From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
Relativism is a family of philosophical views which deny claims to objectivity
within a particular domain and assert that facts in that domain are
relative to the perspective of an observer or the context in which they
are assessed.
There are many different forms of relativism, with a great deal of
variation in scope and differing degrees of controversy among them. Moral relativism encompasses the differences in moral judgments among people and cultures. Epistemic relativism holds that there are no absolute facts regarding norms of belief, justification, or rationality, and that there are only relative ones. Alethic relativism is the doctrine that there are no absolute truths, i.e., that truth is always relative to some particular frame of reference, such as a language or a culture (cultural relativism). Some forms of relativism also bear a resemblance to philosophical skepticism. Descriptive relativism
seeks to describe the differences among cultures and people without
evaluation, while normative relativism evaluates the morality or
truthfulness of views within a given framework.
Forms of relativism
Anthropological versus philosophical relativism
Anthropological relativism refers to a methodological
stance, in which the researcher suspends (or brackets) his or her own
cultural prejudice while trying to understand beliefs or behaviors in
their contexts. This has become known as methodological relativism, and concerns itself specifically with avoiding ethnocentrism or the application of one's own cultural standards to the assessment of other cultures. This is also the basis of the so-called "emic" and "etic" distinction, in which:
- An emic or insider account of behavior is a
description of a society in terms that are meaningful to the participant
or actor's own culture; an emic account is therefore culture-specific,
and typically refers to what is considered "common sense" within the culture under observation.
- An etic or outsider account is a description of a society by
an observer, in terms that can be applied to other cultures; that is, an
etic account is culturally neutral, and typically refers to the
conceptual framework of the social scientist. (This is complicated when
it is scientific research itself that is under study, or when there is
theoretical or terminological disagreement within the social sciences.)
Philosophical relativism, in contrast, asserts that the truth of a
proposition depends on the metaphysical, or theoretical frame, or the
instrumental method, or the context in which the proposition is
expressed, or on the person, groups, or culture who interpret the
proposition.
Methodological relativism and philosophical relativism can exist
independently from one another, but most anthropologists base their
methodological relativism on that of the philosophical variety.
Descriptive versus normative relativism
The concept of relativism also has importance both for philosophers and for anthropologists
in another way. In general, anthropologists engage in descriptive
relativism ("how things are" or "how things seem"), whereas philosophers
engage in normative
relativism ("how things ought to be"), although there is some overlap
(for example, descriptive relativism can pertain to concepts, normative
relativism to truth).
Descriptive relativism assumes that certain cultural groups have
different modes of thought, standards of reasoning, and so forth, and it
is the anthropologist's task to describe, but not to evaluate the
validity of these principles and practices of a cultural group. It is
possible for an anthropologist in his or her fieldwork to be a
descriptive relativist about some things that typically concern the
philosopher (e.g., ethical principles) but not about others (e.g.,
logical principles). However, the descriptive relativist's empirical
claims about epistemic principles, moral ideals and the like are often
countered by anthropological arguments that such things are universal,
and much of the recent literature on these matters is explicitly
concerned with the extent of, and evidence for, cultural or moral or
linguistic or human universals.
The fact that the various species of descriptive relativism are
empirical claims, may tempt the philosopher to conclude that they are of
little philosophical interest, but there are several reasons why this
isn't so. First, some philosophers, notably Kant, argue that certain
sorts of cognitive differences between human beings (or even all
rational beings) are impossible, so such differences could never be
found to obtain in fact, an argument that places a priori limits on what
empirical inquiry could discover and on what versions of descriptive
relativism could be true. Second, claims about actual differences
between groups play a central role in some arguments for normative
relativism (for example, arguments for normative ethical relativism
often begin with claims that different groups in fact have different
moral codes or ideals). Finally, the anthropologist's descriptive
account of relativism helps to separate the fixed aspects of human
nature from those that can vary, and so a descriptive claim that some
important aspect of experience or thought does (or does not) vary across
groups of human beings tells us something important about human nature
and the human condition.
Normative relativism concerns normative or evaluative
claims that modes of thought, standards of reasoning, or the like are
only right or wrong relative to a framework. ‘Normative’ is meant in a
general sense, applying to a wide range of views; in the case of
beliefs, for example, normative correctness equals truth. This does not
mean, of course, that framework-relative correctness or truth is always
clear, the first challenge being to explain what it amounts to in any
given case (e.g., with respect to concepts, truth, epistemic norms).
