A twin prime is a prime number
that is either 2 less or 2 more than another prime number—for example,
either member of the twin prime pair (41, 43). In other words, a twin
prime is a prime that has a prime gap of two. Sometimes the term twin prime is used for a pair of twin primes; an alternative name for this is prime twin or prime pair.
Twin primes become increasingly rare as one examines larger
ranges, in keeping with the general tendency of gaps between adjacent
primes to become larger as the numbers themselves get larger. However,
it is unknown whether there are infinitely many twin primes (the
so-called twin prime conjecture) or if there is a largest pair. The breakthrough work of Yitang Zhang in 2013, as well as work by James Maynard, Terence Tao
and others, has made substantial progress towards proving that there
are infinitely many twin primes, but at present this remains unsolved.
Properties
Usually the pair (2, 3) is not considered to be a pair of twin primes.
Since 2 is the only even prime, this pair is the only pair of prime
numbers that differ by one; thus twin primes are as closely spaced as
possible for any other two primes.
Five is the only prime that belongs to two pairs, as every twin prime pair greater than is of the form for some natural numbern; that is, the number between the two primes is a multiple of 6. As a result, the sum of any pair of twin primes (other than 3 and 5) is divisible by 12.
In 1915, Viggo Brun showed that the sum of reciprocals of the twin primes was convergent. This famous result, called Brun's theorem, was the first use of the Brun sieve and helped initiate the development of modern sieve theory. The modern version of Brun's argument can be used to show that the number of twin primes less than N does not exceed
for some absolute constant C > 0. In fact, it is bounded above by
where , where C2 is the twin prime constant, given below.
Twin prime conjecture
The question of whether there exist infinitely many twin primes has been one of the great open questions in number theory for many years. This is the content of the twin prime conjecture, which states that there are infinitely many primes p such that p + 2 is also prime. In 1849, de Polignac made the more general conjecture that for every natural numberk, there are infinitely many primes p such that p + 2k is also prime. The case k = 1 of de Polignac's conjecture is the twin prime conjecture.
A stronger form of the twin prime conjecture, the
Hardy–Littlewood conjecture (see below), postulates a distribution law
for twin primes akin to the prime number theorem.
On April 17, 2013, Yitang Zhang announced a proof that for some integer N that is less than 70 million, there are infinitely many pairs of primes that differ by N. Zhang's paper was accepted by Annals of Mathematics in early May 2013. Terence Tao subsequently proposed a Polymath Project collaborative effort to optimize Zhang's bound. As of April 14, 2014, one year after Zhang's announcement, the bound has been reduced to 246. Further, assuming the Elliott–Halberstam conjecture and its generalized form, the Polymath project wiki states that the bound has been reduced to 12 and 6, respectively.
These improved bounds were discovered using a different approach that
was simpler than Zhang's and was discovered independently by James
Maynard and Terence Tao. This second approach also gave bounds for the
smallest f(m) needed to guarantee that infinitely many intervals of width f(m) contain at least m primes.
A strengthening of Goldbach’s conjecture, if proved, would also prove there is an infinite number of twin primes.
Other theorems weaker than the twin prime conjecture
In 1940, Paul Erdős showed that there is a constantc < 1 and infinitely many primes p such that (p′ − p) < (c ln p) where p′ denotes the next prime after p. What this means is that we can find infinitely many intervals that contain two primes (p,p′)
as long as we let these intervals grow slowly in size as we move to
bigger and bigger primes. Here, "grow slowly" means that the length of
these intervals can grow logarithmically. This result was successively
improved; in 1986 Helmut Maier showed that a constant c < 0.25 can be used. In 2004 Daniel Goldston and Cem Yıldırım showed that the constant could be improved further to c = 0.085786… In 2005, Goldston, János Pintz and Yıldırım established that c can be chosen to be arbitrarily small, i.e.
On the other hand, this result does not rule out that there may not
be infinitely many intervals that contain two primes if we only allow
the intervals to grow in size as, for example, c ln ln p.
By assuming the Elliott–Halberstam conjecture or a slightly weaker version, they were able to show that there are infinitely many n such that at least two of n, n + 2, n + 6, n + 8, n + 12, n + 18, or n + 20 are prime. Under a stronger hypothesis they showed that for infinitely many n, at least two of n, n + 2, n + 4, and n + 6 are prime.
is a major improvement on the Goldston–Graham–Pintz–Yıldırım result. The Polymath Project optimization of Zhang's bound and the work of Maynard have reduced the bound to N = 246.
Conjectures
First Hardy–Littlewood conjecture
The Hardy–Littlewood conjecture (named after G. H. Hardy and John Littlewood) is a generalization of the twin prime conjecture. It is concerned with the distribution of prime constellations, including twin primes, in analogy to the prime number theorem. Let π2(x) denote the number of primes p ≤ x such that p + 2 is also prime. Define the twin prime constantC2 as
(here the product extends over all prime numbers p ≥ 3). Then a special case of the first Hardy-Littlewood conjecture is that
in the sense that the quotient of the two expressions tends to 1 as x approaches infinity. (The second ~ is not part of the conjecture and is proven by integration by parts.)
The conjecture can be justified (but not proven) by assuming that 1 / ln t describes the density function
of the prime distribution. This assumption, which is suggested by the
prime number theorem, implies the twin prime conjecture, as shown in the
formula for π2(x) above.
Polignac's conjecture from 1849 states that for every positive even natural number k, there are infinitely many consecutive prime pairs p and p′ such that p′ − p = k (i.e. there are infinitely many prime gaps of size k). The case k = 2 is the twin prime conjecture. The conjecture has not yet been proven or disproven for any specific value of k, but Zhang's result proves that it is true for at least one (currently unknown) value of k. Indeed, if such a k did not exist, then for any positive even natural number N there are at most finitely many n such that pn+1 − pn = m for all m < N and so for n large enough we have pn+1 − pn > N, which would contradict Zhang's result.
Large twin primes
Beginning in 2007, two distributed computing projects, Twin Prime Search and PrimeGrid, have produced several record-largest twin primes. As of September 2018, the current largest twin prime pair known is 2996863034895 · 21290000 ± 1, with 388,342 decimal digits. It was discovered in September 2016.
There are 808,675,888,577,436 twin prime pairs below 1018.
An empirical analysis of all prime pairs up to 4.35 · 1015 shows that if the number of such pairs less than x is f(x)·x/(log x)2 then f(x) is about 1.7 for small x and decreases towards about 1.3 as x tends to infinity. The limiting value of f(x) is conjectured to equal twice the twin prime constant (OEIS: A114907) (not to be confused with Brun's constant), according to the Hardy–Littlewood conjecture.
