Neoplatonism is a strand of Platonic philosophy that emerged in the third century AD against the background of Hellenistic philosophy and religion. The term does not encapsulate a set of ideas as much as it encapsulates a chain of thinkers which began with Ammonius Saccas and his student Plotinus (c. 204/5
– 270 AD) and which stretches to the sixth century AD. Even though
neoplatonism primarily circumscribes the thinkers who are now labeled
Neoplatonists and not their ideas, there are some ideas that are common
to neoplatonic systems, for example, the monistic idea that all of reality can be derived from a single principle, "the One".
After Plotinus there were three distinct periods in the history of neoplatonism: the work of his student Porphyry (third to early fourth century); that of Iamblichus
(third to fourth century) and that school's later continuation in
Syria; and the period in the fifth and sixth centuries, when the
Academies in Alexandria and Athens flourished.
Neoplatonism had an enduring influence on the subsequent history of philosophy. In the Middle Ages, neoplatonic ideas were studied and discussed by Muslim, Christian, and Jewish
thinkers. In the Islamic cultural sphere, neoplatonic texts were
available in Arabic and Persian translations, and notable thinkers such
as al-Farabi, Solomon ibn Gabirol (Avicebron), Avicenna, and Moses Maimonides incorporated neoplatonic elements into their own thinking. Thomas Aquinas had direct access to works by Proclus, Simplicius and Pseudo-Dionysius the Areopagite, and he knew about other Neoplatonists, such as Plotinus and Porphyry, through secondhand sources. The mystic Meister Eckhart
(c. 1260 – c. 1328) was also influenced by neoplatonism, propagating a
contemplative way of life which points to the Godhead beyond the
nameable God.
Neoplatonism also had a strong influence on the Perennial philosophy of the Italian Renaissance thinkers Marsilio Ficino and Pico della Mirandola, and continues through nineteenth-century Universalism and modern-day spirituality and nondualism.
Origins of the term
Neoplatonism is a modern term. The term neoplatonism has a double function as a historical category. On the one hand, it differentiates the philosophical doctrines of Plotinus and his successors from those of the historical Plato.
On the other, the term makes an assumption about the novelty of
Plotinus's interpretation of Plato. In the nearly six centuries from
Plato's time to Plotinus', there had been an uninterrupted tradition of
interpreting Plato which had begun with Aristotle and with the immediate successors of Plato's academy and continued on through a period of Platonism which is now referred to as Middle Platonism. The term neoplatonism
implies that Plotinus' interpretation of Plato was so distinct from
those of his predecessors that it should be thought to introduce a new
period in the history of Platonism. Some contemporary scholars, however,
have taken issue with this assumption and have doubted that neoplatonism
constitutes a useful label. They claim that merely marginal differences
separate Plotinus' teachings from those of his immediate predecessors.
Whether neoplatonism is a meaningful or useful historical
category is itself a central question concerning the history of the
interpretation of Plato. For much of the history of Platonism, it was
commonly accepted that the doctrines of the neoplatonists were
essentially the same as those of Plato. The Renaissance Platonist Marsilio Ficino,
for instance, thought that the neoplatonic interpretation of Plato was
an authentic and accurate representation of Plato's philosophy.
Although it is unclear precisely when scholars began to disassociate
the philosophy of the historical Plato from the philosophy of his
neoplatonic interpreters, they had clearly begun to do so at least as
early as the first decade of the nineteenth century. Contemporary
scholars often identify the German theologian Friedrich Schleiermacher
as an early thinker who took Plato's philosophy to be separate from
that of his neoplatonic interpreters. However, others have argued that
the differentiation of Plato from neoplatonism was the result of a
protracted historical development that preceded Schleiermacher's
scholarly work on Plato.
Origins and history of classical neoplatonism
Neoplatonism started with Plotinus in the third century. Three distinct phases in classical neoplatonism after Plotinus can be distinguished: the work of his student Porphyry; that of Iamblichus and his school in Syria; and the period in the fifth and sixth centuries, when the Academies in Alexandria and Athens flourished.
