The word omniscience derives from the Latin word sciens ("to know" or "conscious") and the prefix omni ("all" or "every"), but also means "all-seeing".
In religion
Buddhism
The topic of omniscience has been much debated in various Indian traditions, but no more so than by the Buddhists. After Dharmakirti's excursions into the subject of what constitutes a valid cognition, Śāntarakṣita and his student Kamalaśīla thoroughly investigated the subject in the Tattvasamgraha and its commentary the Panjika. The arguments in the text can be broadly grouped into four sections:
The refutation that cognitions, either perceived, inferred, or otherwise, can be used to refute omniscience.
A demonstration of the possibility of omniscience through
apprehending the selfless universal nature of all knowables, by
examining what it means to be ignorant and the nature of mind and
awareness.
A demonstration of the total omniscience where all individual
characteristics (svalaksana) are available to the omniscient being.
The specific demonstration of Shakyamuni Buddha's non-exclusive omniscience, but the knowledge of Shakyamuni Buddha's is really infinite and no other gods or being can match his true omniscience.
Some modern Christian theologians
argue that God's omniscience is inherent rather than total, and that
God chooses to limit his omniscience in order to preserve the free will
and dignity of his creatures. John Calvin,
among other theologians of the 16th century, comfortable with the
definition of God as being omniscient in the total sense, in order for
worthy beings' abilities to choose freely, embraced the doctrine of predestination.
Hinduism
In the Bhakti tradition of Vaishnavism, where Vishnu
is worshipped as the supreme God, Vishnu is attributed with numerous
qualities such as omniscience, energy, strength, lordship, vigour, and
splendour.
Islam
God in Islam is attributed with absolute omniscience. God knows the past, the present, and the future. It is compulsory for a Muslim to believe that God is indeed omniscient as stated in one of the six articles of faith which is:
To believe that God's divine decree and predestination
Say: Do you instruct God about your
religion? But God knows all that is in the heavens and on the earth;
God is Knowing of all things
It is believed that humans can only change their predestination (wealth, health, deed etc.) and not divine decree (date of birth, date of death, family etc.), thus allowing free will.
Baha'i Faith
Omniscience is an attribute of God, yet it is also an attribute that reveals sciences to humanity:
In
like manner, the moment the word expressing My attribute “The
Omniscient” issueth forth from My mouth, every created thing will,
according to its capacity and limitations, be invested with the power to
unfold the knowledge of the most marvelous sciences, and will be
empowered to manifest them in the course of time at the bidding of Him
Who is the Almighty, the All-Knowing.
In Jainism,
omniscience is considered the highest type of perception. In the words
of a Jain scholar, "The perfect manifestation of the innate nature of
the self, arising on the complete annihilation of the obstructive veils,
is called omniscience."
Jainism views infinite knowledge as an inherent capability of every soul. Arihanta
is the word used by Jains to refer to those human beings who have
conquered all inner passions (like attachment, greed, pride, anger) and
possess Kevala Jnana (infinite knowledge). They are said to be of two kinds:
Sāmānya kevali – omniscient beings (Kevalins) who are concerned with their own liberation.
Tirthankara kevali – human beings who attain omniscience and then help others to achieve the same.
Whether omniscience, particularly regarding the choices that a human will make, is compatible with free will has been debated by theologians and philosophers. The argument that divine foreknowledge is not compatible with free will is known as theological fatalism. It is argued that if humans are free to choose between alternatives, God could not know what this choice will be.
A question arises: if an omniscient entity knows everything, even
about its own decisions in the future, does it therefore forbid any
free will to that entity? William Lane Craig states that the question subdivides into two:
If God foreknows the occurrence of some event E, does E happen necessarily?
If some event E is contingent, how can God foreknow E's occurrence?
However, this kind of argument fails to recognize its use of the modal fallacy. It is possible to show that the first premise of arguments like these is fallacious.
Omniscience and the privacy of conscious experience
Some philosophers, such as Patrick Grim, Linda Zagzebski,
Stephan Torre, and William Mander have discussed the issue of whether
the apparent exclusively first-person nature of conscious experience is
compatible with God's omniscience. There is a strong sense in which
conscious experience is private, meaning that no outside observer can
gain knowledge of what it is like to be me as me. If a subject
cannot know what it is like to be another subject in an objective
manner, the question is whether that limitation applies to God as well.
If it does, then God cannot be said to be omniscient since there is then
a form of knowledge that God lacks access to.
The philosopher Patrick Grim most notably raised this issue. Linda Zagzebski argued against this by introducing the notion of perfect empathy,
a proposed relation that God can have to subjects that would allow God
to have perfect knowledge of their conscious experience. William Mander argued that God can only have such knowledge if our experiences are part of God's broader experience. Stephan Torre
claimed that God can have such knowledge if self-knowledge involves the
ascription of properties, either to oneself or to others.
Free will in theology is an important part of the debate on free will
in general. Religions vary greatly in their response to the standard
argument against free will and thus might appeal to any number of
responses to the paradox of free will, the claim that omniscience and free will are incompatible.
The theological doctrine of divine foreknowledge is often alleged to be in conflict with free will, particularly in Calvinistic circles: if God
knows exactly what will happen (right down to every choice a person
makes), it would seem that the "freedom" of these choices is called into
question.
This problem relates to Aristotle's analysis of the problem of the sea battle: tomorrow either there will or will not be a sea battle. According to the Law of Excluded Middle,
there seem to be two options. If there will be a sea battle, then it
seems that it was true even yesterday that there would be one. Thus it
is necessary that the sea battle will occur. If there will not be one, then, by similar reasoning, it is necessary that it will not occur. That means that the future, whatever it is, is completely fixed by past truths: true propositions about the future (a deterministic conclusion is reached: things could not have been any other way).
However, some philosophers follow William of Ockham (c.
1287 – 1347) in holding that necessity and possibility are defined with
respect to a given point in time and a given matrix of empirical
circumstances, and so something that is merely possible from the
perspective of one observer may be necessary from the perspective of an
omniscient. Some philosophers follow Philo in holding that free will is a feature of a human's soul, and thus that non-human animals lack free will.