Other elementary properties
Every
third odd number is divisible by 3, which requires that no three
successive odd numbers can be prime unless one of them is 3. Five is
therefore the only prime that is part of two twin prime pairs. The lower
member of a pair is by definition a Chen prime.
It has been proven that the pair (m, m + 2) is a twin prime if and only if
If m − 4 or m + 6 is also prime then the three primes are called a prime triplet.
For a twin prime pair of the form (6n − 1, 6n + 1) for some natural number n > 1, n must have units digit 0, 2, 3, 5, 7, or 8 (OEIS: A002822).
Isolated prime
An isolated prime (also known as single prime or non-twin prime) is a prime number p such that neither p − 2 nor p + 2 is prime. In other words, p is not part of a twin prime pair. For example, 23 is an isolated prime, since 21 and 25 are both composite.
It follows from Brun's theorem that almost all primes are isolated in the sense that
the ratio of the number of isolated primes less than a given threshold n and the number of all primes less than n tends to 1 as n tends to infinity.
The conjecture has been shown to hold for all integers less than 4 × 1018, but remains unproven despite considerable effort.
History
On 7 June 1742, the German mathematician Christian Goldbach wrote a letter to Leonhard Euler (letter XLIII), in which he proposed the following conjecture:
Every integer that can be written as the sum
of two primes can also be written as the sum of as many primes as one
wishes, until all terms are units.
Goldbach was following the now-abandoned convention of considering 1 to be a prime number, so that a sum of units would indeed be a sum of primes.
He then proposed a second conjecture in the margin of his letter, which implies the first:
... eine jede Zahl, die grösser ist als 2, ein aggregatum trium numerorum primorum sey.
Every integer greater than 2 can be written as the sum of three primes.
Euler replied in a letter dated 30 June 1742 and reminded Goldbach of an earlier conversation they had had ("... so Ew vormals mit mir communicirt haben ..."), in which Goldbach had remarked that the first of those two conjectures would follow from the statement
Every positive even integer can be written as the sum of two primes.
This is in fact equivalent to his second, marginal conjecture.
In the letter dated 30 June 1742, Euler stated:
Dass ...
ein jeder numerus par eine summa duorum primorum sey, halte ich für ein
ganz gewisses theorema, ungeachtet ich dasselbe nicht demonstriren
kann. That ... every even integer is a sum of two primes, I regard as a completely certain theorem, although I cannot prove it.
Each of the three conjectures above has a natural analog in terms of
the modern definition of a prime, under which 1 is excluded.
A modern version of the first conjecture is:
Every integer that can be written as the sum
of two primes can also be written as the sum of as many primes as one
wishes, until either all terms are two (if the integer is even) or one
term is three and all other terms are two (if the integer is odd).
A modern version of the marginal conjecture is:
Every integer greater than 5 can be written as the sum of three primes.
And a modern version of Goldbach's older conjecture of which Euler reminded him is:
Every even integer greater than 2 can be written as the sum of two primes.
These modern versions might not be entirely equivalent to the
corresponding original statements. For example, if there were an even
integer larger than 4, for
a prime, that could not be expressed as the sum of two primes in the
modern sense, then it would be a counterexample to the modern version
of the third conjecture (without being a counterexample to the original
version). The modern version is thus probably stronger (but in order to
confirm that, one would have to prove that the first version, freely
applied to any positive even integer , could not possibly rule out the existence of such a specific counterexample ).
In any case, the modern statements have the same relationships with
each other as the older statements did. That is, the second and third
modern statements are equivalent, and either implies the first modern
statement.
The third modern statement (equivalent to the second) is the form
in which the conjecture is usually expressed today. It is also known as
the "strong", "even", or "binary" Goldbach conjecture. A weaker form of the second modern statement, known as "Goldbach's weak conjecture", the "odd Goldbach conjecture", or the "ternary Goldbach conjecture," asserts that
Every odd integer greater than 7 can be written as the sum of three odd primes.
A proof for the weak conjecture was proposed in 2013 by Harald Helfgott. Helfgott's proof has not yet appeared in a peer-reviewed publication, though was accepted for publication in the Annals of Mathematics Studies series in 2015, and has been undergoing further review and revision since. The weak conjecture would be a corollary of the strong conjecture: if n – 3 is a sum of two primes, then n is a sum of three primes. However, the converse implication and thus the strong Goldbach conjecture remain unproven.
Verified results
For small values of n, the strong Goldbach conjecture (and
hence the weak Goldbach conjecture) can be verified directly. For
instance, in 1938, Nils Pipping laboriously verified the conjecture up
to n ≤ 105. With the advent of computers, many more values of n have been checked; T. Oliveira e Silva ran a distributed computer search that has verified the conjecture for n ≤ 4 × 1018 (and double-checked up to 4 × 1017) as of 2013. One record from this search is that 3325581707333960528 is the smallest number that cannot be written as a sum of two primes where one is smaller than 9781.
Heuristic justification
Statistical considerations that focus on the probabilistic distribution of prime numbers present informal evidence in favour of the conjecture (in both the weak and strong forms) for sufficiently large
integers: the greater the integer, the more ways there are available
for that number to be represented as the sum of two or three other
numbers, and the more "likely" it becomes that at least one of these
representations consists entirely of primes.
Number of ways to write an even number n as the sum of two primes (4 ≤ n ≤ 1,000), (sequence A002375 in the OEIS)
Number of ways to write an even number n as the sum of two primes (4 ≤ n ≤ 1000000)
A very crude version of the heuristic probabilistic argument (for the strong form of the Goldbach conjecture) is as follows. The prime number theorem asserts that an integer m selected at random has roughly a chance of being prime. Thus if n is a large even integer and m is a number between 3 and n/2, then one might expect the probability of m and n − m simultaneously being prime to be . If one pursues this heuristic, one might expect the total number of ways to write a large even integer n as the sum of two odd primes to be roughly
Since , this quantity goes to infinity as n
increases, and we would expect that every large even integer has not
just one representation as the sum of two primes, but in fact very many
such representations.