Hellenism
Neoplatonism
synthesized ideas from various philosophical and religious cultural
spheres. The most important forerunners from Greek philosophy were the Middle Platonists, such as Plutarch, and the neopythagoreans, especially Numenius of Apamea. Philo, a Hellenized Jew, translated Judaism into terms of Stoic, Platonic
and neopythagorean elements, and held that God is "supra rational" and
can be reached only through "ecstasy". Philo also held that the oracles of God supply the material of moral and religious knowledge. The earliest Christian philosophers, such as Justin and Athenagoras, who attempted to connect Christianity with Platonism, and the Christian Gnostics of Alexandria, especially Valentinus and the followers of Basilides, also mirrored elements of neoplatonism, albeit without its rigorous self-consistency.
Saccas
Ammonius Saccas (died c. AD 265;
Greek: Ἀμμώνιος Σακκᾶς) was a teacher of Plotinus. Through Ammonius
Saccas, Plotinus may have been influenced by Indian thought. The
similarities between neoplatonism and the Vedanta philosophies of Hinduism have led several authors to suggest an Indian influence in its founding, particularly on Ammonius Saccas.
Both Christians (see Eusebius, Jerome, and Origen) and pagans (see Porphyry and Plotinus) claimed him a teacher and founder of the neoplatonic system. Porphyry stated in On the One School of Plato and Aristotle, that Ammonius' view was that the philosophies of Plato and Aristotle were in harmony. Eusebius and Jerome
claimed him as a Christian until his death, whereas Porphyry claimed he
had renounced Christianity and embraced pagan philosophy.
Plotinus
Plotinus (c. 205 – c. 270; Greek: Πλωτῖνος), born in upper Egypt, was a major Egyptian
philosopher of the ancient world who is widely considered the father of
neoplatonism. Much of our biographical information about him comes from
Porphyry's preface to his edition of Plotinus' Enneads. While he was himself influenced by the teachings of classical Greek, Persian and Indian philosophy and Egyptian theology, his metaphysical writings later inspired numerous Christian, Jewish, Islamic and Gnostic metaphysicians and mystics over the centuries.
Plotinus taught that there is a supreme, totally transcendent
"One", containing no division, multiplicity, nor distinction; likewise,
it is beyond all categories of being and non-being. The concept of
"being" is derived by us from the objects of human experience and is an
attribute of such objects, but the infinite, transcendent One is beyond
all such objects and, therefore, is beyond the concepts which we can
derive from them. The One "cannot be any existing thing" and cannot be
merely the sum of all such things (compare the Stoic doctrine of
disbelief in non-material existence) but "is prior to all existents".
Porphyry
Porphyry (Greek: Πορφύριος, c. 233–c. 309) was a Syrian
neoplatonist philosopher. He wrote widely on astrology, religion,
philosophy, and musical theory. He produced a biography of his teacher,
Plotinus. He is important in the history of mathematics because of his
Life of Pythagoras and his commentary on Euclid's Elements, which Pappus
used when he wrote his own commentary. Porphyry is also known as an
opponent of Christianity and as a defender of Paganism; of his Adversus
Christianos (Against the Christians) in 15 books, only fragments remain.
He famously said, "The gods have proclaimed Christ to have been most
pious, but the Christians are a confused and vicious sect."
Iamblichus
Iamblichus, also known as Iamblichus Chalcidensis (c. 245 – c. 325; Greek: Ἰάμβλιχος), was a Syrian
neoplatonist philosopher who influenced the direction taken by later
neoplatonic philosophy. He is perhaps best known for his compendium on
Pythagorean philosophy.
In Iamblichus' system, the realm of divinities stretched from the
original One down to material nature itself, where soul, in fact,
descended into matter and became "embodied" as human beings. The world
is thus peopled by a crowd of superhuman beings influencing natural
events and possessing and communicating knowledge of the future, and who
are all accessible to prayers and offerings.
Iamblichus had salvation as his final goal (see henosis). The embodied soul was to return to divinity by performing certain rites, or theurgy, literally, 'divine-working'.
Academies
After Plotinus' (around 205–270) and his student Porphyry (around 232–309) Aristotle's (non-biological) works entered the curriculum of Platonic thought. Porphyry's introduction (Isagoge) to Aristotle's Categoria was important as an introduction to logic, and the study of Aristotle became an introduction to the study of Plato in the late Platonism of Athens and Alexandria. The commentaries of this group seek to harmonise Plato, Aristotle, and, often, the Stoa. Some works of neoplatonism were attributed to Plato or Aristotle. De Mundo, for instance, is thought not to be the work of a 'pseudo-Aristotle' though this remains debatable.
