From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
Pseudoscience is a claim, belief or practice which is falsely presented as
scientific, but does not adhere to a
valid scientific method, lacks supporting
scientific evidence or plausibility, cannot be
reliably tested, or otherwise lacks scientific status.
[1] Pseudoscience is often characterized by the use of vague, contradictory, exaggerated or
unprovable claims, an over-reliance on
confirmation rather than
rigorous attempts at refutation,
a lack of openness to evaluation by other experts, and a general
absence of systematic processes to rationally develop theories.
A field, practice, or body of knowledge can reasonably be called pseudoscientific when it is presented as consistent with the
norms of scientific research, but it demonstrably fails to meet these norms.
[2] Science is also distinguishable from
revelation,
theology, or
spirituality in that it offers insight into the physical world obtained by
empirical research and testing.
[3] Commonly held beliefs in
popular science may not meet the criteria of science.
[4] "Pop science" may blur the divide between science and pseudoscience among the general public, and may also involve
science fiction.
[4]
Pseudoscientific beliefs are widespread, even among public school science teachers and newspaper reporters.
[5]
The
demarcation problem between science and pseudoscience has ethical
political implications, as well as
philosophical and
scientific issues.
[6] Differentiating science from pseudoscience has practical implications in the case of
health care,
expert testimony,
environmental policies, and
science education.
[7] Distinguishing scientific facts and theories from pseudoscientific beliefs such as those found in
astrology,
alchemy,
medical quackery, and
occult beliefs combined with scientific concepts, is part of science education and
scientific literacy.
[8]
The term
pseudoscience is often considered inherently
pejorative, because it suggests something is being inaccurately or even deceptively portrayed as science.
[9] Accordingly, those labeled as practicing or advocating pseudoscience usually dispute the characterization.
[9]
Overview
Scientific methodology
A typical 19th century
phrenology
chart: In the 1820s, phrenologists claimed the mind was located in
areas of the brain, and were attacked for doubting that mind came from
the nonmaterial soul. Their idea of reading "bumps" in the skull to
predict personality traits was later discredited.
[10] Phrenology was first called a pseudoscience in 1843 and continues to be considered so.
[11]
While the standards for determining whether a body of knowledge,
methodology, or practice is scientific can vary from field to field, a
number of basic principles are widely agreed upon by scientists. The
basic notion is that all experimental results should be
reproducible, and able to be
verified by other individuals.
[12] These principles aim to ensure
experiments can be measurably reproduced under the same conditions, allowing further investigation to determine whether a
hypothesis or
theory related to given
phenomena is both
valid and reliable. Standards require the scientific method to be applied throughout, and
bias will be controlled for or eliminated through
randomization, fair sampling procedures,
blinding
of studies, and other methods. All gathered data, including the
experimental or environmental conditions, are expected to be documented
for scrutiny and made available for
peer review, allowing further experiments or studies to be conducted to confirm or falsify results. Statistical quantification of
significance,
confidence, and
error[13] are also important tools for the scientific method.
Falsifiability
In the mid-20th century,
Karl Popper put forth the criterion of
falsifiability to distinguish science from nonscience.
[14]
Falsifiability means a result can be disproved. For example, a
statement such as "God created the universe" may be true or false, but
no tests can be devised that could prove it either way; it simply lies
outside the reach of science. Popper used astrology and
psychoanalysis as examples of pseudoscience and Einstein's
theory of relativity
as an example of science. He subdivided nonscience into philosophical,
mathematical, mythological, religious and metaphysical formulations on
one hand, and pseudoscientific formulations on the other, though he did
not provide clear criteria for the differences.
[15]
Another example which shows the distinct need for a claim to be falsifiable was put forth in
Carl Sagan's The Demon-Haunted World
when he talks about an invisible dragon that he has in his garage. The
point is made that there is no physical test to refute the claim of the
presence of this dragon. No matter what test you think you can come up
with, there is then a reason why this does not apply to the invisible
dragon, so one can never prove that the initial claim is wrong. Sagan
concludes; "Now, what's the difference between an invisible,
incorporeal, floating dragon who spits heatless fire and no dragon at
all?". He states that "your inability to invalidate my hypothesis is not
at all the same thing as proving it true,
[16] once again explaining that even if such a claim were true, it would lie outside the realm of
scientific inquiry.