This heuristic argument is actually somewhat inaccurate, because it assumes that the events of m and n − m being prime are statistically independent of each other. For instance, if m is odd, then n − m is also odd, and if m is even, then n − m is even, a non-trivial relation because, besides the number 2, only odd numbers can be prime. Similarly, if n is divisible by 3, and m was already a prime distinct from 3, then n − m would also be coprime to 3 and thus be slightly more likely to be prime than a general number. Pursuing this type of analysis more carefully, G. H. Hardy and John Edensor Littlewood in 1923 conjectured (as part of their Hardy–Littlewood prime tuple conjecture) that for any fixed c ≥ 2, the number of representations of a large integer n as the sum of c primes with should be asymptotically equal to
where the product is over all primes p, and is the number of solutions to the equation
in modular arithmetic, subject to the constraints. This formula has been rigorously proven to be asymptotically valid for c ≥ 3 from the work of Ivan Matveevich Vinogradov, but is still only a conjecture when . In the latter case, the above formula simplifies to 0 when n is odd, and to
This is sometimes known as the extended Goldbach conjecture. The strong Goldbach conjecture is in fact very similar to the twin prime conjecture, and the two conjectures are believed to be of roughly comparable difficulty.
The Goldbach partition functions shown here can be displayed as histograms, which illustrate the above equations. See Goldbach's comet for more information.
Goldbach's comet also suggests that there are tight upper and
lower bounds on the number of representatives, and that the modulo 6 of 2n plays a part in the number of representations.
The number of representations is about , from and the Prime Number Theorem. If each c is composite, then it must have a prime factor less than or equal to the square root of , by the method outlined in trial division.
This leads to an expectation of representations.
Rigorous results
The strong Goldbach conjecture is much more difficult than the weak Goldbach conjecture. Using Vinogradov's method, Nikolai Chudakov, Johannes van der Corput, and Theodor Estermann showed that almost all
even numbers can be written as the sum of two primes (in the sense that
the fraction of even numbers which can be so written tends towards 1).
In 1930, Lev Schnirelmann proved that any natural number greater than 1 can be written as the sum of not more than C prime numbers, where C is an effectively computable constant; see Schnirelmann density. Schnirelmann's constant is the lowest number C with this property. Schnirelmann himself obtained C < 800000. This result was subsequently enhanced by many authors, such as Olivier Ramaré, who in 1995 showed that every even number n ≥ 4
is in fact the sum of at most 6 primes. The best known result currently
stems from the proof of the weak Goldbach conjecture by Harald Helfgott, which directly implies that every even number n ≥ 4 is the sum of at most 4 primes.
In 1924, Hardy and Littlewood showed under the assumption of the generalized Riemann hypothesis that the number of even numbers up to X violating the Goldbach conjecture is much less than for small c.
In 1975, Hugh Montgomery and Robert Charles Vaughan
showed that "most" even numbers are expressible as the sum of two
primes. More precisely, they showed that there exist positive constants
c and C such that for all sufficiently large numbers N, every even number less than N is the sum of two primes, with at most exceptions. In particular, the set of even integers that are not the sum of two primes has density zero.
In 1951, Yuri Linnik proved the existence of a constant K such that every sufficiently large even number is the sum of two primes and at most K powers of 2. Roger Heath-Brown and Jan-Christoph Schlage-Puchta found in 2002 that K = 13 works.
Related problems
Although Goldbach's conjecture implies that every positive integer
greater than one can be written as a sum of at most three primes, it is
not always possible to find such a sum using a greedy algorithm that uses the largest possible prime at each step. The Pillai sequence tracks the numbers requiring the largest number of primes in their greedy representations.
Similar problems to Goldbach's conjecture exist in which primes
are replaced by other particular sets of numbers, such as the squares:
Hardy and Littlewood listed as their Conjecture I: "Every large odd number (n > 5) is the sum of a prime and the double of a prime" (Mathematics Magazine, 66.1 (1993): 45–47). This conjecture is known as Lemoine's conjecture and is also called Levy's conjecture.
The Goldbach conjecture for practical numbers, a prime-like sequence of integers, was stated by Margenstern in 1984, and proved by Melfi in 1996: every even number is a sum of two practical numbers.
A strengthening of the Goldbach conjecture proposed by Harvey Dubner states that every even integer greater than 4,208 is the sum of two twin primes. Only 34 even integers less than 4,208 are not the sum of two twin primes. Dubner has verified computationally that this list is complete up to 2×1010. A proof of this stronger conjecture would not only imply Goldbach's conjecture, but also the twin prime conjecture.
In popular culture
Goldbach's Conjecture (Chinese: 哥德巴赫猜想) is the title of the biography of Chinese mathematician and number theorist Chen Jingrun, written by Xu Chi.
Cantor's theory of transfinite numbers was originally regarded as so counter-intuitive – even shocking – that it encountered resistance from mathematical contemporaries such as Leopold Kronecker and Henri Poincaré and later from Hermann Weyl and L. E. J. Brouwer, while Ludwig Wittgenstein raised philosophical objections. Cantor, a devout Lutheran Christian, believed the theory had been communicated to him by God. Some Christian theologians (particularly neo-Scholastics) saw Cantor's work as a challenge to the uniqueness of the absolute infinity in the nature of God – on one occasion equating the theory of transfinite numbers with pantheism –
a proposition that Cantor vigorously rejected. It is important to note
that not all theologians were against Cantor's theory, prominent
neo-scholastic philosopher Constantin Gutberlet was in favor and
Cardinal Johann Baptist Franzelin accepted as a valid theory (after Cantor made some important clarifications).
The objections to Cantor's work were occasionally fierce: Leopold Kronecker's
public opposition and personal attacks included describing Cantor as a
"scientific charlatan", a "renegade" and a "corrupter of youth".
Kronecker objected to Cantor's proofs that the algebraic numbers are
countable, and that the transcendental numbers are uncountable, results
now included in a standard mathematics curriculum. Writing decades after
Cantor's death, Wittgenstein lamented that mathematics is "ridden
through and through with the pernicious idioms of set theory", which he
dismissed as "utter nonsense" that is "laughable" and "wrong".
Cantor's recurring bouts of depression from 1884 to the end of his life
have been blamed on the hostile attitude of many of his contemporaries, though some have explained these episodes as probable manifestations of a bipolar disorder.
The harsh criticism has been matched by later accolades. In 1904, the Royal Society awarded Cantor its Sylvester Medal, the highest honor it can confer for work in mathematics. David Hilbert defended it from its critics by declaring, "No one shall expel us from the paradise that Cantor has created."