Hypatia (c. 360 –
415) was a Greek philosopher and mathematician who served as head of
the Platonist school in Alexandria, Egypt, where she taught philosophy,
mathematics and astronomy prior to her murder by a fanatical mob of Coptic Parabalani monks because she had been advising the Christian prefect of Egypt Orestes during his feud with Cyril, Alexandria's dynastic archbishop. The extent of Cyril's personal involvement in her murder remains a matter of scholarly debate.
Proclus
Lycaeus (February 8, 412 – April 17, 485), surnamed "The Successor" or
"diadochos" (Greek Πρόκλος ὁ Διάδοχος Próklos ho Diádokhos), was a Greek
neoplatonist philosopher, one of the last major Greek philosophers (see
Damascius). He set forth one of the most elaborate, complex, and fully
developed neoplatonic systems, providing also an allegorical way of
reading the dialogues of Plato. The particular characteristic of
Proclus' system is his insertion of a level of individual ones, called
henads between the One itself and the divine Intellect, which is the
second principle. The henads are beyond being, like the One itself, but
they stand at the head of chains of causation (seirai or taxeis) and in
some manner give to these chains their particular character. They are
also identified with the traditional Greek gods, so one henad might be
Apollo and be the cause of all things apollonian, while another might be
Helios and be the cause of all sunny things. The henads serve both to
protect the One itself from any hint of multiplicity and to draw up the
rest of the universe towards the One, by being a connecting,
intermediate stage between absolute unity and determinate multiplicity.
Ideas
The Enneads of Plotinus
are the primary and classical document of neoplatonism. As a form of
mysticism, it contains theoretical and practical parts. The theoretical
parts deal with the high origin of the human soul,
showing how it has departed from its first estate. The practical parts
show the way by which the soul may again return to the Eternal and
Supreme. The system can be divided between the invisible world and the phenomenal world, the former containing the transcendent One from which emanates an eternal, perfect, essence (nous, or intellect), which, in turn, produces the world-soul.
The One
For
Plotinus, the first principle of reality is "the One", an utterly
simple, ineffable, unknowable subsistence which is both the creative
source and the teleological
end of all existing things. Although, properly speaking, there is no
name appropriate for the first principle, the most adequate names are
"the One" or "the Good". The One is so simple that it cannot even be
said to exist or to be a being. Rather, the creative principle of all
things is beyond being, a notion which is derived from Book VI of the Republic, when, in the course of his famous analogy of the sun, Plato says that the Good is beyond being (ἐπέκεινα τῆς οὐσίας) in power and dignity. In Plotinus' model of reality, the One is the cause of the rest of reality, which takes the form of two subsequent "hypostases"
or substances: Nous and Soul. Although neoplatonists after Plotinus
adhered to his cosmological scheme in its most general outline, later
developments in the tradition also departed substantively from Plotinus'
teachings in regards to significant philosophical issues, such as the
nature of evil.
Emanations
From the One emanated the rest of the universe as a sequence of lesser beings.
Demiurge or Nous
The original Being initially emanates, or throws out, the nous,
which is a perfect image of the One and the archetype of all existing
things. It is simultaneously both being and thought, idea and ideal
world. As image, the nous corresponds perfectly to the One, but as derivative, it is entirely different. What Plotinus understands by the nous is the highest sphere accessible to the human mind, while also being pure intellect itself. Nous is the most critical component of idealism, Neoplatonism being a pure form of idealism. The demiurge (the nous) is the energy, or ergon (does the work), which manifests or organises the material world into perceivability.
The world-soul
The image and product of the motionless nous is the world-soul, which, according to Plotinus, is immaterial like the nous. Its relation to the nous is the same as that of the nous to the One. It stands between the nous and the phenomenal world, and it is permeated and illuminated by the former, but it is also in contact with the latter. The nous/spirit is indivisible; the world-soul may preserve its unity and remain in the nous,
but, at the same time, it has the power of uniting with the corporeal
world and thus being disintegrated. It therefore occupies an
intermediate position. As a single world-soul, it belongs in essence and
destination to the intelligible world; but it also embraces innumerable
individual souls; and these can either allow themselves to be informed
by the nous, or turn aside from the nous and choose the phenomenal world and lose themselves in the realm of the senses and the finite.