Merton's norms
In 1942,
Robert K. Merton
identified a small set of "norms" which characterized what makes a
"real" science. If any of the norms were violated, Merton considered the
enterprise to be nonscience. These are not broadly accepted in the
scientific community. His norms were:
- Originality: The tests and research done must present something new to the scientific community.
- Detachment: The scientists' reasons for practicing this science must
be simply for the expansion of their knowledge. The scientists should
not have personal reasons to expect certain results.
- Universality: No person should be able to more easily obtain the
information of a test than another person. Social class, religion,
ethnicity, or any other personal factors should not be factors in
someone's ability to receive or perform a type of science.
- Skepticism: Scientific facts must not be based on faith. One should
always question every case and argument and constantly check for errors
or invalid claims.
- Public accessibility: Any scientific knowledge one obtains should be
made available to everyone. The results of any research should be
openly published and shared with the scientific community.[17]
Refusal to acknowledge problems
In 1978,
Paul Thagard
proposed that pseudoscience is primarily distinguishable from science
when it is less progressive than alternative theories over a long period
of time, and its proponents fail to acknowledge or address problems
with the theory.
[18] In 1983,
Mario Bunge
has suggested the categories of "belief fields" and "research fields"
to help distinguish between pseudoscience and science, where the former
is primarily personal and subjective and the latter involves a certain
systematic approach.
[19]
Criticism of the term
Philosophers of science, such as
Paul Feyerabend, argued that a distinction between science and nonscience is neither possible nor desirable.
[20][21]
Among the issues which can make the distinction difficult is variable
rates of evolution among the theories and methodologies of science in
response to new data.
[22] In addition, specific standards applicable to one field of science may not be applicable in other fields.
[citation needed]
Larry Laudan
has suggested pseudoscience has no scientific meaning and is mostly
used to describe our emotions: "If we would stand up and be counted on
the side of reason, we ought to drop terms like 'pseudo-science' and
'unscientific' from our vocabulary; they are just hollow phrases which
do only emotive work for us".
[23] Likewise,
Richard McNally
states, "The term 'pseudoscience' has become little more than an
inflammatory buzzword for quickly dismissing one's opponents in media
sound-bites" and "When therapeutic entrepreneurs make claims on behalf
of their interventions, we should not waste our time trying to determine
whether their interventions qualify as pseudoscientific. Rather, we
should ask them: How do you know that your intervention works? What is
your evidence?"
[24]
Etymology
The word "pseudoscience" is derived from the Greek root
pseudo meaning false and the English word
science. Although the term has been in use since at least the late 18th century (used in 1796 in reference to
alchemy,
[25][26])
the concept of pseudoscience as distinct from real or proper science
appears to have emerged in the mid-19th century. Among the first
recorded uses of the word "pseudo-science" was in 1844 in the
Northern Journal of Medicine,
I 387: "That opposite kind of innovation which pronounces what has been
recognized as a branch of science, to have been a pseudo-science,
composed merely of so-called facts, connected together by
misapprehensions under the disguise of principles". An earlier recorded
use of the term was in 1843 by the French physiologist
François Magendie.
[11]
During the 20th century, the word was used as a pejorative to describe
explanations of phenomena which were claimed to be scientific, but which
were not in fact supported by reliable experimental evidence. From time
to time, though, the usage of the word occurred in a more formal,
technical manner around a perceived threat to individual and
institutional security in a social and cultural setting.
[27]
History
The history of pseudoscience is the study of pseudoscientific
theories over time. A pseudoscience is a set of ideas that presents
itself as science, while it does not meet the criteria to properly be
called such.
[28][29]
Distinguishing between proper science and pseudoscience is sometimes
difficult. One proposal for demarcation between the two is the
falsification criterion, most notably attributed to the philosopher
Karl Popper. In the
history of science and "
history of pseudoscience"
it can be especially hard to separate the two, because some sciences
developed from pseudosciences. An example of this is the science
chemistry, which traces its origins to pseudoscientific
alchemy.
The vast diversity in pseudosciences further complicates the history
of science. Some modern pseudosciences, such as astrology and
acupuncture, originated before the scientific era. Others developed as part of an ideology, such as
Lysenkoism, or as a response to perceived threats to an ideology. Examples are
creation science and
intelligent design, which were developed in response to the scientific
theory of evolution.
Despite failing to meet proper scientific standards, many pseudosciences survive. This is usually due to a persistent core of
devotees
who refuse to accept scientific criticism of their beliefs, or due to
popular misconceptions. Sheer popularity is also a factor, as is
attested by astrology, which remains popular despite being rejected by a
large majority of scientists.