Normative relativism (say, in regard to normative ethical relativism)
therefore implies that things (say, ethical claims) are not simply true
in themselves, but only have truth values
relative to broader frameworks (say, moral codes). (Many normative
ethical relativist arguments run from premises about ethics to
conclusions that assert the relativity of truth values, bypassing
general claims about the nature of truth, but it is often more
illuminating to consider the type of relativism under question
directly.)
Related and contrasting positions
Relationism
is the theory that there are only relations between individual
entities, and no intrinsic
properties. Despite the similarity in name, it is held by some to be a
position distinct from relativism—for instance, because "statements
about relational properties [...] assert an absolute truth about things
in the world".
On the other hand, others wish to equate relativism, relationism and even relativity, which is a precise theory of relationships between physical objects:
Nevertheless, "This confluence of relativity theory with relativism
became a strong contributing factor in the increasing prominence of
relativism".
Whereas previous investigations of science only sought
sociological or psychological explanations of failed scientific theories
or pathological science, the 'strong programme' is more relativistic, assessing scientific truth and falsehood equally in a historic and cultural context.
Criticisms
A common argument against relativism suggests that it inherently contradicts, refutes, or stultifies itself:
the statement "all is relative" classes either as a relative statement
or as an absolute one. If it is relative, then this statement does not
rule out absolutes. If the statement is absolute,
on the other hand, then it provides an example of an absolute
statement, proving that not all truths are relative. However, this
argument against relativism only applies to relativism that positions
truth as relative–i.e. epistemological/truth-value relativism. More
specifically, it is only extreme forms of epistemological relativism
that can come in for this criticism as there are many epistemological
relativists
who posit that some aspects of what is regarded as factually "true" are
not universal, yet still accept that other universal truths exist (e.g.
gas laws or moral laws).
Another argument against relativism posits a Natural Law.
Simply put, the physical universe works under basic principles: the
"Laws of Nature". Some contend that a natural Moral Law may also exist,
for example as argued by Richard Dawkins in The God Delusion (2006) and addressed by C. S. Lewis in "Mere Christianity" (1952).
Dawkins said "I think we face an equal but much more sinister challenge
from the left, in the shape of cultural relativism - the view that
scientific truth is only one kind of truth and it is not to be
especially privileged".
Philosopher Hilary Putnam, among others,
states that some forms of relativism make it impossible to believe one
is in error. If there is no truth beyond an individual's belief
that something is true, then an individual cannot hold their own
beliefs to be false or mistaken. A related criticism is that
relativizing truth to individuals destroys the distinction between truth
and belief.
Views
Ancient India
Ancient Indian philosophers Mahavira (c. 599 – c. 527 BC) and Nagarjuna (c. 150 – c. 250 BC) made contributions to the development of relativist philosophy.
Sophism
Sophists are considered the founding fathers of relativism in Western philosophy. Elements of relativism emerged among the Sophists in the 5th century BC. Notably, it was Protagoras
who coined the phrase, "Man is the measure of all things: of things
which are, that they are, and of things which are not, that they are
not." The thinking of the Sophists is mainly known through their
opponent, Plato. In a paraphrase from Plato's dialogue Protagoras, Protagoras said: "What is true for you is true for you, and what is true for me is true for me."
Pyrrhonism
Pyrrhonist philosophy views relativity as a reason for philosophical skepticism, as it is one of the reasons that truth cannot be grasped. All perception
is relative to a perceiver, and perception differs according to
position. Hence, no particular perception can be judged as representing
the truth about what is perceived. Arguments from relativity form the
basis of trope 8 of the ten modes of Aenesidemus and trope 3 of the five modes of Agrippa.
Modern
Bernard Crick
Bernard Crick, a British political scientist and advocate of relativism, wrote the book In Defence of Politics (first published in 1962), suggesting the inevitability of moral conflict between people. Crick stated that only ethics could resolve such conflict, and when that occurred in public it resulted in politics. Accordingly, Crick saw the process of dispute resolution, harms reduction, mediation or peacemaking as central to all of moral philosophy. He became an important influence on the feminists and later on the Greens.
Paul Feyerabend
The philosopher of science Paul Feyerabend is often considered to be a relativist, though he denied being one.
Feyerabend argued that modern science suffers from being
methodologically monistic (the belief that only a single methodology can
produce scientific progress). Feyerabend summarises his case in his work Against Method with the phrase "anything goes".