Common defenses
Jewish philosophy stresses that free will is a product of the intrinsic human soul, using the word neshama (from the Hebrew rootn.sh.m. or .נ.ש.מ meaning "breath"), but the ability to make a free choice is through Yechida (from Hebrew word "yachid", יחיד, singular), the part of the soul that is united with God,
the only being that is not hindered by or dependent on cause and effect
(thus, freedom of will does not belong to the realm of the physical
reality, and inability of natural philosophy to account for it is
expected).
In Islam, the theological issue is not usually how to reconcile free will with God's foreknowledge but with God's jabr or divine commanding power. al-Ash'ari developed an "acquisition" or "dual-agency" form of compatibilism, in which human free will and divine jabr were both asserted, and which became a cornerstone of the dominant Ash'ari position. In Shia Islam, Ash'aris understanding of a higher balance toward predestination is challenged by most theologists.
Free will, according to Islamic doctrine is the main factor for man's
accountability in his/her actions throughout life. All actions committed
by man's free will are said to be counted on the Day of Judgement because they are his/her own and not God's.
The philosopher Søren Kierkegaard claimed that divine omnipotence cannot be separated from divine goodness.
As a truly omnipotent and good being, God could create beings with true
freedom over God. Furthermore, God would voluntarily do so because "the
greatest good... which can be done for a being, greater than anything
else that one can do for it, is to be truly free." Alvin Plantinga's free-will defense is a contemporary expansion of this theme, adding how God, free will, and evil are consistent.
Frede
wrote that he could not find either the language of free will nor even
any assumption of it in the New Testament or the Greek Old Testament. According to Frede, the early Church fathers most certainly developed their doctrine of free will from the pagans.
Another Oxford scholar, Dr. Alister McGrath,
concurs entirely with Frede, "The term 'free will' is not biblical, but
derives from Stoicism. It was introduced into Western Christianity by
the second-century theologian Tertullian."
Pauline expert, Troels Engberg-Pedersen,
unequivocally insists that, "Paul firmly believed in divine
determination as an intrinsic part of his whole conception of God."
The implicit argument
Nonetheless,
many have argued an "implicit" case for finding free will in the Bible.
The most fundamental source for this case lies in the fall into sin by Adam and Eve that occurred in their "willfully chosen" disobedience to God.
Some contend that "freedom" and "free will" can be treated as one because the two terms are commonly used as synonyms; however, there are widespread disagreements in definitions of the two terms. Because of these disagreements, Christian philosopher Mortimer Adler found that a delineation of three kinds of freedom is necessary for clarity on the subject, as follows:
(1) Circumstantial freedom is "freedom from coercion or restraint" that prevents acting as one wills.
In the Bible, circumstantial freedom was given to the Israelites in The Exodus from slavery in Egypt.
(2) Natural freedom (a.k.a. volitional freedom) is freedom to
determine one's own "decisions or plans." Natural freedom is inherent in
all people, in all circumstances, and "without regard to any state of mind or character which they may or may not acquire in the course of their lives."
Other theologians, paralleling Adler, view all humanity as naturally possessing the "free choice of the will."
If "free will" is taken to mean unconstrained and voluntary choice, the
Bible assumes that all people, unregenerate and regenerate, possess it. For examples, "free will" is taught in Matthew 23:37 and Revelation 22:17.
(3) Acquired freedom is freedom "to live as [one] ought to
live," a freedom that requires a transformation whereby a person
acquires a righteous, holy, healthy, etc. "state of mind or character."
The Bible testifies to the need for acquired freedom because no
one "is free for obedience and faith till he is freed from sin's
dominion." People possess natural freedom but their "voluntary choices"
serve sin until they acquire freedom from "sin's dominion." The New Bible Dictionary denotes this acquired freedom for "obedience and faith" as "free will" in a theological sense.
Therefore, in biblical thinking, an acquired freedom from being
"enslaved to sin" is needed "to live up to Jesus' commandments to love
God and love neighbor."
Jesus told his hearers that they needed to be made "free indeed" (John 8:36). "Free indeed [ontós]" means "truly free" or "really free," as it is in some translations. Being made "free indeed" means freedom from "bondage to sin." This acquired freedom is "freedom to serve the Lord."
Being "free indeed" (i.e., true freedom) comes by "God's changing our
nature" to free us from being "slaves to sin." and endowing us with "the
freedom to choose to be righteous."
Mark R. Talbot, a "classical Christian theist," views this acquired "compatibilist freedom" as the freedom that "Scripture portrays as worth having."
Open theism denies that classical theism's compatibilist "freedom to choose to be righteous without the possibility of choosing otherwise." qualifies as true freedom. For open theism, true libertarian freedom is incompatibilist freedom. Regardless of factors, a person has the freedom to choose the opposite alternatives. In open theist William Hasker's words, regarding any action it is always "within the agent's power to perform the action and also in the agent's power to refrain from the action."
Although open theism generally contradicts classical theism's "freedom
to choose to be righteous without the possibility of choosing
otherwise," Hasker allows that Jesus possessed and humans in heaven will
possess such freedom. Regarding Jesus, Hasker views Jesus as "a free
agent," but he also thinks that "it was not really possible" that Jesus
would "abort the mission."
Regarding heaven, Hasker foresees that as the result of our choice we
will be "unable to sin" because all sinful impulses will be gone.
Roman Catholic
Today, theologians of the Roman Catholic Church universally embrace the idea of free will, but generally do not view free will as existing apart from or in contradiction to grace.
According to the Roman Catholic Church "To God, all moments of time are
present in their immediacy. When therefore he establishes his eternal
plan of "predestination", he includes in it each person's free response to his grace."
The Council of Trent declared that "the free will of man, moved and
excited by God, can by its consent co-operate with God, Who excites and
invites its action; and that it can thereby dispose and prepare itself
to obtain the grace of justification. The will can resist grace if it
chooses. It is not like a lifeless thing, which remains purely passive.
Weakened and diminished by Adam's fall, free will is yet not destroyed
in the race (Sess. VI, cap. i and v)."
During the era of the original Jesuits, a movement arose in Catholicism called Jansenism, which contradicted the Jesuits' teaching on free will. French Philosopher, Blaise Pascal was an adherent of this theology. There are no modern adherents of Jansenism.
