endpoints) that
minimizes
or, provided that M is constant along the path,
.
— Leonhard Euler
As Euler states, ∫Mvds is the integral of the momentum over distance travelled, which, in modern notation, equals the abbreviated or reduced action
Euler's principle
Thus, Euler made an equivalent and (apparently) independent statement
of the variational principle in the same year as Maupertuis, albeit
slightly later. Curiously, Euler did not claim any priority, as the
following episode shows.
Disputed priority
Maupertuis' priority was disputed in 1751 by the mathematician Samuel König, who claimed that it had been invented by Gottfried Leibniz
in 1707. Although similar to many of Leibniz's arguments, the principle
itself has not been documented in Leibniz's works. König himself showed
a copy of a 1707 letter from Leibniz to Jacob Hermann with the principle, but the original letter has been lost. In contentious proceedings, König was accused of forgery, and even the King of Prussia entered the debate, defending Maupertuis (the head of his Academy), while Voltaire defended König.
Euler, rather than claiming priority, was a staunch defender of
Maupertuis, and Euler himself prosecuted König for forgery before the
Berlin Academy on 13 April 1752. The claims of forgery were re-examined 150 years later, and archival work by C.I. Gerhardt in 1898 and W. Kabitz in 1913 uncovered other copies of the letter, and three others cited by König, in the Bernoulli archives.
Further development
Euler continued to write on the topic; in his Réflexions sur quelques loix générales de la nature (1748), he called action "effort". His expression corresponds to modern potential energy,
and his statement of least action says that the total potential energy
of a system of bodies at rest is minimized, a principle of modern
statics.
Much of the calculus of variations was stated by Joseph-Louis Lagrange in 1760 and he proceeded to apply this to problems in dynamics. In Mécanique analytique (1788) Lagrange derived the general equations of motion of a mechanical body. William Rowan Hamilton in 1834 and 1835 applied the variational principle to the classical Lagrangianfunction
In 1842, Carl Gustav Jacobi tackled the problem of whether the variational principle always found minima as opposed to other stationary points (maxima or stationary saddle points); most of his work focused on geodesics on two-dimensional surfaces. The first clear general statements were given by Marston Morse in the 1920s and 1930s, leading to what is now known as Morse theory. For example, Morse showed that the number of conjugate points
in a trajectory equalled the number of negative eigenvalues in the
second variation of the Lagrangian. A particularly elegant derivation of
the Euler-Lagrange equation was formulated by Constantin Caratheodory and published by him in 1935.
The mathematical equivalence of the differentialequations of motion and their integral
counterpart has important philosophical implications. The differential
equations are statements about quantities localized to a single point in
space or single moment of time. For example, Newton's second law
states that the instantaneous force F applied to a mass m produces an acceleration a at the same instant.
By contrast, the action principle is not localized to a point; rather,
it involves integrals over an interval of time and (for fields) an
extended region of space. Moreover, in the usual formulation of classical action principles, the initial and final states of the system are fixed, e.g.,
Given that the particle begins at position x1 at time t1 and ends at position x2 at time t2, the physical trajectory that connects these two endpoints is an extremum of the action integral.
In particular, the fixing of the final state has been interpreted as giving the action principle a teleological character which has been controversial historically. However, according to W. Yourgrau and S. Mandelstam, the
teleological approach... presupposes that the variational principles
themselves have mathematical characteristics which they de facto do not possess In addition, some critics maintain this apparent teleology
occurs because of the way in which the question was asked. By
specifying some but not all aspects of both the initial and final
conditions (the positions but not the velocities) we are making some
inferences about the initial conditions from the final conditions, and
it is this "backward" inference that can be seen as a teleological
explanation. Teleology can also be overcome if we consider the classical
description as a limiting case of the quantum formalism of path integration, in which stationary paths are obtained as a result of interference of amplitudes along all possible paths.
The short story Story of Your Life by the speculative fiction writer Ted Chiang contains visual depictions of Fermat's Principle along with a discussion of its teleological dimension. Keith Devlin's The Math Instinct
contains a chapter, "Elvis the Welsh Corgi Who Can Do Calculus" that
discusses the calculus "embedded" in some animals as they solve the
"least time" problem in actual situations.
