Particle physics (also known as high energy physics) is a branch of physics that studies the nature of the particles that constitute matter and radiation. Although the word particle can refer to various types of very small objects (e.g. protons, gas particles, or even household dust), particle physics usually investigates the irreducibly smallest detectable particles and the fundamental interactions necessary to explain their behaviour.
In current understanding, these elementary particles are excitations of the quantum fields
that also govern their interactions. The currently dominant theory
explaining these fundamental particles and fields, along with their
dynamics, is called the Standard Model.
Thus, modern particle physics generally investigates the Standard Model
and its various possible extensions, e.g. to the newest "known"
particle, the Higgs boson, or even to the oldest known force field, gravity.
Dynamics of particles are also governed by quantum mechanics; they exhibit wave–particle duality, displaying particle-like behaviour under certain experimental conditions and wave-like behaviour in others. In more technical terms, they are described by quantum state vectors in a Hilbert space, which is also treated in quantum field theory. Following the convention of particle physicists, the term elementary particles
is applied to those particles that are, according to current
understanding, presumed to be indivisible and not composed of other
particles.
All particles and their interactions observed to date can be described almost entirely by a quantum field theory called the Standard Model. The Standard Model, as currently formulated, has 61 elementary particles.
Those elementary particles can combine to form composite particles,
accounting for the hundreds of other species of particles that have been
discovered since the 1960s.
The Standard Model has been found to agree with almost all the experimental
tests conducted to date. However, most particle physicists believe that
it is an incomplete description of nature and that a more fundamental
theory awaits discovery (See Theory of Everything). In recent years, measurements of neutrinomass have provided the first experimental deviations from the Standard Model, since neutrinos are massless in the Standard Model.
The idea that all matter is fundamentally composed of elementary particles dates from at least the 6th century BC. In the 19th century, John Dalton, through his work on stoichiometry, concluded that each element of nature was composed of a single, unique type of particle. The word atom, after the Greek word atomos meaning "indivisible", has since then denoted the smallest particle of a chemical element,
but physicists soon discovered that atoms are not, in fact, the
fundamental particles of nature, but are conglomerates of even smaller
particles, such as the electron. The early 20th century explorations of nuclear physics and quantum physics led to proofs of nuclear fission in 1939 by Lise Meitner (based on experiments by Otto Hahn), and nuclear fusion by Hans Bethe in that same year; both discoveries also led to the development of nuclear weapons.
Throughout the 1950s and 1960s, a bewildering variety of particles were
found in collisions of particles from beams of increasingly high
energy. It was referred to informally as the "particle zoo". Important discoveries such as the CP violation by James Cronin and Val Fitch brought new questions to matter-antimatter imbalance. The term particle zoo was modified
after the formulation of the Standard Model during the 1970s, in which
the large number of particles was explained as combinations of a
(relatively) small number of more fundamental particles, which marked
the beginning of modern particle physics.
The current state of the classification of all elementary particles is explained by the Standard Model, which gained widespread acceptance in the mid-1970s after experimental confirmation of the existence of quarks. It describes the strong, weak, and electromagneticfundamental interactions, using mediating gauge bosons. The species of gauge bosons are eight gluons, W− , W+ and Z bosons, and the photon. The Standard Model also contains 24 fundamentalfermions (12 particles and their associated anti-particles), which are the constituents of all matter. Finally, the Standard Model also predicted the existence of a type of boson known as the Higgs boson.
On 4 July 2012, physicists with the Large Hadron Collider at CERN
announced they had found a new particle that behaves similarly to what
is expected from the Higgs boson.
Experimental laboratories
Fermi National Accelerator Laboratory, USA
The world's major particle physics laboratories are:
Budker Institute of Nuclear Physics (Novosibirsk, Russia). Its main projects are now the electron-positron collidersVEPP-2000, operated since 2006, and VEPP-4, started experiments in 1994. Earlier facilities include the first electron–electron beam–beam collider VEP-1, which conducted experiments from 1964 to 1968; the electron-positron colliders VEPP-2, operated from 1965 to 1974; and, its successor VEPP-2M, performed experiments from 1974 to 2000.
CERN (European Organization for Nuclear Research) (Franco-Swiss border, near Geneva). Its main project is now the Large Hadron Collider
(LHC), which had its first beam circulation on 10 September 2008, and
is now the world's most energetic collider of protons. It also became
the most energetic collider of heavy ions after it began colliding lead
ions. Earlier facilities include the Large Electron–Positron Collider (LEP), which was stopped on 2 November 2000 and then dismantled to give way for LHC; and the Super Proton Synchrotron, which is being reused as a pre-accelerator for the LHC and for fixed-target experiments.