St. Augustine and St. Thomas Aquinas wrote extensively on free will, with Augustine focusing on the importance of free will in his responses to the Manichaeans, and also on the limitations of a concept of unlimited free will as denial of grace, in his refutations of Pelagius.
Denying the Roman Catholic teaching, John Duns Scotus asserted that "the created will acts just for internal reasons, and therefore contingently in all circumstances", even in Heaven, "regardless of the perfection of the object presented by the intellect."
On the contrary, the Roman Catholic teaching affirms that when God—the
proper object of the will—is known with sufficient clarity in the
afterlife, then "the perpetuity" of the free will's act is necessary and "in Heaven is guaranteed by the absence of reason for the will to will something else."
The Catechism of the Roman Catholic Church asserts that "Freedom is the power, rooted in reason and will". It goes on to say that "God created man a rational
being, conferring on him the dignity of a person who can initiate and
control his own actions. God willed that man should be 'left in the hand
of his own counsel,' so that he might of his own accord seek his
Creator and freely attain his full and blessed perfection by cleaving to
him.""
The section concludes with the role that grace plays, "By the working
of grace the Holy Spirit educates us in spiritual freedom in order to
make us free collaborators in his work in the Church and in the world."
ReformedLatin Christianity's views on free will and grace are often contrasted with predestination in ReformedProtestant Christianity,
especially after the Counter-Reformation, but in understanding
differing conceptions of free will it is just as important to understand
the differing conceptions of the nature of God, focusing on the idea
that God can be all-powerful and all-knowing even while people continue to exercise free will, because God transcends time.
The papal encyclical on human freedom, Libertas Praestantissimum by Pope Leo XIII (1888),
seems to leave the question unresolved as to the relation between free
will and determinism: whether the correct notion is the compatibilist
one or the libertarian one. The quotations supporting compatibilism
include the one from St. Thomas (footnote 4) near the end of paragraph
6, regarding the cause of evil ("Whereas, when he sins, he acts in
opposition to reason, is moved by another, and is the victim of foreign
misapprehensions"),
and a similar passus suggesting a natural, cause-and-effect function of
human will ("harmony with his natural inclinations", "Creator of will",
"by whom all things are moved in conformity with their nature") near
the end of paragraph 8 (when considering the problem of how grace can
have effects on free will). On the other hand, metaphysical
libertarianism – at least as a sort of possibility of reversing the
direction of one's acting – is suggested by the reference to the
well-known philosophical term metaphysical freedom at the
beginning of paragraph 3 and, to an extent, a contrasting comparison of
animals, which always act "of necessity", with human liberty, by means
of which one can "either act or not act, do this or do that".
Critique that seems more or less to support popular
incompatibilistic views can be found in some papal documents especially
in the 20th century, no explicit condemnation, however, of causal determinism in its most generic form can be found there. More often these documents focus on condemnation of physicalism/materialism and the stressing of significance of belief in soul, as a non-physical indivisible substance equipped with intellect and will, which decides human proceeding in a (perhaps imprecise) way.
Orthodox Christianity
Oriental Orthodox
The concept of free will is also of vital importance in the Oriental (or non-Chalcedonian) Churches, those in communion with the Coptic Orthodox Church of Alexandria. As in Judaism, free will is regarded as axiomatic. Everyone is regarded as having a free choice as to in what measure he or she will follow his or her conscience or arrogance,
these two having been appointed for each individual. The more one
follows one's conscience, the more it brings one good results, and the
more one follows one's arrogance, the more it brings one bad results.
Following only one's arrogance is sometimes likened to the dangers of
falling into a pit while walking in pitch darkness, without the light of
conscience to illuminate the path. Very similar doctrines have also
found written expression in the Dead Sea Scrolls "Manual of Discipline", and in some religious texts possessed by the Beta Israel Jews of Ethiopia.
Eastern Orthodox
The Eastern (or Chalcedonian) Orthodox Church
espouses a belief different from the Lutheran, Calvinist, and Arminian
Protestant views. The difference is in the interpretation of original sin, alternatively known as "ancestral sin," where the Orthodox do not believe in total depravity. The Orthodox reject the Pelagian
view that the original sin did not damage human nature; they accept
that the human nature is depraved, but despite man's fallenness the
divine image he bears has not been destroyed.
The Orthodox Church holds to the teaching of synergy (συνεργός,
meaning working together), which says that man has the freedom to, and
must if he wants to be saved, choose to accept and work with the grace
of God. St. John Cassian, a 4th-century Church Father and pupil of St. John Chrysostom,
articulated this view and all the Eastern Fathers embraced it. He
taught that "Divine grace is necessary to enable a sinner to return unto
God and live, yet man must first, of himself, desire and attempt to
choose and obey God", and that "Divine grace is indispensable for
salvation, but it does not necessarily need to precede a free human
choice, because, despite the weakness of human volition, the will can
take the initiative toward God.".
Some Orthodox Christians use the parable of a drowning man to
plainly illustrate the teaching of synergy: God from the ship throws a
rope to a drowning man, pulls him up, saving him, and the man, if he
wants to be saved, must hold on tightly to the rope; explaining both
that salvation is a gift from God and man cannot save himself, and that
man must co-work (syn-ergo) with God in the process of salvation.
Fyodor Dostoevsky, the Russian Orthodox Christian novelist, suggested many arguments for and against free will. Famous arguments are found in "The Grand Inquisitor" chapter in The Brothers Karamazov, and in his work Notes from Underground. He also developed an argument that suicide, if irrational, is actually a validation of free will (see Kirilov in the Demons) novel. As for the argument presented in The Brothers Karamazov's
section "The Rebellion" that the suffering of innocents was not worth
the price of free will, Dostoevsky appears to propose the idea of apocatastasis (or universal reconciliation) as one possible rational solution.
Roman Catholic teaching
Illustrating as it does that the human part in salvation (represented
by holding on to the rope) must be preceded and accompanied by grace
(represented by the casting and drawing of the rope), the image of the
drowning man holding on to the rope cast and drawn by his rescuer
corresponds closely to Roman Catholic teaching, which holds that God,
who "destined us in love to be his sons" and "to be conformed to the
image of his Son", includes in his eternal plan of "predestination" each person's free response to his grace.