In physics, action is a numerical value describing how a physical system has changed over time. Action is significant because the equations of motion of the system can be derived through the principle of stationary action. In the simple case of a single particle moving with a specified velocity, the action is the momentum of the particle times the distance it moves, added up along its path, or equivalently, twice its kinetic energy
times the length of time for which it has that amount of energy, added
up over the period of time under consideration. For more complicated
systems, all such quantities are added together. More formally, action
is a mathematical functional which takes the trajectory, also called path or history, of the system as its argument and has a real number as its result. Generally, the action takes different values for different paths. Action has dimensions of energy × time or momentum × length, and its SI unit is joule-second (like the Planck constanth).
Hamilton's principle states that the differential equations of motion for any physical system can be re-formulated as an equivalent integral equation. Thus, there are two distinct approaches for formulating dynamical models.
Empirical laws are frequently expressed as differential equations, which describe how physical quantities such as position and momentum change continuously with time, space or a generalization thereof. Given the initial and boundary conditions for the situation, the "solution" to these empirical equations is one or more functions that describe the behavior of the system and are called equations of motion.
Minimization of action integral
Action
is a part of an alternative approach to finding such equations of
motion. Classical mechanics postulates that the path actually followed
by a physical system is that for which the action is minimized, or more generally, is stationary. In other words, the action satisfies a variational principle: the principle of stationary action (see also below). The action is defined by an integral, and the classical equations of motion of a system can be derived by minimizing the value of that integral.
This simple principle provides deep insights into physics, and is an important concept in modern theoretical physics.
History
Action was defined in several now obsolete ways during the development of the concept.
Leonhard Euler
(and, possibly, Leibniz) defined action for a material particle as the
integral of the particle's speed along its path through space.
Pierre Louis Maupertuis introduced several ad hoc and contradictory definitions of action within a single article,
defining action as potential energy, as virtual kinetic energy, and as a
hybrid that ensured conservation of momentum in collisions.
Mathematical definition
Expressed in mathematical language, using the calculus of variations, the evolution of a physical system (i.e., how the system actually progresses from one state to another) corresponds to a stationary point (usually, a minimum) of the action.
Several different definitions of "the action" are in common use in physics. The action is usually an integral over time. However, when the action pertains to fields,
it may be integrated over spatial variables as well. In some cases, the
action is integrated along the path followed by the physical system.
The action is typically represented as an integral over time, taken along the path of the system between the initial time and the final time of the development of the system:
where the integrand L is called the Lagrangian. For the action integral to be well-defined, the trajectory has to be bounded in time and space.
Most commonly, the term is used for a functional which takes a function of time and (for fields) space as input and returns a scalar. In classical mechanics, the input function is the evolution q(t) of the system between two times t1 and t2, where q represents the generalized coordinates. The action is defined as the integral of the LagrangianL for an input evolution between the two times:
where the endpoints of the evolution are fixed and defined as and . According to Hamilton's principle, the true evolution qtrue(t) is an evolution for which the action is stationary (a minimum, maximum, or a saddle point). This principle results in the equations of motion in Lagrangian mechanics.
Abbreviated action (functional)
Usually denoted as , this is also a functional. Here the input function is the path
followed by the physical system without regard to its parameterization
by time. For example, the path of a planetary orbit is an ellipse, and
the path of a particle in a uniform gravitational field is a parabola;
in both cases, the path does not depend on how fast the particle
traverses the path. The abbreviated action is defined as the integral of the generalized momenta along a path in the generalized coordinates:
The Hamilton's principal function is obtained from the action functional by fixing the initial time and the initial endpoint while allowing the upper time limit and the second endpoint to vary. The Hamilton's principal function satisfies the Hamilton–Jacobi equation, a formulation of classical mechanics. Due to a similarity with the Schrödinger equation, the Hamilton–Jacobi equation provides, arguably, the most direct link with quantum mechanics.
where the time-independent function W(q1, q2, … qN) is called Hamilton's characteristic function. The physical significance of this function is understood by taking its total time derivative
The Hamilton–Jacobi equations are often solved by additive separability; in some cases, the individual terms of the solution, e.g., Sk(qk), are also called an "action".
