Indeterminism is the idea that events (or certain events, or events of certain types) are not caused, or not caused deterministically.
It is the opposite of determinism and related to chance. It is highly relevant to the philosophical problem of free will, particularly in the form of metaphysical libertarianism. In science, most specifically quantum theory in physics, indeterminism is the belief that no event is certain and the entire outcome of anything is probabilistic. The Heisenberg uncertainty relations and the "Born rule", proposed by Max Born, are often starting points in support of the indeterministic nature of the universe. Indeterminism is also asserted by Sir Arthur Eddington, and Murray Gell-Mann. Indeterminism has been promoted by the French biologist Jacques Monod's essay "Chance and Necessity". The physicist-chemist Ilya Prigogine argued for indeterminism in complex systems.
Necessary but insufficient causation
Indeterminists do not have to deny that causes exist. Instead, they
can maintain that the only causes that exist are of a type that do not
constrain the future to a single course; for instance, they can maintain
that only necessary and not sufficient causes exist. The
necessary/sufficient distinction works as follows:
If x is a necessary cause of y; then the presence of y implies that x definitely preceded it. The presence of x, however, does not imply that y will occur.
If x is a sufficient cause of y, then the presence of y implies that x may have preceded it. (However, another cause z may alternatively cause y. Thus the presence of y does not imply the presence of x, or z, or any other suspect.)
It is possible for everything to have a necessary cause,
even while indeterminism holds and the future is open, because a
necessary condition does not lead to a single inevitable effect.
Indeterministic (or probabilistic) causation is a proposed possibility,
such that "everything has a cause" is not a clear statement of
determinism.
Probabilistic causation
Interpreting causation as a deterministic relation means that if A causes B, then A must always be followed by B. In this sense, war does not cause deaths, nor does smoking cause cancer. As a result, many turn to a notion of probabilistic causation. Informally, A probabilistically causes B if A's occurrence increases the probability of B.
This is sometimes interpreted to reflect the imperfect knowledge of a
deterministic system but other times interpreted to mean that the
causal system under study has an inherently indeterministic nature. (Propensity probability
is an analogous idea, according to which probabilities have an
objective existence and are not just limitations in a subject's
knowledge).
It can be proved that realizations of any probability distribution other than the uniform one are mathematically equal to applying a (deterministic) function (namely, an inverse distribution function) on a random variable following the latter (i.e. an "absolutely random" one);
the probabilities are contained in the deterministic element. A simple
form of demonstrating it would be shooting randomly within a square and
then (deterministically) interpreting a relatively large subsquare as
the more probable outcome.
Intrinsic indeterminism versus unpredictability
A
distinction is generally made between indeterminism and the mere
inability to measure the variables (limits of precision). This is
especially the case for physical indeterminism (as proposed by various interpretations of quantum mechanics). Yet some philosophers have argued that indeterminism and unpredictability are synonymous.
Philosophy
One of the important philosophical implications of determinism is that, according to incompatibilists, it undermines many versions of free will,
also undermining the sense of moral responsibility and the judgement of
regret. You wouldn’t even pass the judgement of regret since moral
responsibility is irrelevant; murdering a man would be no different than
drinking water when you are thirsty.
First of all, this lack of moral responsibility is chaotic in and of
itself; the act of drinking water is certainly morally distinct from
murdering a man. To clarify, a deterministic world would consider your
action, such as murdering a man, to be the only possibility of what
could have happened; the outcome of not murdering the man is literally
impossible. If this was true, as Kant states, if our will is determined
by antecedent causes, then we are no longer the ones responsible for
those actions, because those actions that are determined by a force
outside of ourselves. The moral reality of our world is greatly
disturbed by determinism, because murdering a man is clearly morally
wrong.
The judgement of regret is also irrelevant in a deterministic world
according to William James in his “Dilemma of Determinism”. We simply
would have no logical reason to regret, to consider an “impossible”
event to happen in place of “necessity”, to make moral judgements on
past events that could not possibly obtain any other outcome. Our
ability and will to pass the judgement of regret, on the contrary, is
proof that our world is in fact indeterministic and reaffirms the
uncertainty of the outcomes of events.
The judgement of regret can be effectively passed, because our will is
not determined by antecedent causes. Bertrand Russell presents an
argument in his essay “Elements of Ethics” against these antecedent
causes. Imagine this, we are presented with two alternative choices;
determinism maintains that our will to choose one of them is driven by
an antecedent cause, and the other two alternatives would be impossible,
“but that does not prevent our will from being itself the cause of the
other effects (Russell).” The fact that different possibilities are able
to be caused and chosen by our will means that morality (right and
wrong) is able to be distinguished from the choices. The ability to
effectively judge the different possible outcomes is rock hard proof
that moral responsibility exists and should be kept in check, and it
lines up perfectly with indeterminism.
