From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
|
|
|
John Rogers Searle (; born July 31, 1932) is an American philosopher widely noted for contributions to the philosophy of language, philosophy of mind, and social philosophy.
He began teaching at UC Berkeley in 1959, and was Willis S. and Marion
Slusser Professor Emeritus of the Philosophy of Mind and Language and
Professor of the Graduate School at the University of California, Berkeley
until June 2019, when his status as professor emeritus was revoked
because he was found to have violated the university's sexual harassment
policies.
As an undergraduate at the University of Wisconsin–Madison, Searle was secretary of "Students against Joseph McCarthy". He received all his university degrees, BA, MA, and DPhil, from the University of Oxford, where he held his first faculty positions. Later, at UC Berkeley, he became the first tenured professor to join the 1964–1965 Free Speech Movement. In the late 1980s, Searle challenged the restrictions of Berkeley's 1980 rent stabilization ordinance.
Following what came to be known as the California Supreme Court's
"Searle Decision" of 1990, Berkeley changed its rent control policy,
leading to large rent increases between 1991 and 1994.
In 2000, Searle received the Jean Nicod Prize; in 2004, the National Humanities Medal; and in 2006, the Mind & Brain Prize. He was elected to the American Philosophical Society in 2010. Searle's early work on speech acts, influenced by J.L. Austin and Ludwig Wittgenstein, helped establish his reputation. His notable concepts include the "Chinese room" argument against "strong" artificial intelligence.
Biography
John Searle speaking at Google, 2015
Searle's father, G.W. Searle, an electrical engineer, was employed by AT&T Corporation; his mother, Hester Beck Searle, was a physician.
Searle began his college education at the University of Wisconsin–Madison and in his junior year became a Rhodes Scholar at the University of Oxford, where he obtained all his university degrees, BA, MA, and DPhil.
Searle was the Willis S. and Marion Slusser Professor Emeritus of
the Philosophy of Mind and Language and Professor of the Graduate
School at the University of California, Berkeley; he had retired in 2014 but continued teaching until 2016. In June 2019, the emeritus title was revoked.
Politics
While an undergraduate at the University of Wisconsin–Madison, Searle became the secretary of "Students against Joseph McCarthy". McCarthy at that time served as the junior senator from Wisconsin. In 1959, Searle began teaching at Berkeley, and he was the first tenured professor to join the 1964–65 Free Speech Movement. In 1969, while serving as chairman of the Academic Freedom Committee of the Academic Senate of the University of California, he supported the university in its dispute with students over the People's Park.
In The Campus War: A Sympathetic Look at the University in Agony (1971), Searle investigates the causes behind the campus protests of the era. In it he declares, "I have been attacked by both the House Un-American Activities Committee
and...several radical polemicists... Stylistically, the attacks are
interestingly similar. Both rely heavily on insinuation and innuendo,
and both display a hatred --one might almost say terror-- of close
analysis and dissection of argument." He asserts that "My wife was
threatened that I (and other members of the administration) would be assassinated or violently attacked."
In the late 1980s, Searle, along with other landlords, petitioned
Berkeley's rental board to raise the limits on how much he could charge
tenants under the city's 1980 rent-stabilization ordinance.
The rental board refused to consider Searle's petition and Searle filed
suit, charging a violation of due process. In 1990, in what came to be
known as the "Searle Decision", the California Supreme Court upheld
Searle's argument in part and Berkeley changed its rent-control policy,
leading to large rent-increases between 1991 and 1994. Searle was
reported to see the issue as one of fundamental rights, being quoted as
saying "The treatment of landlords in Berkeley is comparable to the
treatment of blacks in the South... our rights have been massively
violated and we are here to correct that injustice." The court described the debate as a "morass of political invective, ad hominem attack, and policy argument".