The phenomenal world
The
soul, as a moving essence, generates the corporeal or phenomenal world.
This world ought to be so pervaded by the soul that its various parts
should remain in perfect harmony. Plotinus is no dualist in the same
sense as sects like the Gnostics;
in contrast, he admires the beauty and splendour of the world. So long
as idea governs matter, or the soul governs the body, the world is fair
and good. It is an image – though a shadowy image – of the upper world,
and the degrees of better and worse in it are essential to the harmony
of the whole. But, in the actual phenomenal world, unity and harmony are
replaced by strife or discord; the result is a conflict, a becoming
and vanishing, an illusive existence. And the reason for this state of
things is that bodies rest on a substratum of matter. Matter is the
indeterminate: that with no qualities. If destitute of form and idea, it
is evil; as capable of form, it is neutral.
Evil here is understood as a parasite, having no-existence of its own
(parahypostasis), an unavoidable outcome of the Universe, having an
"other" necessity, as a harmonizing factor.
Celestial hierarchy
Later neoplatonic philosophers, especially Iamblichus,
added hundreds of intermediate beings such as gods, angels, demons, and
other beings as mediators between the One and humanity. The
neoplatonist gods are omni-perfect beings and do not display the usual
amoral behaviour associated with their representations in the myths.
- The One: God, The Good. Transcendent and ineffable.
- The Hypercosmic Gods: those that make Essence, Life, and Soul
- The Demiurge: the Creator
- The Cosmic Gods: those who make Being, Nature, and Matter—including the gods known to us from classical religion.
Evil
Neoplatonists did not believe in an independent existence of evil.
They compared it to darkness, which does not exist in itself but only
as the absence of light. So, too, evil is simply the absence of good.
Things are good insofar as they exist; they are evil only insofar as
they are imperfect, lacking some good which they should have.
Return to the One
Neoplatonists believed human perfection and happiness were attainable in this world, without awaiting an afterlife. Perfection and happiness—seen as synonymous—could be achieved through philosophical contemplation.
All people return to the One, from which they emanated.
The neoplatonists believed in the pre-existence, and immortality of the soul. The human soul consists of a lower irrational soul and a higher rational soul (mind), both of which can be regarded as different powers of the one soul. It was widely held that the soul possesses a "vehicle", accounting for the human soul's immortality and allowing for its return to the One after death. After bodily death, the soul takes up a level in the afterlife corresponding with the level at which it lived during its earthly life. The neoplatonists believed in the principle of reincarnation. Although the most pure and holy souls would dwell in the highest regions, the impure soul would undergo a purification, before descending again, to be reincarnated into a new body, perhaps into animal form.
Plotinus believed that a soul may be reincarnated into another human or
even a different sort of animal. However, Porphyry maintained, instead,
that human souls were only reincarnated into other humans. A soul which has returned to the One achieves union with the cosmic universal soul and does not descend again; at least, not in this world period.
Influence
Early Christianity
Augustine
Certain central tenets of neoplatonism served as a philosophical interim for the Christian theologian Augustine of Hippo on his journey from dualistic Manichaeism to Christianity.
As a Manichee hearer, Augustine had held that evil has substantial
being and that God is made of matter; when he became a neoplatonist, he
changed his views on these things. As a neoplatonist, and later a
Christian, Augustine believed that evil is a privation of good and that God is not material. When writing his treatise 'On True Religion' several years after his 387 baptism, Augustine's Christianity was still tempered by neoplatonism.
The term "Logos" was interpreted variously in neoplatonism. Plotinus refers to Thales in interpreting Logos as the principle of meditation, the interrelationship between the Hypostases (Soul, Spirit (nous) and the 'One'). St. John introduces a relation between 'Logos' and the Son, Christ, whereas St. Paul calls it 'Son', 'Image', and 'Form'. Victorinus subsequently differentiated the Logos interior to God from the Logos related to the world by creation and salvation.
For Augustine, the Logos "took on flesh" in Christ, in whom the Logos was present as in no other man. He strongly influenced Early Medieval Christian Philosophy. Perhaps the key subject in this was Logos.