The Roman Catholic Church holds to the teaching that "by free
will, (the human person) is capable of directing himself toward his true
good ... man is endowed with freedom, an outstanding manifestation of
the divine image'." Man has free will either to accept or reject the grace of God, so that for salvation "there is a kind of interplay, or synergy, between human freedom and divine grace".
"Justification establishes cooperation between God's grace and man's
freedom. On man's part it is expressed by the assent of faith to the
Word of God, which invites him to conversion, and in the cooperation of
charity with the prompting of the Holy Spirit who precedes and preserves
his assent: 'When God touches man's heart through the illumination of
the Holy Spirit, man himself is not inactive while receiving that
inspiration, since he could reject it; and yet, without God's grace, he
cannot by his own free will move himself toward justice in God's sight'
(Council of Trent)."
God has freely chosen to associate man with the work of his
grace. the fatherly action of God is first on his own initiative, and
then follows man's free acting through his collaboration. For Roman Catholics, therefore, human cooperation with grace is essential.
When God establishes his eternal plan of 'predestination', he includes
in it each person's free response to his grace, whether it is positive
or negative: "In this city, in fact, both Herod and Pontius Pilate, with
the Gentiles and the peoples of Israel, gathered together against your
holy servant Jesus, whom you anointed, to do whatever your hand and your
plan had predestined to take place" (Acts 4:27–28).
The initiative comes from God,
but it demands a free response from man: "God has freely chosen to
associate man with the work of his grace. the fatherly action of God is
first on his own initiative, and then follows man's free acting through
his collaboration".
"Since the initiative belongs to God in the order of grace, no one can
merit the initial grace of forgiveness and justification, at the
beginning of conversion. Moved by the Holy Spirit and by charity, we can
then merit for ourselves and for others the graces needed for our
sanctification, for the increase of grace and charity, and for the
attainment of eternal life."
Orthodox criticism of Roman Catholic theology
Orthodox theologian Vladimir Lossky has stated that the teaching of John Cassian,
who in the East is considered a witness to Tradition, but who "was
unable to make himself correctly understood", "was interpreted, on the
rational plane, as a semi-pelagianism, and was condemned in the West".
Where the Roman Catholic Church defends the concept of faith and free
will these are questioned in the East by the conclusions of the Second Council of Orange. This council is not accepted by the Eastern churches and the Roman Catholic Church's use of describing their position and St Cassian as Semi-Pelagian is also rejected.
Although the Roman Catholic Church explicitly teaches that
"original sin does not have the character of a personal fault in any of
Adam's descendants",
some Eastern Orthodox nevertheless claim that Roman Catholicism
professes the teaching, which they attribute to Saint Augustine, that
everyone bears not only the consequence, but also the guilt of Adam's
sin.
Differences of view between Roman Catholic and Orthodox Churches
Various Roman Catholic theologians identify Cassian as a teacher of the semipelagian heresy which was condemned by the Council of Orange.
While the Orthodox do not apply the term semipelagian to their
theology, they criticize the Roman Catholics for rejecting Cassian whom
they accept as fully orthodox, and for holding that human consent to God's justifying action is itself an effect of grace, a position shared by Eastern Orthodox theologian Georges Florovsky,
who says that the Eastern Orthodox Church "always understood that God
initiates, accompanies, and completes everything in the process of
salvation", rejecting instead the Calvinist idea of irresistible grace.
Recently, some Roman Catholic theologians have argued that Cassian's writings should not be considered semipelagian. And scholars of other denominations too have concluded that Cassian's thought "is not Semi-Pelagian", and that he instead taught that "salvation is, from beginning to end, the effect of God's grace" and held that "God's grace, not human free will, is responsible for 'everything which pertains to salvation' - even faith."
The Orthodox Church holds to the teaching of synergy
(συνεργός, meaning working together), which says that man has the
freedom to, and must if he wants to be saved, choose to accept and work
with the grace of God. Once baptised the experience of his salvation and
relationship with God is called theosis.
Mankind has free will to accept or reject the grace of God. Rejection
of the gifts of God is called blasphemy of the Holy Spirit (gifts of
grace, faith, life). The first who defined this teaching was John Cassian, 4th-century Church Father, and a pupil of John Chrysostom,
and all Eastern Fathers accept it. He taught that "Divine grace is
necessary to enable a sinner to return unto God and live, yet man must
first, of himself, desire and attempt to choose and obey God", and that
"Divine grace is indispensable for salvation, but it does not
necessarily need to precede a free human choice, because, despite the
weakness of human volition, the will can take the initiative toward
God.".
Some Orthodox use an example of a drowning man to illustrate the
teaching of synergy: God from the ship throws a rope to a drowning man,
the man may take the rope if he wants to be saved, but he may decide not
to take the rope and perish by his own will. Explaining both that
salvation is a gift from God and man cannot save himself. That man must
co-work (syn-ergo) with God in the process of salvation.
Lutherans adhere to divine monergism,
the teaching that salvation is by God's act alone, and therefore reject
the idea that humans in their fallen state have a free will concerning
spiritual matters.
Lutherans believe that although humans have free will concerning civil
righteousness, they cannot work spiritual righteousness without the Holy
Spirit, since righteousness in the heart cannot be wrought in the
absence of the Holy Spirit. In other words, humanity is free to choose and act in every regard except for the choice of salvation.
Lutherans also teach that sinners, while capable of doing works that are outwardly "good," are not capable of doing works that satisfy God's justice. Every human thought and deed is infected with sin and sinful motives. For Luther himself, in his Bondage of the Will,
people are by nature endowed with free-will/free choice in regard to
"goods and possessions" with which a person "has the right of using,
acting, and omitting according to his Free-will." However, in "God-ward"
things pertaining to "salvation or damnation" people are in bondage
"either to the will of God, or to the will of Satan."
As found in Paul Althaus' study of Luther's theology, sin's infection of every human thought and deed began with Adam's fall into sin, the Original Sin.