Shortly after the September 11 attacks,
Searle wrote an article arguing that the attacks were a particular
event in a long-term struggle against forces that are intractably
opposed to the United States, and signaled support for a more aggressive
neoconservative interventionist foreign policy. He called for the realization that the United States is in a more-or-less permanent state of war with these forces. Moreover, a probable course of action would be to deny terrorists
the use of foreign territory from which to stage their attacks.
Finally, he alluded to the long-term nature of the conflict and blamed
the attacks on the lack of American resolve to deal forcefully with
America's enemies over the past several decades.
Sexual assault allegations
In March 2017, Searle became the subject of sexual assault allegations. The Los Angeles Times
reported: "A new lawsuit alleges that university officials failed to
properly respond to complaints that John Searle ... sexually assaulted
his ... research associate last July and cut her pay when she rejected
his advances." The case brought to light several earlier complaints against Searle, on which Berkeley allegedly had failed to act.
The lawsuit, filed in a California court on March 21, 2017,
alleged sexual harassment, retaliation, wrongful termination and assault
and battery and sought damages both from Searle and from the Regents of the University of California as his employers.
It also claims that Jennifer Hudin, the director of the John Searle
Center for Social Ontology, where the complainant had been employed as
an assistant to Searle, has stated that Searle "has had sexual
relationships with his students and others in the past in exchange for
academic, monetary or other benefits".
After news of the lawsuit became public, several previous allegations
of sexual harassment and assault by Searle were also revealed.
On June 19, 2019, following campus disciplinary proceedings by
Berkeley's Office for the Prevention of Harassment and Discrimination
(OPHD), University of California President Janet Napolitano
approved a recommendation that Searle have his emeritus status revoked,
after a determination that he had violated university policies against
sexual harassment and retaliation between July and September 2016.
Awards and recognitions
Searle has five honorary-doctorate degrees from four countries and is an honorary visiting professor at Tsing Hua University and at East China Normal University.
In 2000, Searle received the Jean Nicod Prize; in 2004, the National Humanities Medal; and in 2006, the Mind & Brain Prize.
Philosophical work
Speech acts
Searle's early work, which did much to establish his reputation, was on speech acts. He attempted to synthesize ideas from many colleagues – including J.L. Austin (the "illocutionary act", from How To Do Things with Words), Ludwig Wittgenstein and G.C.J. Midgley (the distinction between regulative and constitutive rules) – with his own thesis that such acts are constituted by the rules of language. He also drew on the work of Paul Grice
(the analysis of meaning as an attempt at being understood), Hare and
Stenius (the distinction, concerning meaning, between illocutionary
force and propositional content), P.F. Strawson, John Rawls and William Alston,
who maintained that sentence meaning consists in sets of regulative
rules requiring the speaker to perform the illocutionary act indicated
by the sentence and that such acts involve the utterance of a sentence
which (a) indicates that one performs the act; (b) means what one says;
and (c) addresses an audience in the vicinity.
In his 1969 book Speech Acts, Searle sets out to combine all these elements to give his account of illocutionary acts.
There he provides an analysis of what he considers the prototypical
illocutionary act of promising and offers sets of semantical rules
intended to represent the linguistic meaning
of devices indicating further illocutionary act types. Among concepts
presented in the book is the distinction between the "illocutionary
force" and the "propositional content" of an utterance.
Searle does not precisely define the former as such, but rather
introduces several possible illocutionary forces by example. According
to Searle, the sentences...
- Sam smokes habitually.
- Does Sam smoke habitually?
- Sam, smoke habitually!
- Would that Sam smoked habitually!
... each indicate the same propositional content (Sam smoking
habitually) but differ in the illocutionary force indicated
(respectively, a statement, a question, a command and an expression of
desire).
According to a later account, which Searle presents in Intentionality (1983) and which differs in important ways from the one suggested in Speech Acts,
illocutionary acts are characterised by having "conditions of
satisfaction", an idea adopted from Strawson's 1971 paper "Meaning and
Truth", and a "direction of fit", an idea adopted from Austin and Elizabeth Anscombe.