Action of a generalized coordinate
This is a single variable Jk in the action-angle coordinates, defined by integrating a single generalized momentum around a closed path in phase space, corresponding to rotating or oscillating motion:
The variable Jk is called the "action" of the generalized coordinate qk; the corresponding canonical variable conjugate to Jk is its "angle" wk, for reasons described more fully under action-angle coordinates. The integration is only over a single variable qk and, therefore, unlike the integrated dot product in the abbreviated action integral above. The Jk variable equals the change in Sk(qk) as qk is varied around the closed path. For several physical systems of interest, Jk is either a constant or varies very slowly; hence, the variable Jk is often used in perturbation calculations and in determining adiabatic invariants.
In Lagrangian mechanics, the requirement that the action integral be stationary under small perturbations is equivalent to a set of differential equations (called the Euler–Lagrange equations) that may be obtained using the calculus of variations.
The trajectory (path in spacetime) of a body in a gravitational field can be found using the action principle. For a free falling body, this trajectory is a geodesic.
Implications of symmetries in a physical situation can be found with the action principle, together with the Euler–Lagrange equations, which are derived from the action principle. An example is Noether's theorem, which states that to every continuous symmetry in a physical situation there corresponds a conservation law (and conversely). This deep connection requires that the action principle be assumed.
In quantum mechanics, the system does not follow a single path whose
action is stationary, but the behavior of the system depends on all
permitted paths and the value of their action. The action corresponding
to the various paths is used to calculate the path integral, which gives the probability amplitudes of the various outcomes.
Although equivalent in classical mechanics with Newton's laws, the action principle
is better suited for generalizations and plays an important role in
modern physics. Indeed, this principle is one of the great
generalizations in physical science. It is best understood within
quantum mechanics, particularly in Richard Feynman's path integral formulation, where it arises out of destructive interference of quantum amplitudes.
When relativistic effects are significant, the action of a point particle of mass m travelling a world lineC parametrized by the proper time is
If instead, the particle is parametrized by the coordinate time t of the particle and the coordinate time ranges from t1 to t2, then the action becomes
The action principle can be generalized still further. For example, the action need not be an integral, because nonlocal actions are possible. The configuration space need not even be a functional space, given certain features such as noncommutative geometry. However, a physical basis for these mathematical extensions remains to be established experimentally.
Originally proposed in 1899 by German physicist Max Planck, these units are a system of natural units because the origin of their definition comes only from properties of nature and not from any human construct. Planck units are only one of several systems of natural units, but Planck units are not based on properties of any prototype object or particle (the choice of which is inherently arbitrary), but rather on only the properties of free space. They are relevant in research on unified theories such as quantum gravity.
The term Planck scale refers to quantities of space, time,
energy and other units that are similar in magnitude to corresponding
Planck units. This region may be characterized by energies of around 1019 GeV, time intervals of around 10−43 s and lengths of around 10−35 m
(approximately respectively the energy-equivalent of the Planck mass,
the Planck time and the Planck length). At the Planck scale, the
predictions of the Standard Model, quantum field theory and general relativity are not expected to apply, and quantum effects of gravity are expected to dominate. The best-known example is represented by the conditions in the first 10−43 seconds of our universe after the Big Bang, approximately 13.8 billion years ago.
The four universal constants that, by definition, have a numeric value 1 when expressed in these units are:
Planck units do not incorporate an electromagnetic dimension. Some
authors choose to extend the system to electromagnetism by, for example,
adding either the electric constantε0 or 4πε0
to this list. Similarly, authors choose to use variants of the system
that give other numeric values to one or more of the four constants
above.
Introduction
Any system of measurement may be assigned a mutually independent set of base quantities and associated base units, from which all other quantities and units may be derived. In the International System of Units, for example, the SI base quantities include length with the associated unit of the metre.
In the system of Planck units, a similar set of base quantities and
associated units may be selected, in terms of which other quantities and
coherent units may be expressed. The Planck unit of length has become
known as the Planck length,
and the Planck unit of time is known as the Planck time, but this
nomenclature has not been established as extending to all quantities.