DESY (Deutsches Elektronen-Synchrotron) (Hamburg, Germany). Its main facility was the Hadron Elektron Ring Anlage (HERA), which collided electrons and positrons with protons. The accelerator complex is now focused on the production of synchrotron radiation with PETRA III, FLASH and the European XFEL.
The techniques required for modern experimental particle physics
are quite varied and complex, constituting a sub-specialty nearly
completely distinct from the theoretical side of the field.
Theoretical particle physics attempts to develop the models,
theoretical framework, and mathematical tools to understand current
experiments and make predictions for future experiments (see also theoretical physics). There are several major interrelated efforts being made in theoretical particle physics today.
One important branch attempts to better understand the Standard Model and its tests. Theorists make quantitative predictions of observables at collider and astronomical
experiments, which along with experimental measurements is used to
extract the parameters of the Standard Model with less uncertainty. This
work probes the limits of the Standard Model and therefore expands
scientific understanding of nature's building blocks. Those efforts are
made challenging by the difficulty of calculating high precision
quantities in quantum chromodynamics. Some theorists working in this area use the tools of perturbative quantum field theory and effective field theory, referring to themselves as phenomenologists. Others make use of lattice field theory and call themselves lattice theorists.
Another major effort is in model building where model builders develop ideas for what physics may lie beyond the Standard Model (at higher energies or smaller distances). This work is often motivated by the hierarchy problem and is constrained by existing experimental data. It may involve work on supersymmetry, alternatives to the Higgs mechanism, extra spatial dimensions (such as the Randall–Sundrum models), Preon theory, combinations of these, or other ideas.
A third major effort in theoretical particle physics is string theory. String theorists attempt to construct a unified description of quantum mechanics and general relativity by building a theory based on small strings, and branes rather than particles. If the theory is successful, it may be considered a "Theory of Everything", or "TOE".
This division of efforts in particle physics is reflected in the names of categories on the arXiv, a preprint archive: hep-th (theory), hep-ph (phenomenology), hep-ex (experiments), hep-lat (lattice gauge theory).
Practical applications
In
principle, all physics (and practical applications developed therefrom)
can be derived from the study of fundamental particles. In practice,
even if "particle physics" is taken to mean only "high-energy atom
smashers", many technologies have been developed during these pioneering
investigations that later find wide uses in society. Particle
accelerators are used to produce medical isotopes for research and treatment (for example, isotopes used in PET imaging), or used directly in external beam radiotherapy. The development of superconductors has been pushed forward by their use in particle physics. The World Wide Web and touchscreen technology were initially developed at CERN.
Additional applications are found in medicine, national security,
industry, computing, science, and workforce development, illustrating a
long and growing list of beneficial practical applications with
contributions from particle physics.
Future
The primary goal, which is pursued in several distinct ways, is to find and understand what physics may lie beyond the standard model. There are several powerful experimental reasons to expect new physics, including dark matter and neutrino mass. There are also theoretical hints that this new physics should be found at accessible energy scales.
Much of the effort to find this new physics are focused on new collider experiments. The Large Hadron Collider (LHC) was completed in 2008 to help continue the search for the Higgs boson, supersymmetric particles, and other new physics. An intermediate goal is the construction of the International Linear Collider
(ILC), which will complement the LHC by allowing more precise
measurements of the properties of newly found particles. In August 2004,
a decision for the technology of the ILC was taken but the site has
still to be agreed upon.
In addition, there are important non-collider experiments that also attempt to find and understand physics beyond the Standard Model. One important non-collider effort is the determination of the neutrino masses, since these masses may arise from neutrinos mixing with very heavy particles. In addition, cosmological
observations provide many useful constraints on the dark matter,
although it may be impossible to determine the exact nature of the dark
matter without the colliders. Finally, lower bounds on the very long lifetime of the proton put constraints on Grand Unified Theories at energy scales much higher than collider experiments will be able to probe any time soon.
In May 2014, the Particle Physics Project Prioritization Panel
released its report on particle physics funding priorities for the
United States over the next decade. This report emphasized continued
U.S. participation in the LHC and ILC, and expansion of the Deep Underground Neutrino Experiment, among other recommendations.