For example, the statement "John bought two candy bars" is satisfied if
and only if it is true, i.e., John did buy two candy bars. By contrast,
the command "John, buy two candy bars!" is satisfied if and only if
John carries out the action of purchasing two candy bars. Searle refers
to the first as having the "word-to-world" direction of fit, since the
words are supposed to change to accurately represent the world, and the
second as having the "world-to-word" direction of fit, since the world
is supposed to change to match the words. There is also the double
direction of fit, in which the relationship goes both ways, and the null
or zero direction of fit, in which it goes neither way because the
propositional content is presupposed, as in "I am sorry I ate John's
candy bars."
In Foundations of Illocutionary Logic (1985, with Daniel Vanderveken), Searle prominently uses the notion of the "illocutionary point".
Searle's speech-act theory has been challenged by several
thinkers in various ways. Collections of articles referring to Searle's
account are found in Burkhardt 1990 and Lepore / van Gulick 1991.
Intentionality and the background
In Intentionality: An Essay in the Philosophy of Mind (1983), Searle applies the principles of his account(s) of illocutionary acts to the investigation of intentionality,
which is central to Searle's "Philosophy of Mind". (Searle is at pains
to emphasize that 'intentionality', the capacity of mental states to be about
worldly objects, is not to be confused with 'intensionality', the
referential opacity of contexts that fail tests for 'extensionality'.)
For Searle, intentionality is exclusively mental, being the power of minds to represent or symbolize over, things, properties and states of affairs in the external world.
Causal covariance, about-ness and the like are not enough: maps, for
instance, only have a 'derived' intentionality, a mere after-image of
the real thing.
Searle also introduces a technical term the Background,
which, according to him, has been the source of much philosophical
discussion ("though I have been arguing for this thesis for almost
twenty years," Searle writes, "many people whose opinions I respect still disagree with me about it"). He calls Background
the set of abilities, capacities, tendencies, and dispositions that
humans have that are not themselves intentional states but that generate
appropriate such states on demand.
Thus, when someone is asked to "cut the cake," they know to use a
knife and when someone is asked to "cut the grass," they know to use a
lawnmower (and not vice versa), even though the request did not mention
this. Beginning with the possibility of reversing these two, an endless
series of sceptical, anti-real or science-fiction interpretations could
be imagined. "I wish to say that there is a radical underdetermination of what is said by the literal meaning..." emphasizes Searle.
The Background fills the gap, being the capacity always to have a
suitable interpretation to hand. "I just take a huge metaphysics for
granted," he says. Searle sometimes supplements his reference to the Background with the concept of the Network,
one's network of other beliefs, desires, and other intentional states
necessary for any particular intentional state to make sense.
To give an example, two chess players might be engaged in a
bitter struggle at the board, but they share all sorts of Background
presuppositions: that they will take turns to move, that no one else
will intervene, that they are both playing to the same rules, that the
fire alarm will not go off, that the board will not suddenly
disintegrate, that their opponent will not magically turn into a
grapefruit, and so on indefinitely. As most of these possibilities will
not have occurred to either player, Searle thinks the Background is
itself unconscious as well as nonintentional.
To have a Background is to have a set of brain structures that generate
appropriate intentional states (if the fire alarm does go off, say).
"Those brain structures enable me to activate the system of
intentionality and to make it function, but the capacities realized in
the brain structures do not themselves consist in intentional states."
It seems to Searle that Hume and Nietzsche were probably the
first philosophers to appreciate, respectively, the centrality and
radical contingency of the Background. "Nietzsche saw, with anxiety,
that the Background does not have to be the way it is."
Searle also thinks that a Background appears in the ideas of other
modern thinkers: as the river-bed/substratum of Wittgenstein's On Certainty ("the work of the later Wittgenstein is in large part about the Background, especially On Certainty") and Pierre Bourdieu's habitus.