All Planck units are derived from the dimensional universal
physical constants that define the system, and in a convention in which
these units are omitted (i.e. treated as having the dimensionless value
1), these constants are then eliminated from equations of physics in
which they appear. For example, Newton's law of universal gravitation,
can be expressed as:
Both equations are dimensionally consistent and equally valid in any system of quantities, but the second equation, with G absent, is relating only dimensionless quantities
since any ratio of two like-dimensioned quantities is a dimensionless
quantity. If, by a shorthand convention, it is understood that each
physical quantity is the corresponing ratio with a coherent Planck unit
(or "expressed in Planck units"), the ratios above may be expressed
simply with the symbols of physical quantity, without being scaled
explicitly by their corresponding unit:
This last equation (without G) is valid with F′, m1′, m2′, and r′ being the dimensionless ratio quantities corresponding to the standard quantities, written e.g. F′ ≘ F or F′ = F/FP, but not as a direct equality of quantities. This may seem to be "setting the constants c, G,
etc., to 1" if the correspondence of the quantities is thought of as
equality. For this reason, Planck or other natural units should be
employed with care. Referring to "G = c = 1", Paul S. Wesson
wrote that, "Mathematically it is an acceptable trick which saves
labour. Physically it represents a loss of information and can lead to
confusion."
History and definition
The concept of natural units was introduced in 1881, when George Johnstone Stoney, noting that electric charge is quantized, derived units of length, time, and mass, now named Stoney units in his honor, by normalizing G, c, and the electron charge, e, to 1. In 1899, one year before the advent of quantum theory, Max Planck introduced what became later known as the Planck constant. At the end of the paper, he proposed the base units later named in his honor. The Planck units are based on the quantum of action, now usually known as the Planck constant, which appeared in the Wien approximation for blackbody radiation. Planck underlined the universality of the new unit system, writing:
... die Möglichkeit gegeben ist,
Einheiten für Länge, Masse, Zeit und Temperatur aufzustellen, welche,
unabhängig von speciellen Körpern oder Substanzen, ihre Bedeutung für
alle Zeiten und für alle, auch außerirdische und außermenschliche
Culturen notwendig behalten und welche daher als »natürliche
Maßeinheiten« bezeichnet werden können.
... it is possible to set up units for length, mass, time and
temperature, which are independent of special bodies or substances,
necessarily retaining their meaning for all times and for all
civilizations, including extraterrestrial and non-human ones, which can
be called "natural units of measure".
Planck considered only the units based on the universal constants , , , and to arrive at natural units for length, time, mass, and temperature. His definitions differ from the modern ones by a factor of , because the modern definitions use rather than .
Table 1: Modern values for Planck's original choice of quantities
Unlike the case with the International System of Units, there is no official entity that establishes a definition of a Planck unit system. Frank Wilczek and Barton Zwiebach
both define the base Planck units to be those of mass, length and time,
regarding an additional unit for temperature to be redundant. Other tabulations add, in addition to a unit for temperature, a unit for electric charge, sometimes also replacing mass with energy when doing so. Depending on the author's choice, this charge unit is given by
or
The Planck charge, as well as other electromagnetic units that can be
defined like resistance and magnetic flux, are more difficult to
interpret than Planck's original units and are used less frequently.
In SI units, the values of c, h, e and kB are exact and the values of ε0 and G in SI units respectively have relative uncertainties of 1.5×10−10 and 2.2×10−5. Hence, the uncertainties in the SI values of the Planck units derive almost entirely from uncertainty in the SI value of G.
Derived units
In
any system of measurement, units for many physical quantities can be
derived from base units. Table 2 offers a sample of derived Planck
units, some of which in fact are seldom used. As with the base units,
their use is mostly confined to theoretical physics because most of them
are too large or too small for empirical or practical use and there are
large uncertainties in their values.
Some Planck units, such as of time and length, are many orders of magnitude
too large or too small to be of practical use, so that Planck units as a
system are typically only relevant to theoretical physics. In some
cases, a Planck unit may suggest a limit to a range of a physical
quantity where present-day theories of physics apply. For example, our understanding of the Big Bang does not extend to the Planck epoch,
i.e., when the universe was less than one Planck time old. Describing
the universe during the Planck epoch requires a theory of quantum gravity that would incorporate quantum effects into general relativity. Such a theory does not yet exist.
Several quantities are not "extreme" in magnitude, such as the Planck mass, which is about 22 micrograms:
very large in comparison with subatomic particles, and within the mass
range of living organisms. It has been speculated that it may be an approximate lower limit
at which a black hole could be formed by collapse. Similarly, the
related units of energy and of momentum are in the range of some
everyday phenomena.
Significance
Planck units have little anthropocentric arbitrariness, but do still involve some arbitrary choices in terms of the defining constants. Unlike the metre and second, which exist as base units in the SI system for historical reasons, the Planck length
and Planck time are conceptually linked at a fundamental physical
level. Consequently, natural units help physicists to reframe questions.