The Bohr–Einstein debates were a series of public disputes about quantum mechanics between Albert Einstein and Niels Bohr. Their debates are remembered because of their importance to the philosophy of science,
since the disagreements and the outcome of Bohr's version of quantum
mechanics that became the prevalent view form the root of the modern
understanding of physics. Most of Bohr's version of the events held in Solvay in 1927 and other places was first written by Bohr decades later in an article titled, "Discussions with Einstein
on Epistemological Problems in Atomic Physics". Based on the article, the philosophical issue of the debate was whether Bohr's Copenhagen Interpretation of quantum mechanics, which centered on his belief of complementarity, was valid in explaining nature.
Despite their differences of opinion and the succeeding discoveries
that helped solidify quantum mechanics, Bohr and Einstein maintained a
mutual admiration that was to last the rest of their lives.
The debates represent one of the highest points of scientific
research in the first half of the twentieth century because it called
attention to an element of quantum theory, quantum non-locality,
which is central to our modern understanding of the physical world. The
consensus view of professional physicists has been that Bohr proved
victorious in his defense of quantum theory, and definitively
established the fundamental probabilistic character of quantum
measurement.
Pre-revolutionary debates
Einstein was the first physicist to say that Planck's discovery of the quantum (h) would require a rewriting of the laws of physics. To support his point, in 1905 he proposed that light sometimes acts as a particle which he called a light quantum (see photon and wave–particle duality). Bohr was one of the most vocal opponents of the photon idea and did not openly embrace it until 1925.
The photon appealed to Einstein because he saw it as a physical reality
(although a confusing one) behind the numbers presented by Planck
mathematically in 1900. Bohr disliked it because it made the choice of
mathematical solution arbitrary. Bohr did not like a scientist having to
choose between equations. This was perhaps the first real Bohr-Einstein debate. Einstein had proposed the photon in 1905, and Compton
proved that the photon existed experimentally in 1922, but Bohr refused
to believe the photon existed even then. Bohr fought back against the
existence of the quantum of light (photon) by writing the BKS theory in 1924. However, Einstein was right and Bohr proved to be wrong about light quanta.
Although Bohr and Einstein disagreed, they were great friends all their lives and enjoyed using each other as a foil.
The year 1913 brought the Bohr model of the hydrogen atom,
which made use of the quantum to explain the atomic spectrum although
at the time Bohr did not believe the atom to be wave-like but like a
solar system so that the equations he used were for rotational orbits of
particles similar to planets, yet Planck’s constant had been invented
for light radiation in black bodies. Einstein was at first skeptical
about using h for a solar system style atom, but quickly changed his
mind and admitted his shift in mindset. From 1913 to 1919, Einstein
studied and revised Arnold Sommerfeld’s extension of the Bohr atom to include the Stark effect and Zeeman effect. The coefficients Einstein created during this time are still named for him and still in use today.
The quantum revolution
The
quantum revolution of the mid-1920s occurred under the direction of
both Einstein and Bohr, and their post-revolutionary debates were about
making sense of the change. The shocks for Einstein began in 1925 when Werner Heisenberg introduced matrix equations that removed the Newtonian elements of space and time from any underlying reality. However, when Erwin Schrödinger
sent a preprint of his new equation to Einstein, Einstein wrote back
hailing his equation as a decisive advance of “true genius.” But the next shock came in 1926 when Max Born proposed that mechanics were to be understood as a probability without any causal explanation.
Both Einstein and Erwin Schrödinger rejected this interpretation with its renunciation of causality which had been a key feature of science previous to Quantum Mechanics and was still a feature of General Relativity. In a 1926 letter to Max Born,
Einstein wrote: "quantum mechanics is certainly imposing. But an inner
voice tells me that it is not yet the real thing. The theory says a lot,
but does not really bring us any closer to the secret of the “old one”.
I, at any rate, am convinced that He [God] is not playing at dice." At first, even Heisenberg had heated disputes with Bohr that his matrix mechanics was not compatible with the
Schrödinger Equation. And Bohr was at first opposed to the Uncertainty Principle. But by the Fifth Solvay Conference held in October 1927
Heisenberg and Born concluded that the revolution was over and nothing
further was needed. It was at that last stage that Einstein's skepticism
turned to dismay. He believed that much had been accomplished, but the
reasons for the mechanics still needed to be understood.