In his debate with Jacques Derrida, Searle argued against Derrida's
purported view that a statement can be disjoined from the original
intentionality of its author, for example when no longer connected to
the original author, while still being able to produce meaning. Searle
maintained that even if one was to see a written statement with no
knowledge of authorship it would still be impossible to escape the
question of intentionality, because "a meaningful sentence is just a
standing possibility of the (intentional) speech act". For Searle,
ascribing intentionality to a statement was a basic requirement for
attributing it any meaning at all.
In 2023 Pierre Jacob described Searle's view as "anti-intentionalist".
Consciousness
Building upon his views about intentionality, Searle presents a view concerning consciousness in his book The Rediscovery of the Mind
(1992). He argues that, starting with behaviorism, an early but
influential scientific view, succeeded by many later accounts that
Searle also dismisses, much of modern philosophy has tried to deny the
existence of consciousness, with little success. In Intentionality,
he parodies several alternative theories of consciousness by replacing
their accounts of intentionality with comparable accounts of the hand:
- No one would think of saying, for example, "Having a hand is
just being disposed to certain sorts of behavior such as grasping"
(manual behaviorism), or "Hands can be defined entirely in terms of their causes and effects" (manual functionalism),
or "For a system to have a hand is just for it to be in a certain
computer state with the right sorts of inputs and outputs" (manual Turing machine functionalism), or "Saying that a system has hands is just adopting a certain stance toward it" (the manual stance) (p. 263).
Searle argues that philosophy has been trapped by a false dichotomy:
that, on one hand, the world consists of nothing but objective
particles in fields of force, but that yet, on the other hand,
consciousness is clearly a subjective first-person experience.
Searle says simply that both are true: consciousness is a real
subjective experience, caused by the physical processes of the brain. (A
view which he suggests might be called biological naturalism.)
Ontological subjectivity
Searle has argued that critics like Daniel Dennett, who he claims insist that discussing subjectivity is unscientific because science presupposes objectivity, are making a category error. Perhaps the goal of science is to establish and validate statements which are epistemically objective, i.e., whose truth can be discovered and evaluated by any interested party, but are not necessarily ontologically objective.
Searle calls any value judgment epistemically subjective. Thus, "McKinley is prettier than Everest"
is "epistemically subjective", whereas "McKinley is higher than
Everest" is "epistemically objective". In other words, the latter
statement is evaluable, in fact, falsifiable, by an understood
('background') criterion for mountain height, like "the summit is so
many meters above sea level". No such criteria exist for prettiness.
Beyond this distinction, Searle thinks there are certain phenomena, including all conscious experiences, that are ontologically
subjective, i.e., can only exist as subjective experience. For example,
although it might be subjective or objective in the epistemic sense, a
doctor's note that a patient suffers from back pain is an ontologically objective claim: it counts as a medical diagnosis only because the existence of back pain is "an objective fact of medical science". The pain itself, however, is ontologically subjective: it is only experienced by the person having it.
Searle goes on to affirm that "where consciousness is concerned, the existence of the appearance is the reality".
His view that the epistemic and ontological senses of
objective/subjective are cleanly separable is crucial to his
self-proclaimed biological naturalism,
because it allows epistemically objective judgments like "That object
is a pocket calculator" to pick out agent-relative features of objects,
and such features are, on his terms, ontologically subjective, unlike,
say, "That object is made mostly of plastic".
Artificial intelligence
A consequence of biological naturalism is that if humans want to
create a conscious being, they will have to duplicate whatever physical
processes the brain goes through to cause consciousness. Searle thereby
means to contradict what he calls "Strong AI",
defined by the assumption that as soon as a certain kind of software is
running on a computer, a conscious being is thereby created.
In 1980, Searle presented the "Chinese room" argument, which purports to prove the falsity of strong AI.