Adam's fall was a "terrible example" of what "free will" will do unless
God constantly motivates it to virtuous behavior. Humanity inherits
Adam's sin. Thus, in our "natural condition," we have an inborn desire
to sin because that is the person we are by birth. As Luther noted,
"Adam sinned willingly and freely and from him a will to sin has been
born into us so that we cannot sin innocently but only voluntarily."
The controversial term liberum arbitrium was translated "free-will" by Henry Cole and "free will" remains in general use. However, the Rupp/Watson study of Luther and Erasmus chose "free choice" as the translation and provided a rationale.
Luther used "free choice" (or "free-will") to denote the fact that
humans act "spontaneously" and with "a desirous willingness." He also allowed "Free-will" as that "power" by which humans "can be caught by the Spirit" of God.
However, he deplored the use of the term "Free-will" because it is too
"grand, copious, and full." Therefore, Luther held that the inborn
faculty of "willingness" should be "called by some other term."
Although our wills are a function of and are in bondage to our
inherited sinful desires, Luther insisted that we sin "voluntarily."
Voluntarily means that we sin of our own free will.
We will to do what we desire. As long as we desire sin, our wills are
only free for sin. This is Luther's "bondage of the will" to sin. The
sinner's "will is bound, but it is and remains his will. He
repeatedly and voluntarily acts according to it." So it is, to be set
free from sin and for righteousness requires a "rebirth through faith." A rebirth of faith gives "true freedom from sin," which is, wrote Luther, "a liberty [freedom] to do good."
To use a biblical word important to Luther, to be set free from sin and for righteousness requires a metanoia. Luther used Jesus' image of the good and bad trees
to depict the necessity of changing the person to change what a person
wills and does. In Jesus' image, "a good tree cannot bear bad fruit, and
a bad tree cannot bear good fruit" (Matthew 7:18).
Like the bad tree that can only produce bad fruit, before a rebirth
through faith, people are in bondage to the sinful desires of their
hearts. They can only will to do sin, albeit "spontaneously and with a
desirous willingness."
Given his view of the human condition, Luther concluded that, without a
rebirth, the "free choice" that all humans possess is "not free at all"
because it cannot of itself free itself from its inherent bondage to
sin.
Thus, Luther distinguished between different kinds of freedom:
(a) by nature, a freedom to act as we will and (b) by rebirth through
faith, a freedom to act righteously.
God and creation
Orthodox Lutheran theology holds that God made the world, including humanity, perfect, holy and sinless. However, Adam and Eve chose to disobey God, trusting in their own strength, knowledge, and wisdom. Consequently, people are saddled with original sin, born sinful and unable to avoid committing sinful acts. For Lutherans, original sin is the "chief sin, a root and fountainhead of all actual sins."
According to Lutherans, God preserves his creation, in doing so
cooperates with everything that happens, and guides the universe.
While God cooperates with both good and evil deeds, with evil deeds he
does so only inasmuch as they are deeds, but not with the evil in them.
God concurs with an act's effect, but he does not cooperate in the
corruption of an act or the evil of its effect.
Lutherans believe everything exists for the sake of the Christian
Church, and that God guides everything for its welfare and growth.
Predestination
Lutherans believe that the elect are predestined to salvation. Lutherans believe Christians should be assured that they are among the predestined.
Lutherans believe that all who trust in Jesus alone can be certain of
their salvation, for it is in Christ's work and his promises in which
their certainty lies.
According to Lutheranism, the central final hope of the Christian is
"the resurrection of the body and the life everlasting" as confessed in
the Apostles' Creed rather than predestination. Conversion or regeneration in the strict sense of the term is the work of divine grace and power by which man, born of the flesh, and void of all power to think, to will, or to do any good thing, and dead in sin is, through the gospel and holy baptism, taken from a state of sin and spiritual death under God's wrath into a state of spiritual life of faith and grace, rendered able to will and to do what is spiritually good and, especially, led to accept the benefits of the redemption which is in Christ Jesus.
Lutherans disagree with those that make predestination the source
of salvation rather than Christ's suffering, death, and resurrection.
Lutherans reject the Calvinist doctrine of the perseverance of the saints.
Like both Calvinist camps, Lutherans view the work of salvation as
monergistic in that "the natural [that is, corrupted and divinely
unrenewed] powers of man cannot do anything or help towards salvation" (Formula of Concord: Solid Declaration, art. ii, par. 71Archived 2008-05-16 at the Wayback Machine),
and Lutherans go further along the same lines as the Free Grace
advocates to say that the recipient of saving grace need not cooperate
with it. Hence, Lutherans believe that a true Christian (that is, a
genuine recipient of saving grace) can lose his or her salvation, "[b]ut
the cause is not as though God were unwilling to grant grace for
perseverance to those in whom He has begun the good work... [but that
these persons] wilfully turn away..." (Formula of Concord: Solid Declaration, art. xi, par. 42Archived 2008-05-16 at the Wayback Machine). Unlike Calvinists, Lutherans do not believe in a predestination to damnation.
Instead, Lutherans teach eternal damnation is a result of the
unbeliever's sins, rejection of the forgiveness of sins, and unbelief.
John Calvin ascribed "free will" to all people in the sense that they act "voluntarily, and not by compulsion."
He elaborated his position by allowing "that man has choice and that it
is self-determined" and that his actions stem from "his own voluntary
choosing."
The free will that Calvin ascribed to all people is what Mortimer Adler calls the "natural freedom" of the will. This freedom to will what one desires is inherent in all people.
Calvin held this kind of inherent/natural
free will in disesteem because unless people acquire the freedom to
live as they ought by being transformed, they will desire and
voluntarily choose to sin. "Man is said to have free will," wrote
Calvin, "because he acts voluntarily, and not by compulsion. This is
perfectly true: but why should so small a matter have been dignified
with so proud a title?"
The glitch in this inherent/natural freedom of the will is that
although all people have the "faculty of willing," by nature they are
unavoidably (and yet voluntarily without compulsion) under "the bondage
of sin."
The kind of free will that Calvin esteems is what Adler calls "acquired freedom" of the will, the freedom/ability
"to live as [one] ought." To possess acquired free will requires a
change by which a person acquires a desire to live a life marked by
virtuous qualities. As Calvin describes the change required for acquired freedom, the will "must be wholly transformed and renovated."