- In an aphorism [Feyerabend] often repeated, "potentially every
culture is all cultures". This is intended to convey that world views
are not hermetically closed, since their leading concepts have an
"ambiguity" - better, an open-endedness - which enables people from
other cultures to engage with them. [...] It follows that relativism,
understood as the doctrine that truth is relative to closed systems, can
get no purchase. [...] For Feyerabend, both hermetic relativism and
its absolutist rival [realism] serve, in their different ways, to
"devalue human existence". The former encourages that unsavoury brand of
political correctness which takes the refusal to criticise "other
cultures" to the extreme of condoning murderous dictatorship and
barbaric practices. The latter, especially in its favoured contemporary
form of "scientific realism", with the excessive prestige it affords to
the abstractions of "the monster 'science'", is in bed with a politics
which likewise disdains variety, richness and everyday individuality - a
politics which likewise "hides" its norms behind allegedly neutral
facts, "blunts choices and imposes laws".
Thomas Kuhn
Thomas Kuhn's philosophy of science, as expressed in The Structure of Scientific Revolutions is often interpreted as relativistic. He claimed that as well as progressing steadily and incrementally ("normal science"), science undergoes periodic revolutions or "paradigm shifts",
leaving scientists working in different paradigms with difficulty in
even communicating. Thus the truth of a claim, or the existence of a
posited entity is relative to the paradigm employed. However, it isn't
necessary for him to embrace relativism because every paradigm
presupposes the prior, building upon itself through history and so on.
This leads to there being a fundamental, incremental, and referential
structure of development which is not relative but again, fundamental.
- From these remarks, one thing is however certain: Kuhn is not
saying that incommensurable theories cannot be compared - what they
can’t be is compared in terms of a system of common measure. He very
plainly says that they can be compared, and he reiterates this
repeatedly in later work, in a (mostly in vain) effort to avert the
crude and sometimes catastrophic misinterpretations he suffered from
mainstream philosophers and post-modern relativists alike.
But Thomas Kuhn denied the accusation of being a relativist later in his postscript.
- scientific development is ... a unidirectional and irreversible
process. Latter scientific theories are better than earlier ones for
solving puzzles ... That is not a relativist's position, and it displays
the sense in which I am a convinced believer in scientific progress.
Some have argued that one can also read Kuhn's work as essentially
positivist in its ontology: the revolutions he posits are
epistemological, lurching toward a presumably 'better' understanding of
an objective reality through the lens presented by the new paradigm.
However, a number of passages in Structures do indeed appear to be
distinctly relativist, and to directly challenge the notion of an
objective reality and the ability of science to progress towards an
ever-greater grasp of it, particularly through the process of paradigm
change.
- In the sciences there need not be progress of another sort. We
may, to be more precise, have to relinquish the notion, explicit or
implicit, that changes of paradigm carry scientists and those who learn
from them closer and closer to the truth.
- We are all deeply accustomed to seeing science as the one
enterprise that draws constantly nearer to some goal set by nature in
advance. But need there be any such goal? Can we not account for both
science’s existence and its success in terms of evolution from the
community’s state of knowledge at any given time? Does it really help to
imagine that there is some one full, objective, true account of nature
and that the proper measure of scientific achievement is the extent to
which it brings us closer to that ultimate goal?
George Lakoff and Mark Johnson
George Lakoff and Mark Johnson define relativism in their book Metaphors We Live By as the rejection of both subjectivism and metaphysical objectivism in order to focus on the relationship between them, i.e. the metaphor
by which we relate our current experience to our previous experience.
In particular, Lakoff and Johnson characterize "objectivism" as a "straw man", and, to a lesser degree, criticize the views of Karl Popper, Kant and Aristotle.
Robert Nozick
In his book Invariances, Robert Nozick
expresses a complex set of theories about the absolute and the
relative. He thinks the absolute/relative distinction should be recast
in terms of an invariant/variant distinction, where there are many
things a proposition can be invariant with regard to or vary with. He
thinks it is coherent for truth to be relative, and speculates that it
might vary with time. He thinks necessity is an unobtainable notion, but
can be approximated by robust invariance across a variety of
conditions—although we can never identify a proposition that is
invariant with regard to everything. Finally, he is not particularly
warm to one of the most famous forms of relativism, moral relativism, preferring an evolutionary account.