Life of Georg Cantor
Youth and studies
Cantor, around 1870
Georg Cantor was born in 1845 in the western merchant colony of Saint Petersburg,
Russia, and brought up in the city until he was eleven. Cantor, the
oldest of six children, was regarded as an outstanding violinist. His
grandfather Franz Böhm (1788–1846) (the violinist Joseph Böhm's brother) was a well-known musician and soloist in a Russian imperial orchestra. Cantor's father had been a member of the Saint Petersburg stock exchange; when he became ill, the family moved to Germany in 1856, first to Wiesbaden, then to Frankfurt, seeking milder winters than those of Saint Petersburg. In 1860, Cantor graduated with distinction from the Realschule in Darmstadt; his exceptional skills in mathematics, trigonometry in particular, were noted. In August 1862, he then graduated from the "Höhere Gewerbeschule Darmstadt", now the Technische Universität Darmstadt. In 1862, Cantor entered the Swiss Federal Polytechnic. After receiving a substantial inheritance upon his father's death in June 1863, Cantor shifted his studies to the University of Berlin, attending lectures by Leopold Kronecker, Karl Weierstrass and Ernst Kummer. He spent the summer of 1866 at the University of Göttingen, then and later a center for mathematical research. Cantor was a good student, and he received his doctorate degree in 1867.
Teacher and researcher
Cantor submitted his dissertation
on number theory at the University of Berlin in 1867. After teaching
briefly in a Berlin girls' school, Cantor took up a position at the University of Halle, where he spent his entire career. He was awarded the requisite habilitation for his thesis, also on number theory, which he presented in 1869 upon his appointment at Halle University.
In 1874, Cantor married Vally Guttmann. They had six children,
the last (Rudolph) born in 1886. Cantor was able to support a family
despite modest academic pay, thanks to his inheritance from his father.
During his honeymoon in the Harz mountains, Cantor spent much time in mathematical discussions with Richard Dedekind, whom he had met two years earlier while on Swiss holiday.
Cantor was promoted to extraordinary professor in 1872 and made full professor in 1879. To attain the latter rank at the age of 34 was a notable accomplishment, but Cantor desired a chair
at a more prestigious university, in particular at Berlin, at that time
the leading German university. However, his work encountered too much
opposition for that to be possible.
Kronecker, who headed mathematics at Berlin until his death in 1891,
became increasingly uncomfortable with the prospect of having Cantor as a
colleague, perceiving him as a "corrupter of youth" for teaching his ideas to a younger generation of mathematicians.
Worse yet, Kronecker, a well-established figure within the mathematical
community and Cantor's former professor, disagreed fundamentally with
the thrust of Cantor's work ever since he intentionally delayed the
publication of Cantor's first major publication in 1874. Kronecker, now seen as one of the founders of the constructive viewpoint in mathematics,
disliked much of Cantor's set theory because it asserted the existence
of sets satisfying certain properties, without giving specific examples
of sets whose members did indeed satisfy those properties. Whenever
Cantor applied for a post in Berlin, he was declined, and it usually
involved Kronecker, so Cantor came to believe that Kronecker's stance would make it impossible for him ever to leave Halle.
In 1881, Cantor's Halle colleague Eduard Heine died, creating a vacant chair. Halle accepted Cantor's suggestion that it be offered to Dedekind, Heinrich M. Weber and Franz Mertens,
in that order, but each declined the chair after being offered it.
Friedrich Wangerin was eventually appointed, but he was never close to
Cantor.
In 1882, the mathematical correspondence between Cantor and
Dedekind came to an end, apparently as a result of Dedekind's declining
the chair at Halle. Cantor also began another important correspondence, with Gösta Mittag-Leffler in Sweden, and soon began to publish in Mittag-Leffler's journal Acta Mathematica.
But in 1885, Mittag-Leffler was concerned about the philosophical
nature and new terminology in a paper Cantor had submitted to Acta. He asked Cantor to withdraw the paper from Acta
while it was in proof, writing that it was "... about one hundred years
too soon." Cantor complied, but then curtailed his relationship and
correspondence with Mittag-Leffler, writing to a third party, "Had
Mittag-Leffler had his way, I should have to wait until the year 1984,
which to me seemed too great a demand! ... But of course I never want to
know anything again about Acta Mathematica."
Cantor suffered his first known bout of depression in May 1884.
Criticism of his work weighed on his mind: every one of the fifty-two
letters he wrote to Mittag-Leffler in 1884 mentioned Kronecker. A
passage from one of these letters is revealing of the damage to Cantor's
self-confidence:
... I don't know when I shall
return to the continuation of my scientific work. At the moment I can do
absolutely nothing with it, and limit myself to the most necessary duty
of my lectures; how much happier I would be to be scientifically
active, if only I had the necessary mental freshness.
This crisis led him to apply to lecture on philosophy rather than mathematics. He also began an intense study of Elizabethan literature thinking there might be evidence that Francis Bacon wrote the plays attributed to William Shakespeare (see Shakespearean authorship question); this ultimately resulted in two pamphlets, published in 1896 and 1897.
Cantor recovered soon thereafter, and subsequently made further important contributions, including his diagonal argument and theorem.
However, he never again attained the high level of his remarkable
papers of 1874–84, even after Kronecker's death on December 29, 1891.
He eventually sought, and achieved, a reconciliation with Kronecker.
Nevertheless, the philosophical disagreements and difficulties dividing
them persisted.
In 1889, Cantor was instrumental in founding the German Mathematical Society
and chaired its first meeting in Halle in 1891, where he first
introduced his diagonal argument; his reputation was strong enough,
despite Kronecker's opposition to his work, to ensure he was elected as
the first president of this society. Setting aside the animosity
Kronecker had displayed towards him, Cantor invited him to address the
meeting, but Kronecker was unable to do so because his wife was dying
from injuries sustained in a skiing accident at the time. Georg Cantor
was also instrumental in the establishment of the first International Congress of Mathematicians, which was held in Zürich, Switzerland, in 1897.
Later years and death
After Cantor's 1884 hospitalization, there is no record that he was in any sanatorium again until 1899.
Soon after that second hospitalization, Cantor's youngest son Rudolph
died suddenly on December 16 (Cantor was delivering a lecture on his
views on Baconian theory and William Shakespeare), and this tragedy drained Cantor of much of his passion for mathematics. Cantor was again hospitalized in 1903. One year later, he was outraged and agitated by a paper presented by Julius König at the Third International Congress of Mathematicians.
The paper attempted to prove that the basic tenets of transfinite set
theory were false. Since the paper had been read in front of his
daughters and colleagues, Cantor perceived himself as having been
publicly humiliated. Although Ernst Zermelo demonstrated less than a day later that König's proof had failed, Cantor remained shaken, and momentarily questioning God.