[30][31][32][33]
Identifying pseudoscience
A field, practice, or body of knowledge might reasonably be called
pseudoscientific when it is presented as consistent with the norms of
scientific research, but it demonstrably fails to meet these norms.
[2]
Karl Popper stated it is insufficient to distinguish science from pseudoscience, or from
metaphysics,
by the criterion of rigorous adherence to the empirical method, which
is essentially inductive, based on observation or experimentation.
[34]
He proposed a method to distinguish between genuine empirical,
nonempirical or even pseudoempirical methods. The latter case was
exemplified by astrology, which appeals to observation and
experimentation. While it had astonishing
empirical evidence based on observation, on
horoscopes and
biographies, it crucially failed to adhere to acceptable scientific standards.
[34] Popper proposed falsifiability as an important criterion in distinguishing science from pseudoscience.
To demonstrate this point, Popper
[34]
gave two cases of human behavior and typical explanations from Freud
and Adler's theories: "that of a man who pushes a child into the water
with the intention of drowning it; and that of a man who sacrifices his
life in an attempt to save the child."
[34] From Freud's perspective, the first man would have suffered from
psychological repression, probably originating from an
Oedipus complex, whereas the second had attained
sublimation. From Adler's perspective, the first and second man suffered from feelings of
inferiority
and had to prove himself which drove him to commit the crime or, in the
second case, rescue the child. Popper was not able to find any
counterexamples of human behavior in which the behavior could not be
explained in the terms of Adler's or Freud's theory. Popper argued
[34]
it was that the observation always fitted or confirmed the theory
which, rather than being its strength, was actually its weakness.
In contrast, Popper
[34] gave the example of Einstein's
gravitational theory, which predicted "light must be attracted by heavy bodies (such as the sun), precisely as material bodies were attracted."
[34]
Following from this, stars closer to the sun would appear to have moved
a small distance away from the sun, and away from each other. This
prediction was particularly striking to Popper because it involved
considerable risk. The brightness of the sun prevented this effect from
being observed under normal circumstances, so photographs had to be
taken during an eclipse and compared to photographs taken at night.
Popper states, "If observation shows that the predicted effect is
definitely absent, then the theory is simply refuted."
[34] Popper summed up his criterion for the scientific status of a theory as depending on its falsifiability, refutability, or
testability.
Paul R. Thagard
used astrology as a case study to distinguish science from
pseudoscience and proposed principles and criteria to delineate them.
[35] First, astrology has not progressed in that it has not been updated nor added any explanatory power since
Ptolemy. Second, it has ignored outstanding problems such as the
precession of equinoxes in astronomy. Third, alternative theories of
personality
and behavior have grown progressively to encompass explanations of
phenomena which astrology statically attributes to heavenly forces.
Fourth, astrologers have remained uninterested in furthering the theory
to deal with outstanding problems or in critically evaluating the theory
in relation to other theories. Thagard intended this criterion to be
extended to areas other than astrology. He believed it would delineate
as pseudoscientific such practices as
witchcraft and
pyramidology, while leaving
physics, chemistry and
biology in the realm of science.
Biorhythms,
which like astrology relied uncritically on birth dates, did not meet
the criterion of pseudoscience at the time because there were no
alternative explanations for the same observations. The use of this
criterion has the consequence that a theory can at one time be
scientific and at another pseudoscientific.
[35]
Science is also distinguishable from revelation, theology, or
spirituality in that it offers insight into the physical world obtained
by empirical research and testing.
[3]
For this reason, the teaching of creation science and intelligent
design has been strongly condemned in position statements from
scientific organisations.
[36] The most notable disputes concern the
evolution
of living organisms, the idea of common descent, the geologic history
of the Earth, the formation of the solar system, and the origin of the
universe.
[37] Systems of belief that derive from divine or inspired
knowledge
are not considered pseudoscience if they do not claim either to be
scientific or to overturn well-established science. Moreover, some
specific religious claims, such as
the power of intercessory prayer to heal the sick, although they may be based on untestable beliefs, can be tested by the scientific method.
Some statements and commonly held beliefs in popular science may not
meet the criteria of science. "Pop" science may blur the divide between
science and pseudoscience among the general public, and may also involve
science fiction.
[4]
Indeed, pop science is disseminated to, and can also easily emanate
from, persons not accountable to scientific methodology and expert peer
review.