Joseph Margolis
Joseph Margolis advocates a view he calls "robust relativism" and defends it in his books: Historied Thought, Constructed World, Chapter 4 (California, 1995) and The Truth about Relativism
(Blackwells, 1991). He opens his account by stating that our logics
should depend on what we take to be the nature of the sphere to which we
wish to apply our logics. Holding that there can be no distinctions
which are not "privileged" between the alethic, the ontic, and the epistemic, he maintains that a many valued logic just might be the most apt for aesthetics or history since, because in these practices, we are loath to hold to simple binary logic;
and he also holds that many-valued logic is relativistic. (This is
perhaps an unusual definition of "relativistic". Compare with his
comments on "relationism"). "True" and "False" as mutually exclusive and
exhaustive judgements on Hamlet,
for instance, really does seem absurd. A many valued logic—"apt",
"reasonable", "likely", and so on—seems intuitively more applicable to
Hamlet interpretation. Where apparent contradictions arise between such
interpretations, we might call the interpretations "incongruent", rather
than dubbing either "false", because using many-valued logic implies
that a measured value is a mixture of two extreme possibilities. Using
the subset of many-valued logic, fuzzy logic,
it can be said that various interpretations can be represented by
membership in more than one possible truth sets simultaneously. Fuzzy
logic is therefore probably the best mathematical structure for
understanding "robust relativism" and has been interpreted by Bart Kosko as philosophically being related to Zen Buddhism.
It was Aristotle
who held that relativism implied we should, sticking with appearances
only, end up contradicting ourselves somewhere if we could apply all
attributes to all ousiai (beings). Aristotle, however, made non-contradiction dependent upon his essentialism.
If his essentialism is false, then so too is his ground for disallowing
relativism. (Subsequent philosophers have found other reasons for
supporting the principle of non-contradiction).
Beginning with Protagoras and invoking Charles Sanders Peirce,
Margolis shows that the historic struggle to discredit relativism is an
attempt to impose an unexamined belief in the world's essentially rigid
rule-like nature. Plato and Aristotle merely attacked
"relationalism"—the doctrine of true-for l or true for k, and the like,
where l and k are different speakers or different worlds, or the
something similar (Most philosophers would call this position
"relativism"). For Margolis, "true" means true; that is, the alethic use
of "true" remains untouched. However, in real world contexts, and
context is ubiquitous in the real world, we must apply truth values.
Here, in epistemic terms, we might retire "true" tout court
as an evaluation and keep "false". The rest of our value-judgements
could be graded from "extremely plausible" down to "false". Judgements
which on a bivalent logic would be incompatible or contradictory are
further seen as "incongruent", though one may well have more weight than
the other. In short, relativistic logic is not, or need not be, the
bugbear it is often presented to be. It may simply be the best type of
logic to apply to certain very uncertain spheres of real experiences in
the world (although some sort of logic needs to be applied to make that
judgement). Those who swear by bivalent logic might simply be the ultimate keepers of the great fear of the flux.
Richard Rorty
Philosopher Richard Rorty has a somewhat paradoxical
role in the debate over relativism: he is criticized for his
relativistic views by many commentators, but has always denied that
relativism applies to much anybody, being nothing more than a Platonic
scarecrow. Rorty claims, rather, that he is a pragmatist, and that to construe pragmatism as relativism is to beg the question.
- '"Relativism" is the traditional epithet applied to pragmatism by realists'
- '"Relativism" is the view that every belief on a certain topic,
or perhaps about any topic, is as good as every other. No one holds this
view. Except for the occasional cooperative freshman, one cannot find
anybody who says that two incompatible opinions on an important topic
are equally good. The philosophers who get called 'relativists' are
those who say that the grounds for choosing between such opinions are
less algorithmic than had been thought.'
- 'In short, my strategy for escaping the self-referential
difficulties into which "the Relativist" keeps getting himself is to
move everything over from epistemology and metaphysics into cultural
politics, from claims to knowledge and appeals to self-evidence to
suggestions about what we should try.'
Rorty takes a deflationary attitude to truth,
believing there is nothing of interest to be said about truth in
general, including the contention that it is generally subjective. He
also argues that the notion of warrant or justification can do most of the work traditionally assigned to the concept of truth, and that justification is relative; justification is justification to an audience, for Rorty.
In Contingency, Irony, and Solidarity
he argues that the debate between so-called relativists and so-called
objectivists is beside the point because they don't have enough premises
in common for either side to prove anything to the other.
Nalin de Silva
In his book Mage Lokaya (My World), 1986, Nalin de Silva
criticized the basis of the established western system of knowledge,
and its propagation, which he refers as "domination throughout the
world".He explained in this book that mind independent reality is
impossible and knowledge is not found but constructed. Further he has
introduced and developed the concept of "Constructive Relativism" as the
basis on which knowledge is constructed relative to the sense organs,
culture and the mind completely based on Avidya.