Origen and Pseudo-Dionysius
Some early Christians, influenced by neoplatonism, identified the Neoplatonic One, or God, with Yahweh. The most influential of these would be Origen, the pupil of Ammonius Saccas; and the sixth-century author known as Pseudo-Dionysius the Areopagite, whose works were translated by John Scotus in the ninth century for the West. Both authors had a lasting influence on Eastern Orthodox and Western Christianity, and the development of contemplative and mystical practices and theology.
Gnosticism
Neoplatonism also had links with Gnosticism, which Plotinus rebuked in his ninth tractate of the second Enneads:
"Against Those That Affirm The Creator of The Cosmos and The Cosmos
Itself to Be Evil" (generally known as "Against The Gnostics").
Due to their belief being grounded in Platonic thought, the neoplatonists rejected Gnosticism's vilification of Plato's demiurge, the creator of the material world or cosmos discussed in the Timaeus. Neoplatonism has been referred to as orthodox Platonic philosophy by scholars like John D. Turner;
this reference may be due, in part, to Plotinus' attempt to refute
certain interpretations of Platonic philosophy, through his Enneads. Plotinus believed the followers of Gnosticism had corrupted the original teachings of Plato and often argued against likes of Valentinus who, according to Plotinus, had given rise to doctrines of dogmatic theology with ideas such as that the Spirit of Christ was brought forth by a conscious god after the fall from Pleroma. According to Plotinus, The One is not a conscious god with intent nor a godhead
nor a conditioned existing entity of any kind, rather a requisite
principle of totality which is also the source of ultimate wisdom.
Byzantine education
After the Platonic Academy was destroyed in the first century BC, philosophers continued to teach Platonism,
but it was not until the early 5th century (c. 410) that a revived
academy (which had no connection with the original Academy) was
established in Athens by some leading Neoplatonists. It persisted until 529 AD when it was finally closed by Justinian I because of active paganism of its professors. Other schools continued in Constantinople, Antioch and Alexandria which were the centers of Justinian's empire.
After the closure of the Neoplatonic academy, neoplatonic and/or
secular philosophical studies continued in publicly funded schools in
Alexandria. In the early seventh century, the neoplatonist Stephanus
brought this Alexandrian tradition to Constantinople, where it would
remain influential, albeit as a form of secular education. The university maintained an active philosophical tradition of Platonism and Aristotelianism, with the former being the longest unbroken Platonic school, running for close to two millennia until the fifteenth century
Michael Psellos (1018–1078) a Byzantine monk, writer, philosopher, politician, and historian. He wrote many philosophical treatises such as De omnifaria doctrina. He wrote most of his philosophy during his time as a court politician at Constantinople in the 1030s and 1040s.
Gemistus Pletho (c. 1355 –
1452; Greek: Πλήθων Γεμιστός) remained the preeminent scholar of
neoplatonic philosophy in the late Byzantine Empire. He introduced his
understanding and insight into the works of neoplatonism during the
failed attempt to reconcile the East–West Schism at the council of Florence. At Florence, Pletho met Cosimo de' Medici and influenced the latter's decision to found a new Platonic Academy there. Cosimo subsequently appointed as head Marsilio Ficino, who proceeded to translate all Plato's works, the Enneads of Plotinus, and various other neoplatonist works into Latin.
Islamic neoplatonism
There were three major reasons for the prominence of neoplatonic influences in the historical Muslim world:
- Availability of neoplatonic texts: Arabic translations and paraphrases of neoplatonic works were readily available to Islamic scholars greatly due to the availability of the Greek copies, in part, because Muslims came to rule over some of the more important centres of Greek civilisation (Egypt and Syria).
- Spatial and temporal proximity: "Plotinus and other Neoplatonists lived only a few centuries before the rise of Islam, and many of them were Egyptian Greeks."
- Neoplatonism's mystical perspectives: Plotinus' system has similar content to Islamic mysticism, like Sufism. This eased the acceptance of neoplatonic doctrines by Islamic philosophers.
Various Arabic scholars and philosophers, including Avicenna (Ibn Sina), Ibn Arabi, al-Kindi, al-Farabi, and al-Himsi, adapted neoplatonism to conform to the monotheistic constraints of Islam.