Frank Wilczek puts it succinctly:
We see that the question [posed] is
not, "Why is gravity so feeble?" but rather, "Why is the proton's mass
so small?" For in natural (Planck) units, the strength of gravity simply
is what it is, a primary quantity, while the proton's mass is the tiny
number [1/(13 quintillion)].
While it is true that the electrostatic repulsive force between two
protons (alone in free space) greatly exceeds the gravitational
attractive force between the same two protons, this is not about the
relative strengths of the two fundamental forces. From the point of view
of Planck units, this is comparing apples with oranges, because mass and electric charge are incommensurable quantities. Rather, the disparity of magnitude of force is a manifestation of the fact that the charge on the protons is approximately the unit charge but the mass of the protons is far less than the unit mass.
At
the Planck length scale, the strength of gravity is expected to become
comparable with the other forces, and it is theorized that all the
fundamental forces are unified at that scale, but the exact mechanism of
this unification remains unknown. The Planck scale is therefore the
point where the effects of quantum gravity can no longer be ignored in
other fundamental interactions, where current calculations and approaches begin to break down, and a means to take account of its impact is necessary.
While physicists have a fairly good understanding of the other fundamental interactions of forces on the quantum level, gravity is problematic, and cannot be integrated with quantum mechanics
at very high energies using the usual framework of quantum field
theory. At lesser energy levels it is usually ignored, while for
energies approaching or exceeding the Planck scale, a new theory of quantum gravity is necessary. Approaches to this problem include string theory and M-theory, loop quantum gravity, noncommutative geometry, and causal set theory.
In Big Bang cosmology, the Planck epoch or Planck era is the earliest stage of the Big Bang, before the time passed was equal to the Planck time, tP, or approximately 10−43 seconds. There is no currently available physical theory to describe such short times, and it is not clear in what sense the concept of time is meaningful for values smaller than the Planck time. It is generally assumed that quantum effects of gravity dominate physical interactions at this time scale. At this scale, the unified force of the Standard Model is assumed to be unified with gravitation. Immeasurably hot and dense, the state of the Planck epoch was succeeded by the grand unification epoch, where gravitation is separated from the unified force of the Standard Model, in turn followed by the inflationary epoch, which ended after about 10−32 seconds (or about 1010tP).
Properties of the observable universe today expressed in Planck units:
After the measurement of the cosmological constant (Λ) in 1998, estimated at 10−122 in Planck units, it was noted that this is suggestively close to the reciprocal of the age of the universe (T) squared. Barrow and Shaw proposed a modified theory in which Λ is a field evolving in such a way that its value remains Λ ~ T−2 throughout the history of the universe.
The Planck length, denoted ℓP, is a unit of length defined as:
It is equal to 1.616255(18)×10−35 m, where the two digits enclosed by parentheses are the estimated standard error associated with the reported numerical value, or about 10−20 times the diameter of a proton.
Planck time
The Planck time tP is the time required for light to travel a distance of 1 Planck length in a vacuum, which is a time interval of approximately 5.39×10−44s.
All scientific experiments and human experiences occur over time scales
that are many orders of magnitude longer than the Planck time, making any events happening at the Planck scale undetectable with current scientific technology. As of October 2020, the smallest time interval uncertainty in direct measurements was on the order of 247 zeptoseconds (2.47×10−19 s).
While there is currently no known way to measure time intervals
on the scale of the Planck time, researchers in 2020 proposed a
theoretical apparatus and experiment that, if ever realized, could be
capable of being influenced by effects of time as short as 10−33 seconds, thus establishing an upper detectable limit for the quantization of a time that is roughly 20 billion times longer than the Planck time.
Planck energy
Most
Planck units are extremely small, as in the case of Planck length or
Planck time, or extremely large, as in the case of Planck temperature or
Planck acceleration. For comparison, the Planck energy EP
is approximately equal to the energy stored in an automobile gas tank
(57.2 L of gasoline at 34.2 MJ/L of chemical energy). The ultra-high-energy cosmic rayobserved in 1991 had a measured energy of about 50 J, equivalent to about 2.5×10−8EP.
Planck unit of force
The Planck unit of force may be thought of as the derived unit of force in the Planck system if the Planck units of time, length, and mass are considered to be base units.