Einstein's refusal to accept the revolution as complete reflected
his desire to see developed a model for the underlying causes from
which these apparent random statistical methods resulted. He did not
reject the idea that positions in space-time could never be completely
known but did not want to allow the uncertainty principle
to necessitate a seemingly random, non-deterministic mechanism by which
the laws of physics operated. Einstein himself was a statistical
thinker but disagreed that no more needed to be discovered and
clarified.
Einstein worked the rest of his life to discover a new theory that
would make sense of Quantum Mechanics and return causality to science,
what many now call, the Theory of Everything.
Bohr, meanwhile, was dismayed by none of the elements that troubled
Einstein. He made his own peace with the contradictions by proposing a principle of complementarity that emphasized the role of the observer over the observed.
Post-revolution: First stage
As
mentioned above, Einstein's position underwent significant
modifications over the course of the years. In the first stage, Einstein
refused to accept quantum indeterminism and sought to demonstrate that
the principle of indeterminacy could be violated, suggesting ingenious thought experiments
which should permit the accurate determination of incompatible
variables, such as position and velocity, or to explicitly reveal
simultaneously the wave and the particle aspects of the same process.
(The main source and substance for these thought experiments is solely
from Bohr’s account twenty years later.)
Bohr admits: “As regards the account of the conversations I am of
course aware that I am relying only on my own memory, just as I am
prepared for the possibility that many features of the development of
quantum theory, in which Einstein has played so large a part, may appear
to himself in a different light.”
Einstein's argument
The first serious attack by Einstein on the "orthodox" conception took place during the Fifth Solvay International Conference on Electrons and Photons in 1927. Einstein pointed out how it was possible to take advantage of the (universally accepted) laws of conservation of energy and of impulse (momentum) in order to obtain information on the state of a particle in a process of interference which, according to the principle of indeterminacy or that of complementarity, should not be accessible.
Figure A.
A monochromatic beam (one for which all the particles have the same
impulse) encounters a first screen, diffracts, and the diffracted wave
encounters a second screen with two slits, resulting in the formation of
an interference figure on the background F. As always, it is
assumed that only one particle at a time is able to pass the entire
mechanism. From the measure of the recoil of the screen S1,
according to Einstein, one can deduce from which slit the particle has
passed without destroying the wave aspects of the process.
Figure B. Einstein's slit.
In order to follow his argumentation and to evaluate Bohr's response,
it is convenient to refer to the experimental apparatus illustrated in
figure A. A beam of light perpendicular to the X axis propagates in the direction z and encounters a screen S1
with a narrow (relative to the wavelength of the ray) slit. After
having passed through the slit, the wave function diffracts with an
angular opening that causes it to encounter a second screen S2 with two slits. The successive propagation of the wave results in the formation of the interference figure on the final screen F.
At the passage through the two slits of the second screen S2, the wave aspects of the process become essential. In fact, it is precisely the interference between the two terms of the quantum superposition
corresponding to states in which the particle is localized in one of
the two slits which implies that the particle is "guided" preferably
into the zones of constructive interference and cannot end up in a point
in the zones of destructive interference (in which the wave function is
nullified). It is also important to note that any experiment designed
to evidence the "corpuscular" aspects of the process at the passage of the screen S2
(which, in this case, reduces to the determination of which slit the
particle has passed through) inevitably destroys the wave aspects,
implies the disappearance of the interference figure and the emergence
of two concentrated spots of diffraction which confirm our knowledge of
the trajectory followed by the particle.
At this point Einstein brings into play the first screen as well
and argues as follows: since the incident particles have velocities
(practically) perpendicular to the screen S1, and
since it is only the interaction with this screen that can cause a
deflection from the original direction of propagation, by the law of conservation of impulse
which implies that the sum of the impulses of two systems which
interact is conserved, if the incident particle is deviated toward the
top, the screen will recoil toward the bottom and vice versa. In
realistic conditions the mass of the screen is so large that it will
remain stationary, but, in principle, it is possible to measure even an
infinitesimal recoil. If we imagine taking the measurement of the
impulse of the screen in the direction X after every single
particle has passed, we can know, from the fact that the screen will be
found recoiled toward the top (bottom), whether the particle in question
has been deviated toward the bottom or top, and therefore through which
slit in S2 the particle has passed. But since the
determination of the direction of the recoil of the screen after the
particle has passed cannot influence the successive development of the
process, we will still have an interference figure on the screen F. The interference takes place precisely because the state of the system is the superposition
of two states whose wave functions are non-zero only near one of the
two slits. On the other hand, if every particle passes through only the
slit b or the slit c, then the set of systems is the
statistical mixture of the two states, which means that interference is
not possible. If Einstein is correct, then there is a violation of the
principle of indeterminacy.