The translations of the works which extrapolate the tenets of God in
neoplatonism present no major modification from their original Greek
sources, showing the doctrinal shift towards monotheism. Islamic adapted the concepts of the One and the First Principle to Islamic theology, attributing the First Principle to God. God is a transcendent being, omnipresent and inalterable to the effects of creation. Islamic philosophers used the framework of Islamic mysticism in their interpretation of Neoplatonic writings and concepts.
The translation and interpretation of Islamic neoplatonists had lasting effects on Western philosophers, affecting Descartes' view on the conception of being.
Jewish thought
In the Middle Ages, neoplatonist ideas influenced Jewish thinkers, such as the Kabbalist Isaac the Blind, and the Jewish neoplatonic philosopher Solomon ibn Gabirol (Avicebron), who modified it in the light of their own monotheism. Neoplatonist ideas also influenced Islamic and Sufi thinkers such as al Farabi and Avicenna.
Western mysticism
The works of Pseudo-Dionysius were instrumental in the flowering of western medieval mysticism, most notably Meister Eckhart.
Western Renaissance
Neoplatonism ostensibly survived in the Eastern Christian Church as
an independent tradition and was reintroduced to the West by Pletho (c. 1355 –
1452/1454), an avowed pagan and opponent of the Byzantine Church,
inasmuch as the latter, under Western scholastic influence, relied
heavily upon Aristotelian methodology. Plethon's
Platonic revival, following the Council of Florence (1438–1439),
largely accounts for the renewed interest in Platonic philosophy which
accompanied the Renaissance.
"Of all the students of Greek in Renaissance Italy, the
best-known are the Neoplatonists who studied in and around Florence"
(Hole). Neoplatonism was not just a revival of Plato's ideas, it is all
based on Plotinus' created synthesis, which incorporated the works and
teachings of Plato, Aristotle, Pythagoras, and other Greek philosophers.
The Renaissance in Italy was the revival of classic antiquity, and this
started at the fall of the Byzantine empire, who were considered the
"librarians of the world", because of their great collection of
classical manuscripts and the number of humanist scholars that resided
in Constantinople (Hole).
Neoplatonism in the Renaissance combined the ideas of Christianity and a new awareness of the writings of Plato.
Marsilio Ficino
(1433–99) was "chiefly responsible for packaging and presenting Plato
to the Renaissance" (Hole). In 1462, Cosimo I de' Medici, patron of
arts, who had an interest in humanism and Platonism, provided Ficino
with all 36 of Plato's dialogues in Greek for him to translate. Between
1462 and 1469, Ficino translated these works into Latin, making them
widely accessible, as only a minority of people could read Greek. And,
between 1484 and 1492, he translated the works of Plotinus, making them
available for the first time to the West.
Giovanni Pico della Mirandola
(1463–94) was another excelling neoplatonist during the Italian
Renaissance. He could not only speak and write in Latin and Greek, but
he also had immense knowledge on the Hebrew and Arabic languages. The
pope banned his works because they were viewed as heretical – unlike
Ficino, who managed to stay on the right side of the church.
The efforts of Ficino and Pico to introduce neoplatonic and
Hermetic doctrines into the teaching of the Roman Catholic Church has
recently been evaluated in terms of an attempted "Hermetic Reformation".
Cambridge Platonists (17th century)
In the seventeenth century in England, neoplatonism was fundamental to the school of the Cambridge Platonists, whose luminaries included Henry More, Ralph Cudworth, Benjamin Whichcote and John Smith, all graduates of the University of Cambridge. Coleridge claimed that they were not really Platonists, but "more truly Plotinists": "divine Plotinus", as More called him.
Later, Thomas Taylor (not a Cambridge Platonist) was the first to translate Plotinus' works into English.
Modern neoplatonism
Notable modern neoplatonists include Thomas Taylor,
"the English Platonist", who wrote extensively on Platonism and
translated almost the entire Platonic and Plotinian corpora into
English, and the Belgian writer Suzanne Lilar.
The science fiction writer Philip K. Dick
identified as a Neoplatonist and explores related mystical experiences
and religious concepts in his theoretical work, compiled in The Exegesis of Philip K. Dick.