If the claims of a given field can be experimentally tested and
methodological standards are upheld, it is not "pseudoscience", however
odd, astonishing, or counterintuitive. If claims made are inconsistent
with existing experimental results or established theory, but the
methodology is sound, caution should be used; science consists of
testing hypotheses which may turn out to be false. In such a case, the
work may be better described as ideas that are "not yet generally
accepted".
Protoscience
is a term sometimes used to describe a hypothesis that has not yet been
adequately tested by the scientific method, but which is otherwise
consistent with existing science or which, where inconsistent, offers
reasonable account of the inconsistency. It may also describe the
transition from a body of practical knowledge into a scientific field.
[38]
Pseudoscientific concepts
Examples of pseudoscience concepts, proposed as scientific when they are not scientific, include
acupuncture,
alchemy,
ancient astronauts,
applied kinesiology,
astrology,
Ayurvedic medicine,
biorhythms,
cellular memory,
cold fusion,
[39] craniometry,
creation science, Scientology founder
L. Ron Hubbard's
engram theory,
enneagrams,
eugenics,
[40] extrasensory perception (ESP),
facilitated communication,
graphology,
homeopathy,
intelligent design,
iridology,
kundalini,
Lysenkoism,
metoposcopy,
N-rays,
naturopathy,
orgone energy,
paranormal plant perception,
phrenology,
physiognomy,
qi, New Age psychotherapies (e.g.,
rebirthing therapy),
reflexology,
remote viewing,
neuro-linguistic programming (NLP),
reiki,
Rolfing,
therapeutic touch, and the revised history of the solar system proposed by
Immanuel Velikovsky.
Robert T. Carroll
stated, in part, "Pseudoscientists claim to base their theories on
empirical evidence, and they may even use some scientific methods,
though often their understanding of a controlled experiment is
inadequate. Many pseudoscientists relish being able to point out the
consistency of their ideas with known facts or with predicted
consequences, but they do not recognize that such consistency is not
proof of anything. It is a necessary condition but not a sufficient
condition that a good scientific theory be consistent with the facts."
[41]
In 2006, the
U.S. National Science Foundation
(NSF) issued an executive summary of a paper on science and engineering
which briefly discussed the prevalence of pseudoscience in modern
times. It said, "belief in pseudoscience is widespread" and, referencing
a
Gallup Poll,
[42] stated that belief in the 10 commonly believed examples of
paranormal phenomena listed in the poll were "pseudoscientific beliefs".
[43] The items were "extrasensory perception (ESP), that
houses can be haunted,
ghosts,
telepathy,
clairvoyance, astrology, that people can
communicate mentally with someone who has died, witches,
reincarnation, and
channelling".
[43] Such beliefs in pseudoscience reflect a lack of knowledge of how science works. The
scientific community may aim to communicate information about science out of concern for the public's susceptibility to unproven claims.
[43]
The following are some of the indicators of the possible presence of pseudoscience.
Use of vague, exaggerated or untestable claims
- Assertion of scientific claims that are vague rather than precise, and that lack specific measurements[44]
- Failure to make use of operational definitions
(i.e. publicly accessible definitions of the variables, terms, or
objects of interest so that persons other than the definer can
independently measure or test them)[45] (See also: Reproducibility)
- Failure to make reasonable use of the principle of parsimony,
i.e. failing to seek an explanation that requires the fewest possible
additional assumptions when multiple viable explanations are possible (see: Occam's razor)[46]
- Use of obscurantist language, and use of apparently technical jargon in an effort to give claims the superficial trappings of science
- Lack of boundary conditions: Most well-supported scientific theories
possess well-articulated limitations under which the predicted
phenomena do and do not apply.[47]
- Lack of effective controls, such as placebo and double-blind, in experimental design
- Lack of understanding of basic and established principles of physics and engineering[48]
Over-reliance on confirmation rather than refutation
- Assertions that do not allow the logical possibility that they can be shown to be false by observation or physical experiment (see also: Falsifiability)[49]
- Assertion of claims that a theory predicts something that it has not been shown to predict.[50]
Scientific claims that do not confer any predictive power are
considered at best "conjectures", or at worst "pseudoscience" (e.g. Ignoratio elenchi)[51]
- Assertion that claims which have not been proven false must be true, and vice versa (see: Argument from ignorance)[52]
- Over-reliance on testimonial, anecdotal evidence, or personal experience:
This evidence may be useful for the context of discovery (i.e.
hypothesis generation), but should not be used in the context of justification (e.g. Statistical hypothesis testing).[53]
- Presentation of data that seems to support claims while suppressing
or refusing to consider data that conflict with those claims.[54] This is an example of selection bias,
a distortion of evidence or data that arises from the way that the data
are collected. It is sometimes referred to as the selection effect.