Cantor suffered from chronic depression for the rest of his life, for
which he was excused from teaching on several occasions and repeatedly
confined in various sanatoria. The events of 1904 preceded a series of
hospitalizations at intervals of two or three years. He did not abandon mathematics completely, however, lecturing on the paradoxes of set theory (Burali-Forti paradox, Cantor's paradox, and Russell's paradox) to a meeting of the Deutsche Mathematiker-Vereinigung in 1903, and attending the International Congress of Mathematicians at Heidelberg in 1904.
In 1911, Cantor was one of the distinguished foreign scholars invited to attend the 500th anniversary of the founding of the University of St. Andrews in Scotland. Cantor attended, hoping to meet Bertrand Russell, whose newly published Principia Mathematica
repeatedly cited Cantor's work, but this did not come about. The
following year, St. Andrews awarded Cantor an honorary doctorate, but
illness precluded his receiving the degree in person.
Cantor retired in 1913, living in poverty and suffering from malnourishment during World War I.
The public celebration of his 70th birthday was canceled because of the
war. In June 1917, he entered a sanatorium for the last time and
continually wrote to his wife asking to be allowed to go home. Georg
Cantor had a fatal heart attack on January 6, 1918, in the sanatorium
where he had spent the last year of his life.
Mathematical work
Cantor's work between 1874 and 1884 is the origin of set theory.
Prior to this work, the concept of a set was a rather elementary one
that had been used implicitly since the beginning of mathematics, dating
back to the ideas of Aristotle.
No one had realized that set theory had any nontrivial content. Before
Cantor, there were only finite sets (which are easy to understand) and
"the infinite" (which was considered a topic for philosophical, rather
than mathematical, discussion). By proving that there are (infinitely)
many possible sizes for infinite sets, Cantor established that set
theory was not trivial, and it needed to be studied. Set theory has come to play the role of a foundational theory
in modern mathematics, in the sense that it interprets propositions
about mathematical objects (for example, numbers and functions) from all
the traditional areas of mathematics (such as algebra, analysis and topology)
in a single theory, and provides a standard set of axioms to prove or
disprove them. The basic concepts of set theory are now used throughout
mathematics.
In one of his earliest papers, Cantor proved that the set of real numbers is "more numerous" than the set of natural numbers; this showed, for the first time, that there exist infinite sets of different sizes. He was also the first to appreciate the importance of one-to-one correspondences (hereinafter denoted "1-to-1 correspondence") in set theory. He used this concept to define finite and infinite sets, subdividing the latter into denumerable (or countably infinite) sets and nondenumerable sets (uncountably infinite sets).
Cantor developed important concepts in topology and their relation to cardinality. For example, he showed that the Cantor set, discovered by Henry John Stephen Smith in 1875, is nowhere dense, but has the same cardinality as the set of all real numbers, whereas the rationals are everywhere dense, but countable. He also showed that all countable dense linear orders without end points are order-isomorphic to the rational numbers.
Cantor introduced fundamental constructions in set theory, such as the power set of a set A, which is the set of all possible subsets of A. He later proved that the size of the power set of A is strictly larger than the size of A, even when A is an infinite set; this result soon became known as Cantor's theorem. Cantor developed an entire theory and arithmetic of infinite sets, called cardinals and ordinals, which extended the arithmetic of the natural numbers. His notation for the cardinal numbers was the Hebrew letter (aleph) with a natural number subscript; for the ordinals he employed the Greek letter ω (omega). This notation is still in use today.
The Continuum hypothesis, introduced by Cantor, was presented by David Hilbert as the first of his twenty-three open problems in his address at the 1900 International Congress of Mathematicians in Paris. Cantor's work also attracted favorable notice beyond Hilbert's celebrated encomium. The US philosopher Charles Sanders Peirce
praised Cantor's set theory and, following public lectures delivered by
Cantor at the first International Congress of Mathematicians, held in
Zurich in 1897, Adolf Hurwitz and Jacques Hadamard
also both expressed their admiration. At that Congress, Cantor renewed
his friendship and correspondence with Dedekind. From 1905, Cantor
corresponded with his British admirer and translator Philip Jourdain on the history of set theory and on Cantor's religious ideas. This was later published, as were several of his expository works.
Number theory, trigonometric series and ordinals
Cantor's first ten papers were on number theory, his thesis topic. At the suggestion of Eduard Heine, the Professor at Halle, Cantor turned to analysis. Heine proposed that Cantor solve an open problem that had eluded Peter Gustav Lejeune Dirichlet, Rudolf Lipschitz, Bernhard Riemann, and Heine himself: the uniqueness of the representation of a function by trigonometric series.
Cantor solved this problem in 1869. It was while working on this
problem that he discovered transfinite ordinals, which occurred as
indices n in the nth derived setSn of a set S of zeros of a trigonometric series. Given a trigonometric series f(x) with S as its set of zeros, Cantor had discovered a procedure that produced another trigonometric series that had S1 as its set of zeros, where S1 is the set of limit points of S. If Sk+1 is the set of limit points of Sk, then he could construct a trigonometric series whose zeros are Sk+1. Because the sets Sk were closed, they contained their limit points, and the intersection of the infinite decreasing sequence of sets S, S1, S2, S3,... formed a limit set, which we would now call Sω, and then he noticed that Sω would also have to have a set of limit points Sω+1, and so on. He had examples that went on forever, and so here was a naturally occurring infinite sequence of infinite numbers ω, ω + 1, ω + 2, ...
Between 1870 and 1872, Cantor published more papers on trigonometric series, and also a paper defining irrational numbers as convergent sequences of rational numbers.
Dedekind, whom Cantor befriended in 1872, cited this paper later that
year, in the paper where he first set out his celebrated definition of
real numbers by Dedekind cuts.
While extending the notion of number by means of his revolutionary
concept of infinite cardinality, Cantor was paradoxically opposed to
theories of infinitesimals of his contemporaries Otto Stolz and Paul du Bois-Reymond, describing them as both "an abomination" and "a cholera bacillus of mathematics". Cantor also published an erroneous "proof" of the inconsistency of infinitesimals.
Set theory
An illustration of Cantor's diagonal argument for the existence of uncountable sets. The sequence at the bottom cannot occur anywhere in the infinite list of sequences above.
The beginning of set theory as a branch of mathematics is often marked by the publication of Cantor's 1874 paper,
"Ueber eine Eigenschaft des Inbegriffes aller reellen algebraischen
Zahlen" ("On a Property of the Collection of All Real Algebraic
Numbers").
