From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Fallacy
A fallacy, also known as paralogia in modern psychology, is the use of invalid or otherwise faulty reasoning in the construction of an argument that may appear to be well-reasoned if unnoticed. The term was introduced in the Western intellectual tradition by the Aristotelian De Sophisticis Elenchis.
Fallacies may be committed intentionally to manipulate or persuade by deception, unintentionally because of human limitations such as carelessness, cognitive or social biases and ignorance,
or potentially due to the limitations of language and understanding of
language. These delineations include not only the ignorance of the right
reasoning standard but also the ignorance of relevant properties of the context. For instance, the soundness of legal arguments depends on the context in which they are made.
Fallacies are commonly divided into "formal" and "informal." A formal fallacy is a flaw in the structure of a deductive argument that renders the argument invalid, while an informal fallacy originates in an error in reasoning other than an improper logical form. Arguments containing informal fallacies may be formally valid, but still fallacious.
A special case is a mathematical fallacy, an intentionally invalid mathematical proof
with a concealed, or subtle, error. Mathematical fallacies are
typically crafted and exhibited for educational purposes, usually taking
the form of false proofs of obvious contradictions.
Overview
Fallacies are types of erroneous reasoning that render arguments logically unsound.
According to The New Handbook of Cognitive Therapy Techniques, they
include "unsubstantiated assertions that are often delivered with a
conviction that makes them sound as though they are proven facts." Informal fallacies, in particular, are frequently found in mass media such as television and newspapers.
Understanding fallacies may allow one to recognize them in either one's
own or others' writing. Avoiding fallacies may help improve one's
ability to produce sound arguments.
It can be difficult to evaluate whether an argument is fallacious, as arguments exist along a continuum of soundness and an argument that has several stages or parts might have some sound sections and some fallacious ones.
Moreover, whether a specific argument is fallacious often depends on
the content rather than the form of the argument. An example is a probabilistically valid instance of the formally invalid argument form of denying the antecedent or affirming the consequent. Thus, "fallacious arguments usually have the deceptive appearance of being good arguments,
because for most fallacious instances of an argument form, a similar
but non-fallacious instance can be found." Evaluating an instance of an
argument as fallacious is therefore often a matter of evaluating the
context of the argument.
Recognizing fallacies in everyday arguments may be difficult since arguments are often embedded in rhetorical patterns that obscure the logical connections between statements. Informal fallacies may also exploit the emotional, intellectual, or psychological
weaknesses of the audience. Recognizing fallacies can develop reasoning
skills to expose the weaker links between premises and conclusions to
better discern between what appears to be true and what is true.
Argumentation theory provides a different approach to understanding and classifying fallacies. In the pragma-dialectical theory,
for instance, an argument is regarded as an interactive protocol
between individuals who attempt to resolve their disagreement on the
merits of a case. The protocol consists of normative rules of interaction, and violations of these rules are considered fallacies because they frustrate the attempt at resolving the disagreement.
Fallacies are used in place of valid reasoning to communicate a point with the intention to persuade. Examples in the mass media today include but are not limited to propaganda, advertisements, politics, newspaper editorials, and opinion-based news shows.
Systems of classification
Fallacies are generally classified strictly by either their structure or their content, such as by classifying them as formal fallacies or informal fallacies,
respectively. The classification of informal fallacies may be
subdivided into categories such as linguistic, relevance through
omission, relevance through intrusion, and relevance through
presumption. Alternatively, fallacies may be classified by the process by which they occur, such as material fallacies (content), verbal fallacies
(linguistic), and formal fallacies (error in inference). In turn,
material fallacies may be placed into the more general category of
informal fallacies. Verbal fallacies may be placed in either formal or
informal classifications: Compare equivocation, which is a word- or phrase-based ambiguity, to the fallacy of composition, which is premise- and inference-based ambiguity.
Greek logic
The Greek philosopher Aristotle
(384–322 BC) was the first to systematize logical errors into a list to
make it easier to refute an opponent's thesis and thus win an argument. Aristotle's "Sophistical Refutations" (De Sophisticis Elenchis)
identifies thirteen fallacies. He divided them up into two major types:
linguistic fallacies and non-linguistic fallacies, some of which depend
on language and others that do not. These fallacies are called verbal fallacies and material fallacies, respectively. A material fallacy is an error in what the arguer is talking about, while a verbal fallacy
is an error in how the arguer is talking. Verbal fallacies are those in
which a conclusion is obtained by improper or ambiguous use of words.
An example of a language dependent fallacy is given as a debate as to who in humanity are learners: the wise or the ignorant. A language-independent fallacy is, for example:
- "Coriscus is different from Socrates."
- "Socrates is a man."