Calvin depicts this transformation as "a new heart and a new
spirit (Ezek. 18:31)." It sets one free from "bondage to sin" and
enables "piety towards God, and love towards men, general holiness and
purity of life."
CalvinistProtestants embrace the idea of predestination,
namely, that God chose who would be saved and who would be not saved
prior to the creation. They quote Ephesians 1:4 "For he chose us in him
before the creation of the world to be holy and blameless in his sight"
and also 2:8 "For it is by grace you are saved, through faith, and this
not of yourselves, it is the gift of God." One of the strongest
defenders of this theological point of view was the American Puritan preacher and theologian Jonathan Edwards.
Edwards believed that indeterminism was incompatible with
individual dependence on God and hence with his sovereignty. He reasoned
that if individuals' responses to God's grace are contra-causally free,
then their salvation depends partly on them and therefore God's
sovereignty is not "absolute and universal." Edwards' book Freedom of the Will
defends theological determinism. In this book, Edwards attempts to show
that libertarianism is incoherent. For example, he argues that by
'self-determination' the libertarian must mean either that one's actions
including one's acts of willing are preceded by an act of free will or
that one's acts of will lack sufficient causes. The first leads to an
infinite regress while the second implies that acts of will happen
accidentally and hence can't make someone "better or worse, any more
than a tree is better than other trees because it oftener happens to be
lit upon by a swan or nightingale; or a rock more vicious than other
rocks, because rattlesnakes have happened oftener to crawl over it."
It should not be thought that this view completely denies freedom
of choice, however. It claims that man is free to act on his strongest
moral impulse and volition, which is externally determined, but is not
free to act contrary to them, or to alter them. Proponents, such as John L. Girardeau,
have indicated their belief that moral neutrality is impossible; that
even if it were possible, and one were equally inclined to contrary
options, one could make no choice at all; that if one is inclined,
however slightly, toward one option, then that person will necessarily
choose that one over any others.
Some non-Calvinist Christians attempt a reconciliation of the
dual concepts of predestination and free will by pointing to the
situation of God as Christ. In taking the form of a man, a necessary
element of this process was that Jesus Christ lived the existence of a
mortal. When Jesus was born he was not born with the omniscient power of
God the Creator, but with the mind of a human child - yet he was still
God in essence. The precedent this creates is that God is able to will
the abandonment of His knowledge, or ignore knowledge, while remaining
fully God. Thus it is not inconceivable that although omniscience
demands that God knows what the future holds for individuals, it is
within his power to deny this knowledge in order to preserve individual
free will. Other theologians argue that the Calvinist-Edwardsean view
suggests that if all human volitions are predetermined by God, then all
actions dictated by fallen will of man necessarily satisfy His sovereign
decree. Hence, it is impossible to act outside of God's perfect will, a
conclusion some non-Calvinists claim poses a serious problem for ethics
and moral theology.
An early proposal toward such a reconciliation states that God
is, in fact, not aware of future events, but rather, being eternal, He
is outside time, and sees the past, present, and future as one whole
creation. Consequently, it is not as though God would know "in advance"
that Jeffrey Dahmer
would become guilty of homicide years prior to the event as an example,
but that He was aware of it from all eternity, viewing all time as a
single present. This was the view offered by Boethius in Book V of The Consolation of Philosophy.
Calvinist theologian Loraine Boettner
argued that the doctrine of divine foreknowledge does not escape the
alleged problems of divine foreordination. He wrote that "what God
foreknows must, in the very nature of the case, be as fixed and certain
as what is foreordained; and if one is inconsistent with the free agency
of man, the other is also. Foreordination renders the events certain,
while foreknowledge presupposes that they are certain."
Some Christian theologians, feeling the bite of this argument, have
opted to limit the doctrine of foreknowledge if not do away with it
altogether, thus forming a new school of thought, similar to Socinianism and process theology, called open theism.
Christians who were influenced by the teachings of Jacobus Arminius (such as Methodists)
believe that while God is all-knowing and always knows what choices
each person will make, he still gives them the ability to choose or not
choose everything, regardless of whether there are any internal or
external factors contributing to that choice.
Concerning grace and free will, this is what I teach according to the
Scriptures and orthodox consent: Free will is unable to begin or to
perfect any true and spiritual good, without grace.... This grace [prœvenit] goes before, accompanies, and follows; it excites, assists, operates that we will, and co operates lest we will in vain.
Prevenient grace is divine grace
which precedes human decision. It exists prior to and without reference
to anything humans may have done. As humans are corrupted by the
effects of sin, prevenient grace allows persons to engage their God-given free will to choose the salvation offered by God in Jesus Christ or to reject that salvific offer. Methodist theology thus teaches:
Our Lord Jesus Christ did so die
for all men as to make salvation attainable by every man that cometh
into the world. If men are not saved that fault is entirely their own,
lying solely in their own unwillingness to obtain the salvation offered
to them. (John 1:9; I Thess. 5:9; Titus 2:11-12).
Thomas Jay Oord
offers perhaps the most cogent free will theology presupposing
prevenient grace. What he calls "essential kenosis" says God acts
preveniently to give freedom/agency to all creatures. This gift comes
from God's eternal essence, and is therefore necessary. God remains free
in choosing how to love, but the fact that God loves and therefore
gives freedom/agency to others is a necessary part of what it means to
be divine.
This view is backed in the Bible with verses such as Luke 13:34, NKJV
O Jerusalem, Jerusalem, the one who kills the prophets and stones
those who are sent to her! How often I wanted to gather your children
together, as a hen gathers her brood under her wings, but you were not
willing!"
Here we see Jesus lamenting that He is unable to save Jerusalem
as they are not willing. We see that whilst Jesus wants to save
Jerusalem He respects their choice to continue on in sin despite His
will that they be saved.
Comparison of Protestants
This table summarizes three classical Protestant beliefs about free will.
John Calvin
Martin Luther
Jacob Arminius
For Calvin, humanity possesses "free will," but it is in bondage to sin, unless it is "transformed."