Postmodernism
The term "relativism" often comes up in debates over postmodernism, poststructuralism and phenomenology. Critics of these perspectives often identify advocates with the label "relativism". For example, the Sapir–Whorf hypothesis
is often considered a relativist view because it posits that linguistic
categories and structures shape the way people view the world. Stanley Fish has defended postmodernism and relativism.
These perspectives do not strictly count as relativist in the
philosophical sense, because they express agnosticism on the nature of
reality and make epistemological rather than ontological claims. Nevertheless, the term is useful to differentiate them from realists
who believe that the purpose of philosophy, science, or literary
critique is to locate externally true meanings. Important philosophers
and theorists such as Michel Foucault, Max Stirner, political movements such as post-anarchism or post-Marxism can also be considered as relativist in this sense - though a better term might be social constructivist.
The spread and popularity of this kind of "soft" relativism varies between academic disciplines. It has wide support in anthropology
and has a majority following in cultural studies. It also has advocates
in political theory and political science, sociology, and continental philosophy
(as distinct from Anglo-American analytical philosophy). It has
inspired empirical studies of the social construction of meaning such as
those associated with labelling theory, which defenders can point to as
evidence of the validity of their theories (albeit risking accusations
of performative contradiction
in the process). Advocates of this kind of relativism often also claim
that recent developments in the natural sciences, such as Heisenberg's uncertainty principle, quantum mechanics, chaos theory and complexity theory
show that science is now becoming relativistic. However, many
scientists who use these methods continue to identify as realist or post-positivist, and some sharply criticize the association.
Religious
Jainism
Mahavira (599-527 BC), the 24th Tirthankara of Jainism, developed an early philosophy regarding relativism and subjectivism known as Anekantavada.
Hinduism
Hindu religion has no theological difficulties in accepting degrees of truth in other religions. A Rig Vedic hymn states that "Truth is One, though the sages tell it variously." (Ékam sat vipra bahudā vadanti)
Buddhism
Madhyamaka Buddhism, which forms the basis for many Mahayana Buddhist schools and which was founded by Nagarjuna.
Nāgārjuna taught the idea of relativity. In the Ratnāvalī, he gives the
example that shortness exists only in relation to the idea of length.
The determination of a thing or object is only possible in relation to
other things or objects, especially by way of contrast. He held that the
relationship between the ideas of "short" and "long" is not due to
intrinsic nature (svabhāva).
This idea is also found in the Pali Nikāyas and Chinese Āgamas, in
which the idea of relativity is expressed similarly: "That which is the
element of light ... is seen to exist on account of [in relation to]
darkness; that which is the element of good is seen to exist on account
of bad; that which is the element of space is seen to exist on account
of form."
Madhyamaka Buddhism discerns two levels of truth, absolute and relative. The two truths doctrine states that there is Relative or common-sense truth, which describes our daily experience of a concrete world, and Ultimate truth, which describes the ultimate reality as sunyata,
empty of concrete and inherent characteristics. The conventional truth
may be interpreted as "obscurative truth" or "that which obscures the
true nature" as a result. It is constituted by the appearances of
mistaken awareness. Conventional truth would be the appearance that
includes a duality of apprehender and apprehended, and objects perceived
within that. Ultimate truths, are phenomena free from the duality of
apprehender and apprehended.
Sikhism
In Sikhism the Gurus (spiritual teacher ) have propagated the message of "many paths" leading to the one God and ultimate salvation for all souls who tread on the path of righteousness. They have supported the view that proponents of all faiths can, by doing good and virtuous deeds and by remembering the Lord,
certainly achieve salvation. The students of the Sikh faith are told to
accept all leading faiths as possible vehicles for attaining spiritual
enlightenment provided the faithful study, ponder and practice the
teachings of their prophets and leaders. The holy book of the Sikhs called the Sri Guru Granth Sahib says: "Do not say that the Vedas, the Bible and the Koran are false. Those who do not contemplate them are false." Guru Granth Sahib page 1350;
later stating "The seconds, minutes, and hours, days, weeks and months,
and the various seasons originate from the one Sun; O nanak, in just
the same way, the many forms originate from the Creator." Guru Granth Sahib page 12,13.
Catholicism
The Catholic Church, especially under John Paul II and Pope Benedict XVI, has identified relativism as one of the most significant problems for faith and morals today.
According to the Church and to some theologians, relativism, as a
denial of absolute truth, leads to moral license and a denial of the
possibility of sin and of God.