- "Therefore, Coriscus is different from a man."
Indian logic
Indian logicians took great pains to identify fallacies in arguments. An influential collection of texts on logic and reason, the Nyāya Sūtras, attributed to Aksapada Gautama,
variously estimated to have been composed between the 6th century BCE
and the 2nd century CE, lists in its theory of inference five such
reasons used in an argument that was further developed by later
logicians.
- Asiddha: It is the unproved reason that results in this fallacy. [Paksadharmata]
- Savyabhichara: This is the fallacy of irregular reason.
- Satpratipaksa: Here the reason is contradicted by another
reason. If both have equal force, then nothing follows. 'Sound is
eternal, because it is audible', and 'Sound is non-eternal, because it
is produced'. Here 'audible' is counterbalanced by 'produced' and both
are of equal force.
- Badhita: When another proof (as by perception) definitely
contradicts and disproves the middle term (reason). 'Fire is cold
because it is a substance'.
- Viruddha: Instead of proving something it is proving the opposite. 'Sound is eternal because it is produced'.
Whately's grouping
English scholar and theologian Richard Whately
(1787–1863) defines a fallacy broadly as, "any argument, or apparent
argument, which professes to be decisive of the matter at hand, while in
reality it is not".
Whately divided fallacies into two groups: logical and material.
According to Whately, logical fallacies are arguments where the
conclusion does not follow from the premises. Material fallacies are not
logical errors because the conclusion follows from the premises. He
then divided the logical group into two groups: purely logical and
semi-logical. The semi-logical group included all of Aristotle's sophisms except ignoratio elenchi, petitio principii, and non causa pro causa, which are in the material group.
Other systems of classification
Other famous methods of classifying fallacies are those of Francis Bacon and J. S. Mill. Bacon (Novum Organum,
Aph. 33, 38 sqq.) divided fallacies into four Idola (Idols, i.e. False
Appearances), which summarize the various kinds of mistakes to which the
human intellect is prone. J. S. Mill discussed the subject in book five
of his Logic, and Jeremy Bentham's Book of Fallacies (1824) contains valuable remarks.
Formal fallacy
A formal fallacy, deductive fallacy, logical fallacy or non sequitur (Latin for "it does not follow") is a flaw in the structure of a deductive argument that renders the argument invalid. The flaw can be expressed in the standard system of logic. Such an argument is always considered to be wrong.
The presence of the formal fallacy does not imply anything about the argument's premises
or its conclusion. Both may actually be true or may even be more
probable as a result of the argument, but the deductive argument is
still invalid because the conclusion does not follow from the premises
in the manner described.
Even non-deductive arguments can be said to be fallacious: for example, an inductive argument that incorrectly applies principles of probability or causality.
But "since deductive arguments depend on formal properties and
inductive arguments don't, formal fallacies apply only to deductive
arguments."
A logical form such as "A and B"
is independent of any particular conjunction of meaningful
propositions. Logical form alone can guarantee that, given true
premises, a true conclusion must follow. However, formal logic makes no
such guarantee if any premise is false; the conclusion can be either
true or false. Any formal error or logical fallacy similarly invalidates
the deductive guarantee. Both the argument and all its premises must be
true for a conclusion to be true.
The term logical fallacy is in a sense self-contradictory because logic refers to valid reasoning, whereas a fallacy is the use of poor reasoning. Therefore, the term formal fallacy is preferred. In informal discourse, however, logical fallacy is used to mean an argument that is problematic for any reason.
The term non sequitur denotes a general formal fallacy, often meaning one that does not belong to any named subclass of formal fallacies, like affirming the consequent.
Common examples
Ecological fallacy
An ecological fallacy
is committed when one draws an inference from data based on the premise
that qualities observed for groups necessarily hold for individuals;
for example, "if countries with more Protestants tend to have higher
suicide rates, then Protestants must be more likely to commit suicide."
Fallacy fork
Maarten Boudry and others
have argued that formal, deductive fallacies rarely occur in real life
and that arguments that would be fallacious in formally deductive terms
are not necessarily so when context and prior probabilities are taken
into account, thus making the argument defeasible and/or inductive.
Boudry coined the term fallacy fork. For a given fallacy, one must either characterize it by means of a deductive argumentation scheme,
which rarely applies (the first prong of the fork), or one must relax
definitions and add nuance to take the actual intent and context of the
argument into account (the other prong of the fork).
To argue, for example, that one became nauseated after eating a
mushroom because the mushroom was poisonous could be an example of the post hoc ergo propter hoc fallacy.
Informal fallacy
In contrast to a formal fallacy, an informal fallacy originates from a
reasoning error other than a flaw in the logical form of the argument. A deductive argument containing an informal fallacy may be formally valid, but still remain rationally unpersuasive. Nevertheless, informal fallacies apply to both deductive and non-deductive arguments.