- Promulgating to the status of facts excessive or untested claims
that have been previously published elsewhere; an accumulation of such
uncritical secondary reports, which do not otherwise contribute their
own empirical investigation, is called the Woozle effect.[55]
- Reversed burden of proof:
science places the burden of proof on those making a claim, not on the
critic. "Pseudoscientific" arguments may neglect this principle and
demand that skeptics
demonstrate beyond a reasonable doubt that a claim (e.g. an assertion
regarding the efficacy of a novel therapeutic technique) is false. It is
essentially impossible to prove a universal negative, so this tactic
incorrectly places the burden of proof on the skeptic rather than on the
claimant.[56]
- Appeals to holism as opposed to reductionism: proponents of pseudoscientific claims, especially in organic medicine, alternative medicine, naturopathy and mental health, often resort to the "mantra of holism" to dismiss negative findings.[57]
Lack of openness to testing by other experts
- Evasion of peer review before publicizing results (called "science by press conference"):[58]
Some proponents of ideas that contradict accepted scientific theories
avoid subjecting their ideas to peer review, sometimes on the grounds
that peer review is biased towards established paradigms, and sometimes
on the grounds that assertions cannot be evaluated adequately using
standard scientific methods. By remaining insulated from the peer review
process, these proponents forgo the opportunity of corrective feedback
from informed colleagues.[59]
- Some agencies, institutions, and publications that fund scientific research require authors to share data
so others can evaluate a paper independently. Failure to provide
adequate information for other researchers to reproduce the claims
contributes to a lack of openness.[60]
- Appealing to the need for secrecy or proprietary knowledge when an independent review of data or methodology is requested[60]
- Substantive debate on the evidence by knowledgeable proponents of all view points is not encouraged.[61]
Absence of progress
- Failure to progress towards additional evidence of its claims.[62] Terence Hines has identified astrology as a subject that has changed very little in the past two millennia.[63] (see also: scientific progress)
- Lack of self-correction: scientific research programmes make mistakes, but they tend to eliminate these errors over time.[64]
By contrast, ideas may be regarded as pseudoscientific because they
have remained unaltered despite contradictory evidence. The work Scientists Confront Velikovsky (1976) Cornell University, also delves into these features in some detail, as does the work of Thomas Kuhn, e.g. The Structure of Scientific Revolutions (1962) which also discusses some of the items on the list of characteristics of pseudoscience.
- Statistical significance of supporting experimental results does not
improve over time and are usually close to the cutoff for statistical
significance. Normally, experimental techniques improve or the
experiments are repeated, and this gives ever stronger evidence. If
statistical significance does not improve, this typically shows the
experiments have just been repeated until a success occurs due to chance
variations.
Personalization of issues
- Tight social groups and authoritarian personality, suppression of dissent, and groupthink
can enhance the adoption of beliefs that have no rational basis. In
attempting to confirm their beliefs, the group tends to identify their
critics as enemies.[65]
- Assertion of claims of a conspiracy on the part of the scientific community to suppress the results[66]
- Attacking the motives or character of anyone who questions the claims (see Ad hominem fallacy)[67]
Use of misleading language
- Creating scientific-sounding terms to add weight to claims and
persuade nonexperts to believe statements that may be false or
meaningless: For example, a long-standing hoax refers to water by the
rarely used formal name "dihydrogen monoxide" and describes it as the main constituent in most poisonous solutions to show how easily the general public can be misled.
- Using established terms in idiosyncratic ways, thereby demonstrating unfamiliarity with mainstream work in the discipline
Demographics
In his book
The Demon-Haunted World Carl Sagan discusses the
government of China and the
Chinese Communist Party
concern about Western pseudoscience developments and certain ancient
Chinese practices in China. He sees pseudoscience occurring in the U.S.
as part of a worldwide trend and suggests its causes, dangers, diagnosis
and treatment may be universal.
[68]
In Spain, another science writer Luis Alfonso Gámez was sued after he
notified the public about the lack of efficacy to support the claims of a
popular pseudoscientist. In the US, 54% of the population believe in
psychic healing and 35% believe in telepathy. In Europe, the statistics
are not that much different. A significant percentage of Europeans
consider homeopathy (34%) and horoscopes (13%) to be reliable science.