A person is in a room with two slits, and they have a book and some
scratch paper. This person does not know any Chinese. Someone outside
the room slides some Chinese characters in through the first slit; the
person in the room follows the instructions in the book, transcribing
the characters as instructed onto the scratch paper, and slides the
resulting sheet out by the second slit. To people outside the room, it
appears that the room speaks Chinese – they have slid Chinese statements
into one slit and got valid responses in English – yet the 'room' does
not understand a word of Chinese. This suggests, according to Searle,
that no computer can ever understand Chinese or English, because, as the
thought experiment
suggests, being able to 'translate' Chinese into English does not
entail 'understanding' either Chinese or English: all that the person in
the thought experiment, and hence a computer, is able to do is to
execute certain syntactic manipulations. Douglas Hofstadter and Daniel Dennett in their book The Mind's I criticize Searle's view of AI, particularly the Chinese room argument.
Stevan Harnad argues that Searle's "Strong AI" is really just another name for functionalism and computationalism, and that these positions are the real targets of his critique.
Functionalists argue that consciousness can be defined as a set of
informational processes inside the brain. It follows that anything that
carries out the same informational processes as a human is also
conscious. Thus, if humans wrote a computer program that was conscious,
they could run that computer program on, say, a system of ping-pong
balls and beer cups and the system would be equally conscious, because
it was running the same information processes.
Searle argues that this is impossible, since consciousness is a
physical property, like digestion or fire. No matter how good a
simulation of digestion is built on the computer, it will not digest
anything; no matter how well it simulates fire, nothing will get burnt.
By contrast, informational processes are observer-relative:
observers pick out certain patterns in the world and consider them
information processes, but information processes are not
things-in-the-world themselves. Since they do not exist at a physical
level, Searle argues, they cannot have causal efficacy and thus
cannot cause consciousness. There is no physical law, Searle insists,
that can see the equivalence between a personal computer, a series of
ping-pong balls and beer cans, and a pipe-and-water system all
implementing the same program.
Social reality
Searle
extended his inquiries into observer-relative phenomena by trying to
understand social reality. Searle begins by arguing collective
intentionality (e.g., "we are going for a walk") is a distinct form of
intentionality, not simply reducible to individual intentionality (e.g.,
"I am going for a walk with him and I think he thinks he is going for a
walk with me and he thinks I think I am going for a walk with him
and...")
In The Construction of Social Reality (1995), Searle
addresses the mystery of how social constructs like "baseball" or
"money" can exist in a world consisting only of physical particles in
fields of force. Adapting an idea by Elizabeth Anscombe in "On Brute Facts", Searle distinguishes between brute facts, like the height of a mountain, and institutional facts,
like the score of a baseball game. Aiming at an explanation of social
phenomena in terms of Anscombe's notion, he argues that society can be
explained in terms of institutional facts, and institutional facts arise
out of collective intentionality through constitutive rules with the
logical form "X counts as Y in C". Thus, for instance, filling out a
ballot counts as a vote in a polling place, getting so many votes counts
as a victory in an election, getting a victory counts as being elected
president in the presidential race, etc.
Many sociologists, however, do not see Searle's contributions to social theory as very significant. Neil Gross, for example, argues that Searle's views on society are more or less a reconstitution of the sociologist Émile Durkheim's
theories of social facts, social institutions, collective
representations, and the like. Searle's ideas are thus open to the same
criticisms as Durkheim's.
Searle responded that Durkheim's work was worse than he had originally
believed and, admitting he had not read much of Durkheim's work, said:
"Because Durkheim's account seemed so impoverished I did not read any
further in his work." Steven Lukes,
however, responded to Searle's response to Gross and argued point by
point against the allegations that Searle makes against Durkheim,
essentially upholding Gross's argument that Searle's work bears a great
resemblance to Durkheim's. Lukes attributes Searle's miscomprehension of
Durkheim's work to the fact that Searle had never read Durkheim.
Searle–Lawson debate
In recent years, Searle's main interlocutor on issues of social ontology has been Tony Lawson.