Though the form of the argument may be relevant, fallacies of
this type are "types of mistakes in reasoning that arise from the
mishandling of the content of the propositions constituting the argument".
Faulty generalization
A special subclass of the informal fallacies is the set of faulty generalizations, also known as inductive fallacies. Here, the most important issue concerns inductive strength or methodology (for example, statistical inference). In the absence of sufficient evidence, drawing conclusions based on induction is unwarranted and fallacious. With the backing of sufficient amounts of the right type of empirical evidence,
however, the conclusions may become warranted and convincing (at which
point the arguments are no longer considered fallacious).
Hasty generalization
Hasty generalization is described as making assumptions about a whole group or range of cases based on a sample
that is inadequate (usually because it is atypical or just too small).
Stereotypes about people ("frat boys are drunkards", "grad students are
nerdy", "women don't enjoy sports", etc.) are common examples of the
principle.
Hasty generalization often follows a pattern such as:
- X is true for A.
- X is true for B.
- Therefore, X is true for C, D, etc.
While never a valid logical deduction, if such an inference can be
made on statistical grounds, it may nonetheless be convincing. This is
because with enough empirical evidence, the generalization is no longer a
hasty one.
Relevance fallacy
The fallacies of relevance are a broad class of informal fallacies, generically represented by missing the point: presenting an argument that may be sound but fails to address the issue in question.
Argument from silence
An argument from silence is a faulty conclusion that is drawn based on the absence of evidence rather than on the presence of evidence.
Examples of informal fallacies
Post hoc (false cause)
The post hoc fallacy assumes that because B comes after A, A caused B. It gets its name from the Latin phrase "post hoc, ergo propter hoc", which translates as "after this, therefore because of this".
Sometimes one event really does cause another one that comes
later—for example, if one registers for a class and their name later
appears on the roll, it's true that the first event caused the one that
came later. But sometimes two events that seem related in time are not
really related as cause and event. That is, temporal correlation does not necessarily entail causation.
For example, if one eats a sandwich and then gets food poisoning, that
does not necessarily mean the sandwich caused the food poisoning.
Something else eaten earlier might have caused the food poisoning.
Slippery slope
For an argument to be a slippery slope type of argument, it must meet the requirements of that argumentation scheme.
A slippery slope argument originates from a conversation or debate in
which two actors take turns. It usually originates from one actor giving
advice on a decision or act. Along the way, the actor must make
additional choices on similar matters through which the actor enters the
‘grey area’ of the slippery slope. At this point, the actor potentially
loses control over the direction of the arguments, thus leading to a
‘fatal’ outcome.
Such an argument is built up according to the following
argumentation scheme: initial premise, sequential premise, indeterminacy
premise, control premise, loss of control premise, catastrophic outcome
premise, and conclusion. Slippery slope arguments may be defeated by
asking critical questions or giving counterarguments.
There are several reasons for a slippery slope to be fallacious:
for example, the argument is going too far into the future, it is a too
complex argument whose structure is hard to identify, or the argument
makes emotional appeals.
It may be that a slippery slope is not necessarily fallacious if
context is taken into account and there is an effort to assess
plausibility.
False analogy
Informally known as the "apples and oranges" fallacy, a false analogy uses unsound comparisons.
Straw man fallacy
The straw man
fallacy refers to the refutation of a standpoint in an argument that
was never proposed. The fallacy usually occurs in the presentation of an
opponent's standpoint as more extreme, distorted, or simplistic than it
actually is. Compared to criticizing the opponent's actual standpoint,
this allows the arguer to offer a seeming refutation of what is,
however, not the actual standpoint. Such an argument involves two arguers, with one criticizing the other's perspective.
The reason for the straw man argument to be fallacious originates from
the problem of how to deal with natural discourse. The opponent's
argument is not reflected by the arguments that are proposed by the
speaker.
Measurement fallacy
Some of the fallacies described above may be committed in the context of measurement.
Where mathematical fallacies
are subtle mistakes in reasoning leading to invalid mathematical
proofs, measurement fallacies are unwarranted inferential leaps involved
in the extrapolation of raw data to a measurement-based value claim.
The ancient Greek Sophist Protagoras
was one of the first thinkers to propose that humans can generate
reliable measurements through his "human-measure" principle and the
practice of dissoi logoi (arguing multiple sides of an issue). This history helps explain why measurement fallacies are informed by informal logic and argumentation theory.
Knowledge value measurement fallacy
The increasing availability and circulation of big data are driving a proliferation of new metrics for scholarly authority,
and there is lively discussion regarding the relative usefulness of
such metrics for measuring the value of knowledge production in the
context of an "information tsunami."