For Luther,
humanity possesses free-will/free choice in regard to "goods and
possessions," but regarding "salvation or damnation" people are in
bondage either to God or Satan."
For Arminius, humanity possesses freedom from necessity, but not "freedom from sin" unless enabled by "prevenient grace."
Latter Day Saints believe that God has given all humans the gift of moral agency. Moral agency includes free will and agency.
Proper exercise of unfettered choice leads to the ultimate goal of
returning to God's presence. Having the choice to do right or wrong was
important, because God wants a society of a certain type—those that
comply with eternal laws. Before this Earth was created, this dispute
over agency rose to the level that there was a "war in heaven." Lucifer
(who favored no agency) and his followers were cast out of heaven for
rebelling against God's will. Many Mormon leaders have also taught that
the battle in Heaven over agency is now being carried out on earth, where dictators, influenced by Satan, fight against freedom (or free agency) in governments contrary to the will of God.
Mormons also believe in a limited form of foreordination — not in
deterministic, unalterable decrees, but rather in callings from God for
individuals to perform specific missions in mortality. Those who are
foreordained can reject the foreordination, either outright or by
transgressing the laws of God and becoming unworthy to fulfill the call.
New Church
The New Church, or Swedenborgianism, teaches that every person has complete freedom to choose heaven or hell. Emanuel Swedenborg,
upon whose writings the New Church is founded, argued that if God is
love itself, people must have free will. If God is love itself, then He
desires no harm to come to anyone: and so it is impossible that he would
predestine anyone to hell. On the other hand, if God is love itself,
then He must love things outside of Himself; and if people do not have
the freedom to choose evil, they are simply extensions of God, and He
cannot love them as something outside of Himself. In addition,
Swedenborg argues that if a person does not have free will to choose
goodness and faith, then all of the commandments in the Bible to love
God and the neighbor are worthless, since no one can choose to do them -
and it is impossible that a God who is love itself and wisdom itself
would give impossible commandments.
As Hinduism is primarily a conglomerate of different religious traditions, there is no one accepted view on the concept of free will. Within the predominant schools of Hindu philosophy there are two main opinions. The Advaita (monistic) schools generally believe in a fate-based approach, and the Dvaita (dualistic) schools are proponents for the theory of free will. The different schools' understandings are based upon their conceptions of the nature of the supreme Being (see Brahman, Paramatma and Ishvara) and how the individual Self (atma or jiva) dictates, or is dictated by karma within the illusory existence of maya.
In both Dvaita and Advaita schools, and also in the many other traditions within Hinduism, there is a strong belief in destiny and that both the past and future are known, or viewable, by certain saints or mystics as well as by the supreme being (Ishvara) in traditions where Ishvara is worshipped as an all-knowing being. In the Bhagavad Gita, the Avatar, Krishna says to Arjuna:
I know everything that has happened in the past, all that is happening in the present, and all things that are yet to come.
However, this belief in destiny is not necessarily believed to rule
out the existence of free will, as in some cases both free will and
destiny are believed to exist simultaneously.
Nor does the Supreme Lord assume anyone's sinful or pious activities (Bhagavad Gita 5.15)
From wherever the mind wanders due to its flickering and unsteady
nature, one must certainly withdraw it and bring it back under the
control of the self (Bhagavad Gita 6.26), indicating that God does not control anyone's will, and that it is possible to control the mind.
Different approaches
The six orthodox (astika) schools of thought in Hindu philosophy give differing opinions: In the Samkhya,
for instance, matter is without any freedom, and Self lacks any ability
to control the unfolding of matter. The only real freedom (kaivalya) consists in realizing the ultimate separateness of matter and self. For the Yoga school, only Ishvara
is truly free, and its freedom is also distinct from all feelings,
thoughts, actions, or wills, and is thus not at all a freedom of will.
The metaphysics of the Nyaya and Vaisheshika schools strongly suggest a belief in determinism, but do not seem to make explicit claims about determinism or free will.
A quotation from Swami Vivekananda, a Vedantist, offers a good example of the worry about free will in the Hindu tradition.
Therefore, we see at once that there cannot be any such
thing as free-will; the very words are a contradiction, because will is
what we know, and everything that we know is within our universe, and
everything within our universe is moulded by conditions of time, space
and causality. ... To acquire freedom we have to get beyond the
limitations of this universe; it cannot be found here.
However, Vivekananda's above quote can't be taken as a literal refutation of all free will, as Vivekanda's teacher, Ramakrishna Paramahansa
used to teach that man is like a goat tied to a stake - the karmic
debts and human nature bind him and the amount of free will he has is
analogous to the amount of freedom the rope allows; as one progresses
spiritually, the rope becomes longer.
On the other hand, Mimamsa, Vedanta, and the more theistic versions of Hinduism such as Shaivism and Vaishnavism have often emphasized the importance of free will. For example, in the Bhagavad Gita the living beings (jivas) are described as being of a higher nature who have the freedom to exploit the inferior material nature (prakrti):
Besides these, O mighty-armed Arjuna, there is another,
superior energy of Mine, which comprises the living entities who are
exploiting the resources of this material, inferior nature.
The doctrine of Karma in Hinduism
requires both that we pay for our actions in the past, and that our
actions in the present be free enough to allow us to deserve the future
reward or punishment that we will receive for our present actions. The Advaitin philosopher Chandrashekhara Bharati Swaminah puts it this way:
Fate is past karma, free-will is present karma. Both are
really one, that is, karma, though they may differ in the matter of
time. There can be no conflict when they are really one.
Fate, as I told you, is the resultant of the past exercise of your
free-will. By exercising your free-will in the past, you brought on the
resultant fate. By exercising your free-will in the present, I want you
to wipe out your past record if it hurts you, or to add to it if you
find it enjoyable. In any case, whether for acquiring more happiness or
for reducing misery, you have to exercise your free-will in the present.