This thought experiment was begun in a simpler form during the
General Discussion portion of the actual proceedings during the 1927
Solvay conference. In those official proceedings, Bohr’s reply is
recorded as: “I feel myself in a very difficult position because I don’t
understand precisely the point that Einstein is trying to make.”
Einstein had explained, “it could happen that the same elementary
process produces an action in two or several places on the screen. But
the interpretation, according to which psi squared expresses the
probability that this particular particle is found at a given point,
assumes an entirely peculiar mechanism of action at a distance.”
It is clear from this that Einstein was referring to separability, not
indeterminacy. In fact, Paul Ehrenfest wrote a letter to Bohr stating
that the 1927 thought experiments of Einstein had nothing to do with the
Uncertainty Relations, as Einstein had already accepted these “and for a
long time never doubted.”
Bohr's response
Bohr's response was to illustrate Einstein's idea more clearly using the diagram in Figure C. (Figure C shows a fixed screen S1
that is bolted down. Then try to imagine one that can slide up or down
along a rod instead of a fixed bolt.) Bohr observes that extremely
precise knowledge of any (potential) vertical motion of the screen is an
essential presupposition in Einstein's argument. In fact, if its
velocity in the direction Xbefore the passage of the
particle is not known with a precision substantially greater than that
induced by the recoil (that is, if it were already moving vertically
with an unknown and greater velocity than that which it derives as a
consequence of the contact with the particle), then the determination of
its motion after the passage of the particle would not give the
information we seek. However, Bohr continues, an extremely precise
determination of the velocity of the screen, when one applies the
principle of indeterminacy, implies an inevitable imprecision of its
position in the direction X. Before the process even begins, the
screen would therefore occupy an indeterminate position at least to a
certain extent (defined by the formalism). Now consider, for example,
the point d in figure A, where the interference is destructive.
Any displacement of the first screen would make the lengths of the two
paths, a–b–d and a–c–d, different from those indicated in the figure. If the difference between the two paths varies by half a wavelength, at point d
there will be constructive rather than destructive interference. The
ideal experiment must average over all the possible positions of the
screen S1, and, for every position, there corresponds, for a certain fixed point F,
a different type of interference, from the perfectly destructive to the
perfectly constructive. The effect of this averaging is that the
pattern of interference on the screen F will be uniformly grey. Once more, our attempt to evidence the corpuscular aspects in S2 has destroyed the possibility of interference in F, which depends crucially on the wave aspects.
Figure C. In order to realize Einstein's proposal, it is necessary to replace the first screen in Figure A (S1) with a diaphragm that can move vertically, such as this proposed by Bohr.
As Bohr recognized, for the understanding of this phenomenon "it is
decisive that, contrary to genuine instruments of measurement, these
bodies along with the particles would constitute, in the case under
examination, the system to which the quantum-mechanical formalism must
apply. With respect to the precision of the conditions under which one
can correctly apply the formalism, it is essential to include the entire
experimental apparatus. In fact, the introduction of any new apparatus,
such as a mirror, in the path of a particle could introduce new effects
of interference which influence essentially the predictions about the
results which will be registered at the end."
Further along, Bohr attempts to resolve this ambiguity concerning which
parts of the system should be considered macroscopic and which not:
In particular, it must be very clear that...the unambiguous
use of spatiotemporal concepts in the description of atomic phenomena
must be limited to the registration of observations which refer to
images on a photographic lens or to analogous practically irreversible
effects of amplification such as the formation of a drop of water around
an ion in a dark room.
Bohr's argument about the impossibility of using the apparatus
proposed by Einstein to violate the principle of indeterminacy depends
crucially on the fact that a macroscopic system (the screen S1)
obeys quantum laws. On the other hand, Bohr consistently held that, in
order to illustrate the microscopic aspects of reality, it is necessary
to set off a process of amplification, which involves macroscopic
apparatuses, whose fundamental characteristic is that of obeying
classical laws and which can be described in classical terms. This
ambiguity would later come back in the form of what is still called
today the measurement problem.
However, Bohr in his article refuting the EPR paper, states
“there is no question of a mechanical disturbance of the system under
investigation.”