For example, anchoring
fallacies can occur when unwarranted weight is given to data generated
by metrics that the arguers themselves acknowledge are flawed. For
example, the limitations of the journal impact factor (JIF) are well documented,
and even JIF pioneer Eugene Garfield notes that, "while citation data
create new tools for analyses of research performance, it should be
stressed that they supplement rather than replace other quantitative and
qualitative indicators."
To the extent that arguers jettison the acknowledged limitations of
JIF-generated data in evaluative judgments or leave behind Garfield's
"supplement rather than replace" caveat, they commit anchoring
fallacies.
A naturalistic fallacy can occur, for example, in the case of sheer quantity metrics based on the premise "more is better" or, in the case of developmental assessment in the field of psychology, "higher is better".
A false analogy occurs when claims are supported by unsound comparisons between data points. For example, the Scopus and Web of Science
bibliographic databases have difficulty distinguishing between
citations of scholarly work that are arms-length endorsements,
ceremonial citations, or negative citations (indicating the citing
author withholds endorsement of the cited work).
Hence, measurement-based value claims premised on the uniform quality
of all citations may be questioned on false analogy grounds.
As another example, consider the Faculty Scholarly Productivity Index
of Academic Analytics. This tool purports to measure overall faculty
productivity, yet it does not capture data based on citations in books.
This creates a possibility that low productivity measurements using the
tool commit argument from silence fallacies, to the extent that such measurements are supported by the absence of book citation data.
Ecological fallacies
can be committed when one measures the scholarly productivity of a
sub-group of individuals (e.g. "Puerto Rican" faculty) via reference to
aggregate data about a larger and different group (e.g., "Hispanic"
faculty).
Intentional fallacy
Sometimes
a speaker or writer uses a fallacy intentionally. In any context,
including academic debate, a conversation among friends, political
discourse, advertising, or comedic purposes, the arguer may use
fallacious reasoning to try to persuade the listener or reader, by means
other than offering relevant evidence, that the conclusion is true.
Examples of this include the speaker or writer:
- Diverting the argument to unrelated issues with a red herring (Ignoratio elenchi)
- Insulting someone's character (argumentum ad hominem)
- Assuming the conclusion of an argument, a kind of circular reasoning, also called "begging the question" (petitio principii)
- Making jumps in logic (non sequitur)
- Identifying a false cause and effect (post hoc ergo propter hoc)
- Asserting that everyone agrees (argumentum ad populum, bandwagoning)
- Creating a false dilemma (either-or fallacy) in which the situation is oversimplified, also called false dichotomy
- Selectively using facts (card stacking)
- Making false or misleading comparisons (false equivalence or false analogy)
- Generalizing quickly and sloppily (hasty generalization) (secundum quid)
- Using an argument's connections to other concepts or people to support or refute it, also called "guilt by association" (association fallacy)
- Claiming that a lack of proof counts as proof (appeal to ignorance)
In humor, errors of reasoning are used for comical purposes. Groucho Marx used fallacies of amphiboly, for instance, to make ironic statements; Gary Larson and Scott Adams
employed fallacious reasoning in many of their cartoons. Wes Boyer and
Samuel Stoddard have written a humorous essay teaching students how to
be persuasive by means of a whole host of informal and formal fallacies.
When someone uses logical fallacies intentionally to mislead in
academic, political, or other high-stakes contexts, the breach of trust
calls into question the authority and intellectual integrity of that person.
Assessment: pragmatic theory
According to the pragmatic theory,
a fallacy can be either a heuristic error or a ploy used intentionally
to unfairly win an argument. There are always two parties to an argument
containing a fallacy: the perpetrator and the intended victim.
The dialogue framework required to support the pragmatic theory
of fallacy is built on the presumption that argumentative dialogue has
both an adversarial component and a collaborative component. A dialogue
has individual goals for each participant as well as shared goals that
apply to all participants. A fallacy of the second kind is seen as more
than simply a violation of the rule of reasonable dialogue. It is also a
deceptive tactic of argumentation based on sleight-of-hand. Aristotle
explicitly compared contentious reasoning to unfair fighting in athletic
contests. But the roots of the pragmatic theory go back even further in
history, to the Sophists. The pragmatic theory finds its roots in the
Aristotelian conception of a fallacy as a sophistical refutation but
also supports the view that many of the types of arguments traditionally
labeled as fallacies are in fact reasonable techniques of argumentation
that can be used, in many cases, to support legitimate goals of
dialogue. Hence, under the pragmatic approach, each case needs to be
analyzed individually to determine whether the argument is fallacious or
reasonable.