This paper was the first to provide a rigorous proof that there was
more than one kind of infinity. Previously, all infinite collections had
been implicitly assumed to be equinumerous (that is, of "the same size" or having the same number of elements). Cantor proved that the collection of real numbers and the collection of positive integers are not equinumerous. In other words, the real numbers are not countable. His proof differs from diagonal argument that he gave in 1891. Cantor's article also contains a new method of constructing transcendental numbers. Transcendental numbers were first constructed by Joseph Liouville in 1844.
Cantor established these results using two constructions. His first construction shows how to write the real algebraic numbers as a sequencea1, a2, a3, ....
In other words, the real algebraic numbers are countable. Cantor starts
his second construction with any sequence of real numbers. Using this
sequence, he constructs nested intervals whose intersection
contains a real number not in the sequence. Since every sequence of
real numbers can be used to construct a real not in the sequence, the
real numbers cannot be written as a sequence – that is, the real numbers
are not countable. By applying his construction to the sequence of
real algebraic numbers, Cantor produces a transcendental number. Cantor
points out that his constructions prove more – namely, they provide a
new proof of Liouville's theorem: Every interval contains infinitely
many transcendental numbers.
Cantor's next article contains a construction that proves the set of
transcendental numbers has the same "power" (see below) as the set of
real numbers.
Between 1879 and 1884, Cantor published a series of six articles in Mathematische Annalen
that together formed an introduction to his set theory. At the same
time, there was growing opposition to Cantor's ideas, led by Leopold
Kronecker, who admitted mathematical concepts only if they could be
constructed in a finite
number of steps from the natural numbers, which he took as intuitively
given. For Kronecker, Cantor's hierarchy of infinities was inadmissible,
since accepting the concept of actual infinity would open the door to paradoxes which would challenge the validity of mathematics as a whole. Cantor also introduced the Cantor set during this period.
The fifth paper in this series, "Grundlagen einer allgemeinen Mannigfaltigkeitslehre" ("Foundations of a General Theory of Aggregates"), published in 1883, was the most important of the six and was also published as a separate monograph. It contained Cantor's reply to his critics and showed how the transfinite numbers were a systematic extension of the natural numbers. It begins by defining well-ordered sets. Ordinal numbers are then introduced as the order types of well-ordered sets. Cantor then defines the addition and multiplication of the cardinal
and ordinal numbers. In 1885, Cantor extended his theory of order types
so that the ordinal numbers simply became a special case of order
types.
In 1891, he published a paper containing his elegant "diagonal
argument" for the existence of an uncountable set. He applied the same
idea to prove Cantor's theorem: the cardinality of the power set of a set A is strictly larger than the cardinality of A. This established the richness of the hierarchy of infinite sets, and of the cardinal and ordinal arithmetic that Cantor had defined. His argument is fundamental in the solution of the Halting problem and the proof of Gödel's first incompleteness theorem. Cantor wrote on the Goldbach conjecture in 1894.
Passage of Georg Cantor's article with his set definition
In 1895 and 1897, Cantor published a two-part paper in Mathematische Annalen under Felix Klein's editorship; these were his last significant papers on set theory. The first paper begins by defining set, subset,
etc., in ways that would be largely acceptable now. The cardinal and
ordinal arithmetic are reviewed. Cantor wanted the second paper to
include a proof of the continuum hypothesis, but had to settle for
expositing his theory of well-ordered sets and ordinal numbers. Cantor attempts to prove that if A and B are sets with Aequivalent to a subset of B and B equivalent to a subset of A, then A and B are equivalent. Ernst Schröder had stated this theorem a bit earlier, but his proof, as well as Cantor's, was flawed. Felix Bernstein supplied a correct proof in his 1898 PhD thesis; hence the name Cantor–Bernstein–Schröder theorem.
Cantor's 1874 Crelle paper was the first to invoke the notion of a 1-to-1 correspondence, though he did not use that phrase. He then began looking for a 1-to-1 correspondence between the points of the unit square and the points of a unit line segment. In an 1877 letter to Richard Dedekind, Cantor proved a far stronger result: for any positive integer n, there exists a 1-to-1 correspondence between the points on the unit line segment and all of the points in an n-dimensional space. About this discovery Cantor wrote to Dedekind: "Je le vois, mais je ne le crois pas!" ("I see it, but I don't believe it!") The result that he found so astonishing has implications for geometry and the notion of dimension.
In 1878, Cantor submitted another paper to Crelle's Journal, in
which he defined precisely the concept of a 1-to-1 correspondence and
introduced the notion of "power" (a term he took from Jakob Steiner)
or "equivalence" of sets: two sets are equivalent (have the same power)
if there exists a 1-to-1 correspondence between them. Cantor defined countable sets (or denumerable sets) as sets which can be put into a 1-to-1 correspondence with the natural numbers, and proved that the rational numbers are denumerable. He also proved that n-dimensional Euclidean spaceRn has the same power as the real numbersR, as does a countably infinite product of copies of R.
While he made free use of countability as a concept, he did not write
the word "countable" until 1883. Cantor also discussed his thinking
about dimension, stressing that his mapping between the unit interval and the unit square was not a continuous one.
This paper displeased Kronecker and Cantor wanted to withdraw it; however, Dedekind persuaded him not to do so and Karl Weierstrass supported its publication. Nevertheless, Cantor never again submitted anything to Crelle.
Cantor was the first to formulate what later came to be known as the continuum hypothesis
or CH: there exists no set whose power is greater than that of the
naturals and less than that of the reals (or equivalently, the
cardinality of the reals is exactly aleph-one, rather than just at least aleph-one). Cantor believed the continuum hypothesis to be true and tried for many years to prove it, in vain. His inability to prove the continuum hypothesis caused him considerable anxiety.
The difficulty Cantor had in proving the continuum hypothesis has
been underscored by later developments in the field of mathematics: a
1940 result by Kurt Gödel and a 1963 one by Paul Cohen together imply that the continuum hypothesis can be neither proved nor disproved using standard Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory plus the axiom of choice (the combination referred to as "ZFC").
Absolute infinite, well-ordering theorem, and paradoxes
In 1883, Cantor divided the infinite into the transfinite and the absolute.
The transfinite is increasable in magnitude, while the absolute
is unincreasable. For example, an ordinal α is transfinite because it
can be increased to α + 1. On the other hand, the ordinals form an
absolutely infinite sequence that cannot be increased in magnitude
because there are no larger ordinals to add to it. In 1883, Cantor also introduced the well-ordering principle "every set can be well-ordered" and stated that it is a "law of thought".