[69] Over the past decade, consumer interest in the use of
complementary and alternative medicine (CAM) practices and products has increased. Surveys demonstrate that the people with the most serious
medical conditions, such as cancer, chronic pain, and HIV, are the most routine consumers of CAM.
[69]
The
National Science Foundation
stated that pseudoscientific beliefs in the U.S. became more widespread
during the 1990s, peaked near 2001, and declined slightly since with
pseudoscientific beliefs remaining common. According to the NSF report,
there is a lack of knowledge of pseudoscientific issues in society and
pseudoscientific practices are commonly followed.
[70] Surveys indicate about a third of all adult Americans consider astrology to be scientific.
[71][72][73]
A large percentage of the United States population lacks scientific
literacy, not adequately understanding scientific principles and
methodology.
[43][74][75][76]
In the Journal of College Science Teaching, Art Hobson writes,
"Pseudoscientific beliefs are surprisingly widespread in our culture
even among public school science teachers and newspaper editors, and are
closely related to scientific illiteracy."
[5]
However, a 10,000 student study in the same journal concluded there was
no strong correlation between science knowledge and belief in
pseudoscience.
[77]
Explanations
In a report Singer and Benassi (1981) wrote that pseudoscientific beliefs have their origin from at least four sources.
[78]
- Common cognitive errors from personal experience
- Erroneous sensationalistic mass media coverage
- Sociocultural factors
- Poor or erroneous science education
Another American study (Eve and Dunn, 1990) supported the findings of
Singer and Benassi and found sufficient levels of pseudoscientific
belief being promoted by high school life science and biology teachers.
[79]
Psychology
The psychology of pseudoscience aims to explore and analyze
pseudoscientific thinking by means of thorough clarification on making
the distinction of what is considered scientific vs. pseudoscientific.
The human proclivity for seeking confirmation rather than refutation
(confirmation bias),
[80]
the tendency to hold comforting beliefs, and the tendency to
overgeneralize have been proposed as reasons for the common adherence to
pseudoscientific thinking. According to Beyerstein (1991), humans are
prone to associations based on resemblances only, and often prone to
misattribution in cause-effect thinking.
[81]
Michael Shermer's theory of belief-dependent realism is driven by the
belief that the brain is essentially a "belief engine," which scans
data perceived by the senses and looks for patterns and meaning. There
is also the tendency for the brain to create
cognitive biases,
as a result of inferences and assumptions made without logic and based
on instinct — usually resulting in patterns in cognition. These
tendencies of
patternicity
and agenticity are also driven "by a meta-bias called the bias blind
spot, or the tendency to recognize the power of cognitive biases in
other people but to be blind to their influence on our own beliefs."
[82]
Lindeman states that social motives (i.e., "to comprehend self and the
world, to have a sense of control over outcomes, to belong, to find the
world benevolent and to maintain one's self-esteem") are often "more
easily" fulfilled by pseudoscience than by scientific information.
Furthermore, pseudoscientific explanations are generally not analyzed
rationally, but instead experientially. Operating within a different set
of rules compared to rational thinking, experiential thinking regards
an explanation as valid if the explanation is "personally functional,
satisfying and sufficient", offering a description of the world that may
be more personal than can be provided by science and reducing the
amount of potential work involved in understanding complex events and
outcomes.
[83]
Some people believe the prevalence of pseudoscientific beliefs is due to widespread "
scientific illiteracy".
[84]
The individuals lacking scientific literacy are more susceptible to
wishful thinking, since they are likely to turn to immediate
gratification powered by System 1, our default operating system which
requires little to no effort. This system encourages one to accept the
conclusions they believe, and reject the ones they don't. Further
analysis of complex pseudoscientific phenomena require System 2, which
follows rules, compares objects along multiple dimensions, and weighs
options. These two systems have several other differences which are
further discussed in the
dual-process theory.
[citation needed]
The scientific and secular systems of morality and meaning are
generally unsatisfying to most people. Humans are, by nature, a
forward-minded species pursuing greater avenues of happiness and
satisfaction, but we are all too frequently willing to grasp at
unrealistic promises of a better life.