Whether moral or epistemological, relativism constitutes a denial of
the capacity of the human mind and reason to arrive at truth. Truth,
according to Catholic theologians and philosophers (following Aristotle)
consists of adequatio rei et intellectus, the correspondence of the mind and reality. Another way of putting it states that the mind
has the same form as reality. This means when the form of the computer
in front of someone (the type, color, shape, capacity, etc.) is also the
form that is in their mind, then what they know is true because their
mind corresponds to objective reality.
The denial of an absolute reference, of an axis mundi, denies God, who equates to Absolute Truth, according to these Christian theologians. They link relativism to secularism, an obstruction of religion in human life.
Leo XIII
Pope Leo XIII (1810–1903) was the first known Pope to use the word relativism in the encyclical Humanum genus (1884). Leo XIII condemned Freemasonry and claimed that its philosophical and political system was largely based on relativism.
John Paul II
John Paul II in Veritatis Splendor
- As is immediately evident, the crisis of truth is not
unconnected with this development. Once the idea of a universal truth
about the good, knowable by human reason, is lost, inevitably the notion
of conscience also changes. Conscience is no longer considered in its
primordial reality as an act of a person's intelligence, the function of
which is to apply the universal knowledge of the good in a specific
situation and thus to express a judgment about the right conduct to be
chosen here and now. Instead, there is a tendency to grant to the
individual conscience the prerogative of independently determining the
criteria of good and evil and then acting accordingly. Such an outlook
is quite congenial to an individualist ethic, wherein each individual is
faced with his own truth, different from the truth of others. Taken to
its extreme consequences, this individualism leads to a denial of the
very idea of human nature.
In Evangelium Vitae (The Gospel of Life), he says:
- Freedom negates and destroys itself, and becomes a factor
leading to the destruction of others, when it no longer recognizes and
respects its essential link with the truth. When freedom, out of a
desire to emancipate itself from all forms of tradition and authority,
shuts out even the most obvious evidence of an objective and universal
truth, which is the foundation of personal and social life, then the
person ends up by no longer taking as the sole and indisputable point of
reference for his own choices the truth about good and evil, but only
his subjective and changeable opinion or, indeed, his selfish interest
and whim.
Benedict XVI
In April 2005, in his homily during Mass prior to the conclave which would elect him as Pope, then Cardinal Joseph Ratzinger talked about the world "moving towards a dictatorship of relativism":
- How many winds of doctrine we have known in recent decades, how
many ideological currents, how many ways of thinking. The small boat of
thought of many Christians has often been tossed about by these waves –
thrown from one extreme to the other: from Marxism to liberalism, even
to libertinism; from collectivism to radical individualism; from atheism
to a vague religious mysticism; from agnosticism to syncretism, and so
forth. Every day new sects are created and what Saint Paul says about human trickery comes true, with cunning which tries to draw those into error (cf Ephesians
4, 14). Having a clear Faith, based on the Creed of the Church, is
often labeled today as a fundamentalism. Whereas, relativism, which is
letting oneself be tossed and "swept along by every wind of teaching",
looks like the only attitude acceptable to today's standards. We are
moving towards a dictatorship of relativism which does not recognize
anything as certain and which has as its highest goal one's own ego and
one's own desires. However, we have a different goal: the Son of God,
true man. He is the measure of true humanism. Being an "Adult" means
having a faith which does not follow the waves of today's fashions or
the latest novelties. A faith which is deeply rooted in friendship with Christ
is adult and mature. It is this friendship which opens us up to all
that is good and gives us the knowledge to judge true from false, and
deceit from truth.
On June 6, 2005, Pope Benedict XVI told educators:
- Today, a particularly insidious obstacle to the task of
education is the massive presence in our society and culture of that
relativism which, recognizing nothing as definitive, leaves as the
ultimate criterion only the self with its desires. And under the
semblance of freedom it becomes a prison for each one, for it separates
people from one another, locking each person into his or her own 'ego'.
Then during the World Youth Day
in August 2005, he also traced to relativism the problems produced by
the communist and sexual revolutions, and provided a counter-counter
argument.
- In the last century we experienced revolutions with a common
programme–expecting nothing more from God, they assumed total
responsibility for the cause of the world in order to change it. And
this, as we saw, meant that a human and partial point of view was always
taken as an absolute guiding principle. Absolutizing what is not
absolute but relative is called totalitarianism. It does not liberate
man, but takes away his dignity and enslaves him. It is not ideologies
that save the world, but only a return to the living God, our Creator,
the Guarantor of our freedom, the Guarantor of what is really good and
true.