Cantor extended his work on the absolute infinite by using it in a
proof. Around 1895, he began to regard his well-ordering principle as a
theorem and attempted to prove it. In 1899, he sent Dedekind a proof of
the equivalent aleph theorem: the cardinality of every infinite set is
an aleph.
First, he defined two types of multiplicities: consistent
multiplicities (sets) and inconsistent multiplicities (absolutely
infinite multiplicities). Next he assumed that the ordinals form a set,
proved that this leads to a contradiction, and concluded that the
ordinals form an inconsistent multiplicity. He used this inconsistent
multiplicity to prove the aleph theorem. In 1932, Zermelo criticized the construction in Cantor's proof.
Cantor avoided paradoxes
by recognizing that there are two types of multiplicities. In his set
theory, when it is assumed that the ordinals form a set, the resulting
contradiction implies only that the ordinals form an inconsistent
multiplicity. In contrast, Bertrand Russell
treated all collections as sets, which leads to paradoxes. In Russell's
set theory, the ordinals form a set, so the resulting contradiction
implies that the theory is inconsistent. From 1901 to 1903, Russell discovered three paradoxes implying that his set theory is inconsistent: the Burali-Forti paradox (which was just mentioned), Cantor's paradox, and Russell's paradox. Russell named paradoxes after Cesare Burali-Forti and Cantor even though neither of them believed that they had found paradoxes.
In 1908, Zermelo published his axiom system for set theory. He had two motivations for developing the axiom system: eliminating the paradoxes and securing his proof of the well-ordering theorem. Zermelo had proved this theorem in 1904 using the axiom of choice, but his proof was criticized for a variety of reasons.
His response to the criticism included his axiom system and a new proof
of the well-ordering theorem. His axioms support this new proof, and
they eliminate the paradoxes by restricting the formation of sets.
In 1923, John von Neumann
developed an axiom system that eliminates the paradoxes by using an
approach similar to Cantor's—namely, by identifying collections that are
not sets and treating them differently. Von Neumann stated that a class
is too big to be a set if it can be put into one-to-one correspondence
with the class of all sets. He defined a set as a class that is a member
of some class and stated the axiom: A class is not a set if and only if
there is a one-to-one correspondence between it and the class of all
sets. This axiom implies that these big classes are not sets, which
eliminates the paradoxes since they cannot be members of any class.
Von Neumann also used his axiom to prove the well-ordering theorem:
Like Cantor, he assumed that the ordinals form a set. The resulting
contradiction implies that the class of all ordinals is not a set. Then
his axiom provides a one-to-one correspondence between this class and
the class of all sets. This correspondence well-orders the class of all
sets, which implies the well-ordering theorem. In 1930, Zermelo defined models of set theory that satisfy von Neumann's axiom.
Philosophy, religion, literature and Cantor's mathematics
The concept of the existence of an actual infinity was an important shared concern within the realms of mathematics, philosophy and religion. Preserving the orthodoxy
of the relationship between God and mathematics, although not in the
same form as held by his critics, was long a concern of Cantor's. He directly addressed this intersection between these disciplines in the introduction to his Grundlagen einer allgemeinen Mannigfaltigkeitslehre, where he stressed the connection between his view of the infinite and the philosophical one.
To Cantor, his mathematical views were intrinsically linked to their
philosophical and theological implications – he identified the Absolute Infinite with God,
and he considered his work on transfinite numbers to have been directly
communicated to him by God, who had chosen Cantor to reveal them to the
world. He was a devout Lutheran whose explicit Christian beliefs shaped his philosophy of science. Joseph Dauben has traced the effect Cantor's Christian convictions had on the development of transfinite set theory.
Debate among mathematicians grew out of opposing views in the philosophy of mathematics
regarding the nature of actual infinity. Some held to the view that
infinity was an abstraction which was not mathematically legitimate, and
denied its existence. Mathematicians from three major schools of thought (constructivism and its two offshoots, intuitionism and finitism)
opposed Cantor's theories in this matter. For constructivists such as
Kronecker, this rejection of actual infinity stems from fundamental
disagreement with the idea that nonconstructive proofs such as Cantor's diagonal argument are sufficient proof that something exists, holding instead that constructive proofs
are required. Intuitionism also rejects the idea that actual infinity
is an expression of any sort of reality, but arrive at the decision via a
different route than constructivism. Firstly, Cantor's argument rests
on logic to prove the existence of transfinite numbers as an actual
mathematical entity, whereas intuitionists hold that mathematical
entities cannot be reduced to logical propositions, originating instead
in the intuitions of the mind.
Secondly, the notion of infinity as an expression of reality is itself
disallowed in intuitionism, since the human mind cannot intuitively
construct an infinite set. Mathematicians such as L. E. J. Brouwer and especially Henri Poincaré adopted an intuitionist stance against Cantor's work. Finally, Wittgenstein's attacks were finitist: he believed that Cantor's diagonal argument conflated the intension of a set of cardinal or real numbers with its extension, thus conflating the concept of rules for generating a set with an actual set.
Some Christian theologians saw Cantor's work as a challenge to the uniqueness of the absolute infinity in the nature of God. In particular, neo-Thomist
thinkers saw the existence of an actual infinity that consisted of
something other than God as jeopardizing "God's exclusive claim to
supreme infinity".
Cantor strongly believed that this view was a misinterpretation of
infinity, and was convinced that set theory could help correct this
mistake:
"... the transfinite species are just as much at the disposal of the
intentions of the Creator and His absolute boundless will as are the
finite numbers.".
It is to note that prominent neo-scholastic german philosopher
Constantin Gutberlet was in favor of such theory, holding that it didn't
oppose the nature of God.
Cantor also believed that his theory of transfinite numbers ran counter to both materialism and determinism – and was shocked when he realized that he was the only faculty member at Halle who did not hold to deterministic philosophical beliefs.
It was important to Cantor that his philosophy provided an "organic explanation" of nature, and in his 1883 Grundlagen, he said that such an explanation could only come about by drawing on the resources of the philosophy of Spinoza and Leibniz. In making these claims, Cantor may have been influenced by FA Trendelenburg, whose lecture courses he attended at Berlin, and in turn Cantor produced a Latin commentary on Book 1 of Spinoza's Ethica. FA Trendelenburg was also the examiner of Cantor's Habilitationsschrift.
In 1888, Cantor published his correspondence with several
philosophers on the philosophical implications of his set theory. In an
extensive attempt to persuade other Christian thinkers and authorities
to adopt his views, Cantor had corresponded with Christian philosophers
such as Tilman Pesch and Joseph Hontheim, as well as theologians such as Cardinal Johann Baptist Franzelin, who once replied by equating the theory of transfinite numbers with pantheism. Although later this Cardinal accepted the theory as valid, due to some clarifications from Cantor's. Cantor even sent one letter directly to Pope Leo XIII himself, and addressed several pamphlets to him.