[85]
Psychology has much to discuss about pseudoscience thinking, as it is
the illusory perceptions of causality and effectiveness of numerous
individuals that needs to be illuminated. Research suggests that
illusionary thinking happens in most people when exposed to certain
circumstances such as reading a book, an advertisement or the testimony
of others are the basis of pseudoscience beliefs. It is assumed that
illusions are not unusual, and given the right conditions, illusions are
able to occur systematically even in normal emotional situations. One
of the things pseudoscience believers quibble most about is that
academic science usually treats them as fools. Minimizing these
illusions in the real world is not simple.
[69]
To this aim, designing evidence-based educational programs can be
effective to help people identify and reduce their own illusions.
[69]
Boundaries between science and pseudoscience
In the
philosophy and history of science,
Imre Lakatos
stresses the social and political importance of the demarcation
problem, the normative methodological problem of distinguishing between
science and pseudoscience. His distinctive historical analysis of
scientific methodology based on research programmes suggests:
"scientists regard the successful theoretical prediction of stunning
novel facts – such as the
return of Halley's comet or the
gravitational bending of light rays –
as what demarcates good scientific theories from pseudo-scientific and
degenerate theories, and in spite of all scientific theories being
forever confronted by 'an ocean of counterexamples'".
[6] Lakatos offers a "novel
fallibilist
analysis of the development of Newton's celestial dynamics, [his]
favourite historical example of his methodology" and argues in light of
this historical turn, that his account answers for certain inadequacies
in those of
Sir Karl Popper and Thomas Kuhn.
[6]
"Nonetheless, Lakatos did recognize the force of Kuhn's historical
criticism of Popper – all important theories have been surrounded by an
'ocean of anomalies', which on a falsificationist view would require the
rejection of the theory outright... Lakatos sought to reconcile the
rationalism of Popperian
falsificationism with what seemed to be its own refutation by history".
[86]
Many philosophers have tried to solve the problem of demarcation in
the following terms: a statement constitutes knowledge if sufficiently
many people believe it sufficiently strongly. But the history of thought
shows us that many people were totally committed to absurd beliefs. If
the strengths of beliefs were a hallmark of knowledge, we should have to
rank some tales about demons, angels, devils, and of heaven and hell as
knowledge. Scientists, on the other hand, are very sceptical even of
their best theories. Newton's is the most powerful theory science has
yet produced, but Newton himself never believed that bodies attract each
other at a distance. So no degree of commitment to beliefs makes them
knowledge. Indeed, the hallmark of scientific behaviour is a certain
scepticism even towards one's most cherished theories. Blind commitment
to a theory is not an intellectual virtue: it is an intellectual crime.
Thus a statement may be pseudoscientific even if it is eminently
'plausible' and everybody believes in it, and it may be scientifically
valuable even if it is unbelievable and nobody believes in it. A theory
may even be of supreme scientific value even if no one understands it,
let alone believes in it.[6]
—Imre Lakatos, Science and Pseudoscience
The boundary lines between science and pseudoscience are disputed and
difficult to determine analytically, even after more than a century of
dialogue among philosophers of science and
scientists in varied fields, and despite some basic agreements on the fundaments of scientific methodology.
[2][87]
The concept of pseudoscience rests on an understanding that scientific
methodology has been misrepresented or misapplied with respect to a
given theory, but many philosophers of science maintain that different
kinds of methods are held as appropriate across different fields and
different eras of human history. According to Lakatos, the typical
descriptive unit of great scientific achievements is not an isolated
hypothesis but "a powerful problem-solving machinery, which, with the
help of sophisticated mathematical techniques, digests anomalies and
even turns them into positive evidence."
[6]
To Popper, pseudoscience uses induction to generate theories, and
only performs experiments to seek to verify them. To Popper,
falsifiability is what determines the scientific status of a theory.
Taking a historical approach, Kuhn observed that scientists did not
follow Popper's rule, and might ignore falsifying data, unless
overwhelming. To Kuhn, puzzle-solving within a paradigm is science.
Lakatos attempted to resolve this debate, by suggesting history shows
that science occurs in research programmes, competing according to how
progressive they are. The leading idea of a programme could evolve,
driven by its heuristic to make predictions that can be supported by
evidence. Feyerabend claimed that Lakatos was selective in his examples,
and the whole history of science shows there is no universal rule of
scientific method, and imposing one on the scientific community impedes
progress.[88]
—David Newbold and Julia Roberts, "An analysis of the demarcation problem in science and its application to therapeutic touch theory" in International Journal of Nursing Practice, Vol. 13
Laudan maintained that the demarcation between science and
non-science was a pseudo-problem, preferring to focus on the more
general distinction between reliable and unreliable knowledge.