Heisenberg quotes Bohr as saying, “I find all such assertions as
‘observation introduces uncertainty into the phenomenon’ inaccurate and
misleading.” Manjit Kumar’s book on the Bohr-Einstein debates finds these assertions by Bohr contrary to his arguments.
The principle of indeterminacy applied to time and energy
Figure D.
A wave extended longitudinally passes through a slit which remains open
only for a brief interval of time. Beyond the slit, there is a
spatially limited wave in the direction of propagation.
In many textbook examples and popular discussions of quantum
mechanics, the principle of indeterminacy is explained by reference to
the pair of variables position and velocity (or momentum). It is
important to note that the wave nature of physical processes implies
that there must exist another relation of indeterminacy: that between
time and energy. In order to comprehend this relation, it is convenient
to refer to the experiment illustrated in
Figure D, which results in the propagation of a wave which is limited in
spatial extension. Assume that, as illustrated in the figure, a ray
which is extremely extended longitudinally is propagated toward a screen
with a slit furnished with a shutter which remains open only for a very
brief interval of time . Beyond the slit, there will be a wave of limited spatial extension which continues to propagate toward the right.
A perfectly monochromatic wave (such as a musical note which
cannot be divided into harmonics) has infinite spatial extent. In order
to have a wave which is limited in spatial extension (which is
technically called a wave packet),
several waves of different frequencies must be superimposed and
distributed continuously within a certain interval of frequencies around
an average value, such as .
It then happens that at a certain instant, there exists a spatial region
(which moves over time) in which the contributions of the various
fields of the superposition add up constructively. Nonetheless,
according to a precise mathematical theorem, as we move far away from
this region, the phases
of the various fields, at any specified point, are distributed causally
and destructive interference is produced. The region in which the wave
has non-zero amplitude is therefore spatially limited. It is easy to
demonstrate that, if the wave has a spatial extension equal to (which means, in our example, that the shutter has remained open for a time
where v is the velocity of the wave), then the wave contains (or is a
superposition of) various monochromatic waves whose frequencies cover an
interval which satisfies the relation:
Remembering that in the universal relation of Planck, frequency and energy are proportional:
it follows immediately from the preceding inequality that the
particle associated with the wave should possess an energy which is not
perfectly defined (since different frequencies are involved in the
superposition) and consequently there is indeterminacy in energy:
From this it follows immediately that:
which is the relation of indeterminacy between time and energy.
Einstein's second criticism
Einstein's
thought experiment of 1930 as designed by Bohr. Einstein's box was
supposed to prove the violation of the indeterminacy relation between
time and energy.
At the sixth Congress of Solvay in 1930, the indeterminacy relation
just discussed was Einstein's target of criticism. His idea contemplates
the existence of an experimental apparatus which was subsequently
designed by Bohr in such a way as to emphasize the essential elements
and the key points which he would use in his response.
Einstein considers a box (called Einstein's box; see
figure) containing electromagnetic radiation and a clock which controls
the opening of a shutter which covers a hole made in one of the walls of
the box. The shutter uncovers the hole for a time
which can be chosen arbitrarily. During the opening, we are to suppose
that a photon, from among those inside the box, escapes through the
hole. In this way a wave of limited spatial extension has been created,
following the explanation given above. In order to challenge the
indeterminacy relation between time and energy, it is necessary to find a
way to determine with adequate precision the energy that the photon has
brought with it. At this point, Einstein turns to his celebrated
relation between mass and energy of special relativity: .
From this it follows that knowledge of the mass of an object provides a
precise indication about its energy. The argument is therefore very
simple: if one weighs the box before and after the opening of the
shutter and if a certain amount of energy has escaped from the box, the
box will be lighter. The variation in mass multiplied by
will provide precise knowledge of the energy emitted.
Moreover, the clock will indicate the precise time at which the event of
the particle's emission took place. Since, in principle, the mass of
the box can be determined to an arbitrary degree of accuracy, the energy
emitted can be determined with a precision as accurate as one desires. Therefore, the product can be rendered less than what is implied by the principle of indeterminacy.
The idea is particularly acute and the argument seemed unassailable.