It is the gravitational attractive force of two bodies of 1 Planck
mass each that are held 1 Planck length apart; equivalently, it is the
electrostatic attractive or repulsive force of two Planck units of
charges that are held 1 Planck length apart.
Various authors have argued that the Planck force is on the order of the maximum force that can be observed in nature. However, the validity of these conjectures has been disputed.
Planck temperature
The Planck temperature TP is 1.416784(16)×1032 K. There are no known physical models able to describe temperatures greater than TP; a quantum theory of gravity would be required to model the extreme energies attained.
List of physical equations
Physical
quantities that have different dimensions (such as time and length)
cannot be equated even if they are numerically equal (1 second is not
the same as 1 metre). In theoretical physics, however, this scruple can
be set aside, by a process called nondimensionalization.
Table 3 shows how the use of Planck units simplifies many fundamental
equations of physics, because this gives each of the five fundamental
constants, and products of them, a simple numeric value of 1. In
the SI form, the units should be accounted for. In the
nondimensionalized form, the units, which are now Planck units, need not
be written if their use is understood.
Table 3: How Planck units simplify the key equations of physics
Alternative choices of normalization
As
already stated above, Planck units are derived by "normalizing" the
numerical values of certain fundamental constants to 1. These
normalizations are neither the only ones possible nor necessarily the
best. Moreover, the choice of what factors to normalize, among the
factors appearing in the fundamental equations of physics, is not
evident, and the values of the Planck units are sensitive to this
choice.
The factor 4π is ubiquitous in theoretical physics because the surface area of a sphere of radius r is 4πr2 in contexts having spherical symmetry in three dimensions. This, along with the concept of flux, are the basis for the inverse-square law, Gauss's law, and the divergence operator applied to flux density. For example, gravitational and electrostatic fields produced by point charges have spherical symmetry (Barrow 2002: 214–15). The 4πr2 appearing in the denominator of Coulomb's law in rationalized form,
for example, follows from the flux of an electrostatic field being
distributed uniformly on the surface of a sphere. Likewise for Newton's
law of universal gravitation. (If space had more than three spatial
dimensions, the factor 4π would be changed according to the geometry of the sphere in higher dimensions.)
Hence a substantial body of physical theory developed since Planck (1899) suggests normalizing not G but 4πG (or 8πG) to 1. Doing so would introduce a factor of 1/4π (or 1/8π)
into the nondimensionalized form of the law of universal gravitation,
consistent with the modern rationalized formulation of Coulomb's law in
terms of the vacuum permittivity. In fact, alternative normalizations
frequently preserve the factor of 1/4π
in the nondimensionalized form of Coulomb's law as well, so that the
nondimensionalized Maxwell's equations for electromagnetism and gravitoelectromagnetism both take the same form as those for electromagnetism in SI, which do not have any factors of 4π. When this is applied to electromagnetic constants, ε0, this unit system is called "rationalized". When applied additionally to gravitation and Planck units, these are called rationalized Planck units and are seen in high-energy physics.
The rationalized Planck units are defined so that .
There are several possible alternative normalizations.
Gravitational constant
In
1899, Newton's law of universal gravitation was still seen as exact,
rather than as a convenient approximation holding for "small" velocities
and masses (the approximate nature of Newton's law was shown following
the development of general relativity in 1915). Hence Planck normalized to 1 the gravitational constantG in Newton's law. In theories emerging after 1899, G nearly always appears in formulae multiplied by 4π
or a small integer multiple thereof. Hence, a choice to be made when
designing a system of natural units is which, if any, instances of 4π appearing in the equations of physics are to be eliminated via the normalization.
Normalizing 4πG to 1 (and therefore setting G = 1/4π):
Eliminates 4πG from the Bekenstein–Hawking formula (for the entropy of a black hole in terms of its mass mBH and the area of its event horizonABH) which is simplified to SBH = πABH = (mBH)2.
Setting 8πG = 1 (and therefore setting G = 1/8π). This would eliminate 8πG from the Einstein field equations, Einstein–Hilbert action, and the Friedmann equations, for gravitation. Planck units modified so that 8πG = 1 are known as reduced Planck units, because the Planck mass is divided by √8π. Also, the Bekenstein–Hawking formula for the entropy of a black hole simplifies to SBH = (mBH)2/2 = 2πABH.