Disputes about free will in Islam began with the Mu'tazili vs Hanbali disputes, with the Mu'tazili arguing that humans had qadar, the capacity to do right or wrong, and thus deserved the reward or punishment they received, whereas Hanbali insisted on God's jabr, or total power and initiative in managing all events. Schools that developed around earlier thinkers such as Abu Hanifa and al-Ash'ari searched for ways to explain how both human qadar and divine jabr
could be asserted at the same time. Ash'ari develops a "dual agency" or
"acquisition" account of free will in which every human action has two
distinct agents. God creates the possibility of a human action with his
divine jabr, but then the human follows through and "acquires"
the act, making it theirs and taking responsibility for it using their
human qadar.
The belief in free will (Hebrew: bechirah chofshit בחירה חפשית, bechirah בחירה) is axiomatic in Jewish thought, and is closely linked with the concept of reward and punishment, based on the Torah itself: "I [God] have set before you life and death, blessing and curse: therefore choose life" (Deuteronomy 30:19).
According to the Mishnah, "This world is like a vestibule before the World to Come".
According to an 18th-century rabbinic work, "Man was created for the
sole purpose of rejoicing in God, and deriving pleasure from the
splendor of His Presence... The place where this joy may truly be
derived is the World to Come, which was expressly created to provide for it; but the path to the object of our desires is this world..."
Free will is thus required by God's justice, "otherwise, Man would not
be given or denied good for actions over which he had no control".
It is further understood that in order for Man to have true free
choice, he must not only have inner free will, but also an environment
in which a choice between obedience and disobedience exists. God thus
created the world such that both good and evil can operate freely, this
is the meaning of the rabbinic maxim, "All is in the hands of Heaven except the fear of Heaven".
Free will is granted to every man.
If he desires to incline towards the good way and be righteous, he has
the power to do so; and if he desires to incline towards the unrighteous
way and be a wicked man, he also has the power to do so. Give no place
in your minds to that which is asserted by many of the ignorant: namely
that the Holy One, blessed be He, decrees that a man from his birth
should be either righteous or wicked. Since the power of doing good or
evil is in our own hands, and since all the wicked deeds which we have
committed have been committed with our full consciousness, it befits us
to turn in penitence and to forsake our evil deed.
The paradox of free will
In rabbinic literature, there is much discussion as to the apparent contradiction between God's omniscience and free will. The representative view is that "Everything is foreseen; yet free will is given" (Pirkei Avot3:15). Based on this understanding, the problem is formally described as a paradox, beyond our understanding.
The Holy One, Blessed Be He, knows
everything that will happen before it has happened. So does He know
whether a particular person will be righteous or wicked, or not? If He
does know, then it will be impossible for that person not to be
righteous. If He knows that he will be righteous but that it is possible
for him to be wicked, then He does not know everything that He has
created. ...[T]he Holy One, Blessed Be He, does not have any
temperaments and is outside such realms, unlike people, whose selves and
temperaments are two separate things. God and His temperaments are one,
and God's existence is beyond the comprehension of Man... [Thus] we do
not have the capabilities to comprehend how the Holy One, Blessed Be He,
knows all creations and events. [Nevertheless] know without doubt that
people do what they want without the Holy One, Blessed Be He, forcing or
decreeing upon them to do so... It has been said because of this that a
man is judged according to all his actions.
The paradox is explained, but not resolved, by observing that God exists outside of time,
and therefore, his knowledge of the future is exactly the same as his
knowledge of the past and present. Just as his knowledge of the past
does not interfere with man's free will, neither does his knowledge of
the future. This distinction, between foreknowledge and predestination, is in fact discussed by Abraham ibn Daud.
One analogy here is that of time travel.
The time traveller, having returned from the future, knows in advance
what x will do, but while he knows what x will do, that knowledge does
not cause x to do so: x had free will, even while the time traveller had
foreknowledge.
One objection raised against this analogy – and ibn Daud's distinction –
is that if x truly has free will, he may choose to act otherwise when
the event in question comes to pass, and therefore the time traveller
(or God) merely has knowledge of a possible event: even having seen the event, there is no way to know with certainty what x will do; see the view of Gersonides below. Further, the presence of the time traveller, may have had some chaotic effect on x's circumstances and choice, absent when the event comes to pass in the present.)
In line with this, the teaching from Pirkei Avot quoted above, can be read as: "Everything is observed (while - and no matter where - it happens), and (since the actor is unaware of being observed) free will is given".
Alternate approaches
Although
the above discussion of the paradox represents the majority rabbinic
view, there are several major thinkers who resolve the issue by
explicitly excluding human action from divine foreknowledge.
Rashi at the beginning of Sotah (Talmud)
(page 2a d.h. Aini) comments "How could the Divine decree concerning a
future marriage be based on the person's merit or wickedness? Before he
is formed, when his future marriage is decreed, his wickedness or merit
is not known. If you will ask that everything is known to Him, we are
taught that 'All is in the power of G-d except for the fear of G-d.'
This is as it says in tractate Niddah (Talmud),
that the angel appointed over pregnancy brings the droplet and presents
it before G-d, and asks 'What shall be the fate of this droplet? Shall
it be strong or weak, wise or foolish, wealthy or poor?' But he does
not ask if it shall be righteous or wicked, for this is not in the power
of G-d."
Gersonides
holds that God knows, beforehand, the choices open to each individual,
but does not know which choice the individual, in his freedom, will
make.
Isaiah Horowitz
takes the view that God cannot know which moral choices people will
make, but that, nevertheless, this does not impair his perfection; it is
as if one's actions cause one of the many possibilities that existed
then to have become known, but only once chosen.
Rabbi Mordechai Yosef Leiner
holds perhaps the most controversial view: apparently denying that man
has free will, and that instead all is determined by God.
The existence of free will, and the paradox above (as addressed by either approach), is closely linked to the concept of Tzimtzum. Tzimtzum entails the idea that God "constricted" his infinite essence, to allow for the existence of a "conceptual space" in which a finite, independent world could exist. This "constriction" made free will possible, and hence the potential to earn the World to Come.
Further, according to the first approach, it is understood that
the Free-will Omniscience paradox provides a temporal parallel to the
paradox inherent within Tzimtzum. In granting free will, God has
somehow "constricted" his foreknowledge, to allow for Man's independent
action; He thus has foreknowledge and yet free will exists. In the case
of Tzimtzum, God has "constricted" his essence to allow for Man's independent existence; He is thus immanent and yet transcendent.