Cantor's philosophy on the nature of numbers led him to affirm a
belief in the freedom of mathematics to posit and prove concepts apart
from the realm of physical phenomena, as expressions within an internal
reality. The only restrictions on this metaphysical
system are that all mathematical concepts must be devoid of internal
contradiction, and that they follow from existing definitions, axioms,
and theorems. This belief is summarized in his assertion that "the
essence of mathematics is its freedom." These ideas parallel those of Edmund Husserl, whom Cantor had met in Halle.
Meanwhile, Cantor himself was fiercely opposed to infinitesimals, describing them as both an "abomination" and "the cholera bacillus of mathematics".
Cantor's 1883 paper reveals that he was well aware of the opposition
his ideas were encountering: "... I realize that in this undertaking I
place myself in a certain opposition to views widely held concerning the
mathematical infinite and to opinions frequently defended on the nature
of numbers."
Hence he devotes much space to justifying his earlier work,
asserting that mathematical concepts may be freely introduced as long as
they are free of contradiction and defined in terms of previously accepted concepts. He also cites Aristotle, René Descartes, George Berkeley, Gottfried Leibniz, and Bernard Bolzano on infinity. Instead, he always strongly rejected Kant's
philosophy, in the realms of both the philosophy of mathematics and
metaphysics. He shared B. Russell's motto "Kant or Cantor", and defined
Kant "yonder sophistical Philistine who knew so little mathematics."
Cantor's ancestry
The
title on the memorial plaque (in Russian): "In this building was born
and lived from 1845 till 1854 the great mathematician and creator of set
theory Georg Cantor", Vasilievsky Island, Saint-Petersburg.
Cantor's paternal grandparents were from Copenhagen and fled to Russia from the disruption of the Napoleonic Wars. There is very little direct information on them. Cantor's father, Georg Waldemar Cantor, was educated in the Lutheran
mission in Saint Petersburg, and his correspondence with his son shows
both of them as devout Lutherans. Very little is known for sure about
Georg Waldemar's origin or education. Cantor's mother, Maria Anna Böhm, was an Austro-Hungarian born in Saint Petersburg and baptized Roman Catholic; she converted to Protestantism upon marriage. However, there is a letter from Cantor's brother Louis to their mother, stating:
Mögen wir zehnmal von Juden
abstammen und ich im Princip noch so sehr für Gleichberechtigung der
Hebräer sein, im socialen Leben sind mir Christen lieber ...
("Even if we were descended from Jews ten times over, and even though
I may be, in principle, completely in favour of equal rights for
Hebrews, in social life I prefer Christians...") which could be read to
imply that she was of Jewish ancestry.
According to biographers Eric Temple Bell, Cantor was of Jewish descent, although both parents were baptized.
In a 1971 article entitled "Towards a Biography of Georg Cantor", the
British historian of mathematics Ivor Grattan-Guinness mentions (Annals of Science
27, pp. 345–391, 1971) that he was unable to find evidence of Jewish
ancestry. (He also states that Cantor's wife, Vally Guttmann, was
Jewish).
In a letter written to Paul Tannery
in 1896 (Paul Tannery, Memoires Scientifique 13 Correspondence,
Gauthier-Villars, Paris, 1934, p. 306), Cantor states that his paternal
grandparents were members of the Sephardic Jewish community of
Copenhagen. Specifically, Cantor states in describing his father: "Er
ist aber in Kopenhagen geboren, von israelitischen Eltern, die der
dortigen portugisischen Judengemeinde...." ("He was born in Copenhagen
of Jewish (lit: 'Israelite') parents from the local Portuguese-Jewish
community.")
In addition, Cantor's maternal great uncle, a Hungarian violinist Josef Böhm, has been described as Jewish, which may imply that Cantor's mother was at least partly descended from the Hungarian Jewish community.
In a letter to Bertrand Russell, Cantor described his ancestry and self-perception as follows:
Neither my father nor my mother
were of German blood, the first being a Dane, borne in Kopenhagen, my
mother of Austrian Hungar descension. You must know, Sir, that I am not a
regular just Germain, for I am born 3 March 1845 at Saint
Peterborough, Capital of Russia, but I went with my father and mother
and brothers and sister, eleven years old in the year 1856, into
Germany.
There were documented statements, during the 1930s, that called this Jewish ancestry into question:
More often [i.e., than the ancestry
of the mother] the question has been discussed of whether Georg Cantor
was of Jewish origin. About this it is reported in a notice of the
Danish genealogical Institute in Copenhagen from the year 1937
concerning his father: "It is hereby testified that Georg Woldemar
Cantor, born 1809 or 1814, is not present in the registers of the Jewish
community, and that he completely without doubt was not a Jew ..."
Biographies
Until the 1970s, the chief academic publications on Cantor were two short monographs by Arthur Moritz Schönflies
(1927) – largely the correspondence with Mittag-Leffler – and Fraenkel
(1930). Both were at second and third hand; neither had much on his
personal life. The gap was largely filled by Eric Temple Bell's Men of Mathematics (1937), which one of Cantor's modern biographers describes as "perhaps the most widely read modern book on the history of mathematics"; and as "one of the worst". Bell presents Cantor's relationship with his father as Oedipal,
Cantor's differences with Kronecker as a quarrel between two Jews, and
Cantor's madness as Romantic despair over his failure to win acceptance
for his mathematics. Grattan-Guinness (1971) found that none of these
claims were true, but they may be found in many books of the intervening
period, owing to the absence of any other narrative. There are other
legends, independent of Bell – including one that labels Cantor's father
a foundling, shipped to Saint Petersburg by unknown parents. A critique of Bell's book is contained in Joseph Dauben's biography. Writes Dauben:
Cantor devoted some of his most vituperative correspondence, as well as a portion of the Beiträge, to attacking what he described at one point as the 'infinitesimal Cholera bacillus of mathematics', which had spread from Germany through the work of Thomae, du Bois Reymond and Stolz,
to infect Italian mathematics ... Any acceptance of infinitesimals
necessarily meant that his own theory of number was incomplete. Thus to
accept the work of Thomae, du Bois-Reymond, Stolz and Veronese
was to deny the perfection of Cantor's own creation. Understandably,
Cantor launched a thorough campaign to discredit Veronese's work in
every way possible.