It's important to consider the impact of all of these exchanges on the
people involved at the time. Leon Rosenfeld, a scientist who had participated in the Congress, described the event several years later:
It was a real shock for Bohr...who, at first, could not think
of a solution. For the entire evening he was extremely agitated, and he
continued passing from one scientist to another, seeking to persuade
them that it could not be the case, that it would have been the end of
physics if Einstein were right; but he couldn't come up with any way to
resolve the paradox. I will never forget the image of the two
antagonists as they left the club: Einstein, with his tall and
commanding figure, who walked tranquilly, with a mildly ironic smile,
and Bohr who trotted along beside him, full of excitement...The morning
after saw the triumph of Bohr.
Bohr's Triumph
The
"Triumph of Bohr" consisted in his demonstrating, once again, that
Einstein's subtle argument was not conclusive, but even more so in the
way that he arrived at this conclusion by appealing precisely to one of
the great ideas of Einstein: the principle of equivalence between
gravitational mass and inertial mass, together with the time dilation of
special relativity, and a consequence of these—the Gravitational redshift.
Bohr showed that, in order for Einstein's experiment to function, the
box would have to be suspended on a spring in the middle of a
gravitational field. In order to obtain a measurement of the weight of
the box, a pointer would have to be attached to the box which
corresponded with the index on a scale. After the release of a photon, a
mass could be added to the box to restore it to its original position and this would allow us to determine the energy that was lost when the photon left. The box is immersed in a gravitational field of strength , and the gravitational redshift affects the speed of the clock, yielding uncertainty in the time
required for the pointer to return to its original position. Bohr gave
the following calculation establishing the uncertainty relation .
Let the uncertainty in the mass be denoted by . Let the error in the position of the pointer be . Adding the load to the box imparts a momentum that we can measure with an accuracy , where ≈ . Clearly , and therefore . By the redshift formula (which follows from the principle of equivalence and the time dilation), the uncertainty in the time is , and , and so . We have therefore proven the claimed .
More recent analyses of the photon box debate questions Bohr’s
understanding of Einstein’s thought experiment, referring instead to a
prelude to the EPR paper, focusing on inseparability rather than
indeterminism being at issue.
The second phase of Einstein's "debate" with Bohr and the orthodox
interpretation is characterized by an acceptance of the fact that it is,
as a practical matter, impossible to simultaneously determine the
values of certain incompatible quantities, but the rejection that this
implies that these quantities do not actually have precise values.
Einstein rejects the probabilistic interpretation of Born and insists that quantum probabilities are epistemic and not ontological
in nature. As a consequence, the theory must be incomplete in some way.
He recognizes the great value of the theory, but suggests that it
"does not tell the whole story", and, while providing an appropriate
description at a certain level, it gives no information on the more
fundamental underlying level:
I have the greatest consideration for the goals which are
pursued by the physicists of the latest generation which go under the
name of quantum mechanics, and I believe that this theory represents a
profound level of truth, but I also believe that the restriction to laws
of a statistical nature will turn out to be transitory....Without doubt
quantum mechanics has grasped an important fragment of the truth and
will be a paragon for all future fundamental theories, for the fact that
it must be deducible as a limiting case from such foundations, just as
electrostatics is deducible from Maxwell's equations of the
electromagnetic field or as thermodynamics is deducible from statistical
mechanics.
These thoughts of Einstein would set off a line of research into hidden variable theories, such as the Bohm interpretation, in an attempt to complete the edifice of quantum theory. If quantum mechanics can be made complete in Einstein's sense, it cannot be done locally; this fact was demonstrated by John Stewart Bell with the formulation of Bell's inequality in 1964.
Although, the Bell inequality ruled out local hidden variable theories,
Bohm’s theory was not ruled out. A 2007 experiment ruled out a large
class of non-Bohmian non-local hidden variable theories, though not
Bohmian mechanics itself.
In 1935 Einstein, Boris Podolsky and Nathan Rosen developed an argument, published in the magazine Physical Review with the title Can Quantum-Mechanical Description of Physical Reality Be Considered Complete?,
based on an entangled state of two systems. Before coming to this
argument, it is necessary to formulate another hypothesis that comes out
of Einstein's work in relativity: the principle of locality. The elements of physical reality which are objectively possessed cannot be influenced instantaneously at a distance.