Although their accounts of social reality are similar, there are
important differences. Lawson emphasizes the notion of social totality
whereas Searle prefers to refer to institutional facts. Furthermore,
Searle believes that emergence implies causal reduction whereas Lawson
argues that social totalities cannot be completely explained by the
causal powers of their components. Searle also places language at the
foundation of the construction of social reality, while Lawson believes
that community formation necessarily precedes the development of
language and, therefore, there must be the possibility for
non-linguistic social structure formation. The debate is ongoing and takes place additionally through regular meetings of the Centre for Social Ontology at the University of California, Berkeley and the Cambridge Social Ontology Group at the University of Cambridge.
Rationality
In Rationality in Action
(2001), Searle argues that standard notions of rationality are badly
flawed. According to what he calls the Classical Model, rationality is
seen as something like a train track: a person moves onto it at one
point with their beliefs and desires, and then the rules of rationality
compel them all the way to a conclusion. Searle doubts that this picture
of rationality holds generally.
Searle briefly critiques one particular set of these rules: those of mathematical decision theory.
He points out that its axioms require that anyone who valued a quarter
and their life would, at some odds, bet their life for a quarter. Searle
insists he would never take such a bet and believes that this stance is
perfectly rational.
Most of his attack is directed against the common conception of
rationality, which he believes is badly flawed. First, he argues that
reasons does not cause an individual to do anything, because having
sufficient reason wills, but does not force, them to do
that thing. Therefore, in any decision situation, people experience a
gap between reasons and actions. For example, when a person decides to
vote, they may determine that they care most about economic policy and
that they prefer candidate Jones's economic policy, but they must also
make an effort to actually cast a vote. Similarly, every time a smoker
who feels guilty about their action lights a cigarette, they are aware
that they are succumbing to their craving, and not merely acting
automatically as they do when they exhale. This gap makes people think
they have freedom of the will. Searle thinks that whether one really has free will
or not is an open question, but considers its absence highly
unappealing because it makes the feeling of freedom of will an
epiphenomenon, which is highly unlikely from the evolutionary point of
view given its biological cost. He also says, "All rational activity
presupposes free will".
Second, Searle believes that people can rationally do things that do
not result from their own desires. It is widely believed that one cannot
derive an "ought" from an "is", i.e., that facts about how the world is
can never tell a person what they should do (Hume's Law).
By contrast, insofar as a fact is understood to relate to an
institution (marriage, promises, commitments, etc.), which is to be
understood as a system of constitutive rules, then what one should do
can be understood as following from the institutional fact of what one
has done; institutional fact, then, can be understood as opposed to the
"brute facts" related to Hume's Law. For example, Searle believes that
the promise of doing something means that one must do it, because by
making the promise one participates in the constitutive rules that
arrange the system of promise-making itself; a "shouldness" is implicit
in the mere factual action of promising. Furthermore, he believes that
this provides a desire-independent reason for an action – if one orders a
drink at a bar, there is an obligation to pay for it even if one has no
desire to do so. This argument, which he first made in his paper, "How
to Derive 'Ought' from 'Is'" (1964),
remains highly controversial, but Searle maintained that "the
traditional metaphysical distinction between fact and value cannot be
captured by the linguistic distinction between 'evaluative' and
'descriptive' because all such speech act notions are already
normative".
Third, Searle argues that much of rational deliberation involves
adjusting patterns of desires, which are often inconsistent, to decide
between outcomes, not the other way around. While in the Classical Model
one would start from viewing a desire to go to Paris as a greater
factor than saving money, which would lead to calculating the cheapest
way to get there, Searle would argue that people balance the desire of
Paris against the desire to save money to determine which one they value
more. Hence, he believes that rationality is not a system of rules, but
more of an adverb. Certain behaviors are seen as rational, no matter
what their source, and a system of rules derives from finding patterns
in what is considered rational.