[89]
[Feyerabend] regards Lakatos's view as being closet anarchism
disguised as methodological rationalism. It should be noted that
Feyerabend's claim was not that standard methodological rules should
never be obeyed, but rather that sometimes progress is made by
abandoning them. In the absence of a generally accepted rule, there is a
need for alternative methods of persuasion. According to Feyerabend,
Galileo employed stylistic and rhetorical techniques to convince his
reader, while he also wrote in Italian rather than Latin and directed
his arguments to those already temperamentally inclined to accept them.[86]
—Alexander Bird, "The Historical Turn in the Philosophy of Science" in Routledge Companion to the Philosophy of Science
Politics, health, and education
Political implications
The demarcation problem between science and pseudoscience brings up debate in the realms of science,
philosophy and
politics. Imre Lakatos, for instance, points out that the
Communist Party of the Soviet Union at one point declared that
Mendelian genetics was pseudoscientific and had its advocates, including well-established scientists such as
Nikolai Vavilov, sent to a
Gulag
and that the "liberal Establishment of the West" denies freedom of
speech to topics it regards as pseudoscience, particularly where they
run up against social mores.
[6]
Pseudoscience is used recurrently in political, policy-making
discourse in allegations of distortion or fabrication of scientific
findings to support a political position. The
Prince of Wales has accused
climate change skeptics of using pseudoscience and persuasion to hinder the world from adopting
precautionary principles to avert the negative
effects of global warming.
People have given attention to the climate skeptics and have tried to
understand the kind of pseudoscience they are canvassing. But the
evidence is already here, which Prince Charles describes as an
"environmental collapse", not only in climbing temperatures but the
imprint on particular species like
honey bees.
[90]
It becomes pseudoscientific when science cannot be separated from
ideology,
scientists misrepresent scientific findings to promote or draw
attention for publicity, when politicians, journalists and a nation's
intellectual elite distort the facts of science for short-term political
gain, when powerful individuals in the public conflate causation and
cofactors (for example, in the causes of HIV/AIDS) through a mixture of
clever wordplay, or when science is being used by the powerful to
promote ignorance rather than tackle ignorance. These ideas reduce the
authority, value, integrity and independence of science in
society.
[91]
Health and education implications
Distinguishing science from pseudoscience has practical implications
in the case of health care, expert testimony, environmental policies,
and science education. Treatments with a patina of scientific authority
which have not actually been subjected to actual scientific testing may
be ineffective, expensive, and dangerous to patients, and confuse health
providers, insurers, government decision makers, and the public as to
what treatments are appropriate. Claims advanced by pseudoscience may
result in government officials and educators making poor decisions in
selecting curricula; for example, creation science may replace evolution
in studies of biology.
[7]
The extent to which students acquire a range of social and
cognitive
thinking skills related to the proper usage of science and technology
determines whether they are scientifically literate. Education in the
sciences encounters new dimensions with the changing landscape of
science and technology,
a fast-changing culture, and a knowledge-driven era. A reinvention of
the school science curriculum is one that shapes students to contend
with its changing influence on human welfare. Scientific literacy, which
allows a person to distinguish science from pseudosciences such as
astrology, is among the attributes that enable students to adapt to the
changing world. Its characteristics are embedded in a curriculum where
students are engaged in resolving problems, conductung investigations,
or developing projects.
[8]
Scientists do not want to get involved to counter pseudoscience for
various reasons. For example, pseudoscientific beliefs are irrational
and impossible to combat with rational arguments, and even agreeing to
talk about pseudoscience indicates acceptance as a credible discipline.
Pseudoscience harbors a continuous and an increasing threat to our
society.
[92]
It is impossible to determine the irreversible harm that will happen in
the long term. In a time when the public science literacy has declined
and the danger of pseudoscience has increased, revising the conventional
science course to address current science through the prism of
pseudoscience could help improve science literacy and help society to
eliminate misconceptions and assault growing trends (remote viewing,
psychic readings, etc.) that may harm (financially or otherwise)
trusting citizens.
[92]
Pseudosciences such as homeopathy, even if generally benign, are
magnets for charlatans. This poses a serious issue because incompetent
practitioners should not be given the right of administering health
care. True-believing zealots may pose a more serious threat than typical
con men because of their affection to homeopathy's ideology. Irrational
health care is not harmless, and it is careless to create patient
confidence in pseudomedicine.
[93]