David Bohm picked up the EPR argument in 1951. In his textbook Quantum Theory, he reformulated it in terms of an entangled state of two particles, which can be summarized as follows:
1) Consider a system of two photons which at time t are located, respectively, in the spatially distant regions A and B and which are also in the entangled state of polarization described below:
2) At time t the photon in region A is tested for vertical
polarization. Suppose that the result of the measurement is that the
photon passes through the filter. According to the reduction of the wave
packet, the result is that, at time t + dt, the system becomes
3) At this point, the observer in A who carried out the first measurement on photon 1,
without doing anything else that could disturb the system or the other
photon ("assumption (R)", below), can predict with certainty that photon
2 will pass a test of vertical polarization. It follows that photon 2 possesses an element of physical reality: that of having a vertical polarization.
4) According to the assumption of locality, it cannot have been
the action carried out in A which created this element of reality for
photon 2. Therefore, we must conclude that the photon possessed the property of being able to pass the vertical polarization test before and independently of the measurement of photon 1.
5) At time t, the observer in A could have decided
to carry out a test of polarization at 45°, obtaining a certain result,
for example, that the photon passes the test. In that case, he could
have concluded that photon 2 turned out to be polarized at 45°. Alternatively, if the photon did not pass the test, he could have concluded that photon 2 turned out to be polarized at 135°. Combining one of these alternatives with the conclusion reached in 4, it seems that photon 2,
before the measurement took place, possessed both the property of being
able to pass with certainty a test of vertical polarization and the
property of being able to pass with certainty a test of polarization at
either 45° or 135°. These properties are incompatible according to the
formalism.
6) Since natural and obvious requirements have forced the conclusion that photon 2
simultaneously possesses incompatible properties, this means that, even
if it is not possible to determine these properties simultaneously and
with arbitrary precision, they are nevertheless possessed objectively by
the system. But quantum mechanics denies this possibility and it is
therefore an incomplete theory.
Bohr's response
Bohr's response to this argument was published, five months later than the original publication of EPR, in the same magazine Physical Review and with exactly the same title as the original. The crucial point of Bohr's answer is distilled in a passage which he later had republished in Paul Arthur Schilpp's book Albert Einstein, scientist-philosopher in honor of the seventieth birthday of Einstein. Bohr attacks assumption (R) of EPR by stating:
The statement of the criterion in question is ambiguous with
regard to the expression "without disturbing the system in any way".
Naturally, in this case no mechanical disturbance of the system under
examination can take place in the crucial stage of the process of
measurement. But even in this stage there arises the essential problem
of an influence on the precise conditions which define the possible
types of prediction which regard the subsequent behaviour of the
system...their arguments do not justify their conclusion that the
quantum description turns out to be essentially incomplete...This
description can be characterized as a rational use of the possibilities
of an unambiguous interpretation of the process of measurement
compatible with the finite and uncontrollable interaction between the
object and the instrument of measurement in the context of quantum
theory.
Confirmatory experiments
Chien-Shiung Wu
Years after the exposition of Einstein via his EPR experiment, many
physicists started performing experiments to show that Einstein's view
of a spooky action in a distance is indeed consistent with the laws of
physics. The first experiment to definitively prove that this was the
case was in 1949, when physicists Chien-Shiung Wu and her colleague Irving Shaknov showcased this theory in real time using photons. Their work was published in the new year of the succeeding decade.
Later in 1975, Alain Aspect proposed in an article of an experiment meticulous enough to be irrefutable: Proposed experiment to test the non-separability of quantum mechanics. This led Aspect, together with physicists Philippe Grangier, Gérard Roger, and Jean Dalibard)
to set up several increasingly complex experiments between 1980 and
1982 that further established quantum entanglement. Finally in 1998, the
Geneva experiment tested the correlation between two detectors set 30
kilometres apart, virtually across the whole city, using the Swiss
optical fibre telecommunication network. The distance gave the necessary
time to commute the angles of the polarizers. It was therefore possible
to have a completely random electrical shunting. Furthermore, the two
distant polarizers were entirely independent. The measurements were
recorded on each side, and compared after each experiment by dating each
measurement using an atomic clock. The experiment once again verified
entanglement under the strictest and most ideal conditions possible. If
Aspect's experiment implied that a hypothetical coordination signal
travel twice as fast as c, Geneva's reached 10 million times c.
Post-revolution: Fourth stage
In his last writing on the topic,
Einstein further refined his position, making it completely clear that
what really disturbed him about the quantum theory was the problem of
the total renunciation of all minimal standards of realism, even at the
microscopic level, that the acceptance of the completeness of the theory
implied. Although the majority of experts in the field agree that Einstein was wrong, the current understanding is still not complete (see Interpretation of quantum mechanics).