Ancient Greek philosophy
Leucippus
The oldest mention of the concept of chance is by the earliest philosopher of atomism, Leucippus, who said:
"The cosmos, then, became like a spherical form in this way: the atoms being submitted to a casual and unpredictable movement, quickly and incessantly".
Aristotle
Aristotle described four possible causes (material, efficient, formal, and final). Aristotle's word for these causes was αἰτίαι (aitiai, as in aetiology),
which translates as causes in the sense of the multiple factors
responsible for an event. Aristotle did not subscribe to the simplistic
"every event has a (single) cause" idea that was to come later.
In his Physics and Metaphysics, Aristotle said there were accidents (συμβεβηκός, sumbebekos) caused by nothing but chance (τύχη, tukhe). He noted that he and the early physicists found no place for chance among their causes.
We have seen how far Aristotle distances himself from any view which makes chance a crucial factor in the general explanation of things. And he does so on conceptual grounds: chance events are, he thinks, by definition unusual and lacking certain explanatory features: as such they form the complement class to those things which can be given full natural explanations.
— R.J. Hankinson, "Causes" in Blackwell Companion to Aristotle
Aristotle opposed his accidental chance to necessity:
Nor is there any definite cause for an accident, but only chance (τυχόν), namely an indefinite (ἀόριστον) cause.
It is obvious that there are principles and causes which are generable and destructible apart from the actual processes of generation and destruction; for if this is not true, everything will be of necessity: that is, if there must necessarily be some cause, other than accidental, of that which is generated and destroyed. Will this be, or not? Yes, if this happens; otherwise not.
Pyrrhonism
The philosopher Sextus Empiricus described the Pyrrhonist position on causes as follows:
...we show the existence of causes are plausible, and if those, too, are plausible which prove that it is incorrect to assert the existence of a cause, and if there is no way to give preference to any of these over others – since we have no agreed-upon sign, criterion, or proof, as has been pointed out earlier – then, if we go by the statements of the Dogmatists, it is necessary to suspend judgment about the existence of causes, too, saying that they are no more existent than non-existent
Epicureanism
Epicurus argued that as atoms moved through the void, there were occasions when they would "swerve" (clinamen)
from their otherwise determined paths, thus initiating new causal
chains. Epicurus argued that these swerves would allow us to be more
responsible for our actions, something impossible if every action was
deterministically caused. For Epicureanism, the occasional interventions of arbitrary gods would be preferable to strict determinism.
Early modern philosophy
In 1729 theTestament of Jean Meslier states:
"The matter, by virtue of its own active force, moves and acts in blind manner".
Soon after Julien Offroy de la Mettrie in his L'Homme Machine. (1748, anon.) wrote:
"Perhaps, the cause of man's existence is just in existence itself? Perhaps he is by chance thrown in some point of this terrestrial surface without any how and why".
In his Anti-Sénèque [Traité de la vie heureuse, par Sénèque, avec un Discours du traducteur sur le même sujet, 1750] we read:
"Then, the chance has thrown us in life".
In the 19th century the French Philosopher Antoine-Augustin Cournot theorized chance in a new way, as series of not-linear causes. He wrote in Essai sur les fondements de nos connaissances (1851):
"It is not because of rarity that the chance is actual. On the contrary, it is because of chance they produce many possible others."
Modern philosophy
Charles Peirce
Tychism (Greek: τύχη "chance") is a thesis proposed by the American philosopher Charles Sanders Peirce in the 1890s. It holds that absolute chance, also called spontaneity, is a real factor operative in the universe. It may be considered both the direct opposite of Albert Einstein's oft quoted dictum that: "God does not play dice with the universe" and an early philosophical anticipation of Werner Heisenberg's uncertainty principle.
Peirce does not, of course, assert that there is no law in
the universe. On the contrary, he maintains that an absolutely chance
world would be a contradiction and thus impossible.
Complete lack of order is itself a sort of order. The position he
advocates is rather that there are in the universe both regularities and
irregularities.
Karl Popper comments
that Peirce's theory received little contemporary attention, and that
other philosophers did not adopt indeterminism until the rise of quantum
mechanics.
Arthur Holly Compton
In 1931, Arthur Holly Compton championed the idea of human freedom based on quantum indeterminacy and invented the notion of amplification of microscopic quantum events to bring chance
into the macroscopic world. In his somewhat bizarre mechanism, he
imagined sticks of dynamite attached to his amplifier, anticipating the Schrödinger's cat paradox.
Reacting to criticisms that his ideas made chance the direct
cause of our actions, Compton clarified the two-stage nature of his idea
in an Atlantic Monthly article in 1955. First there is a range of random possible events, then one adds a determining factor in the act of choice.
A set of known physical conditions is not adequate to specify precisely what a forthcoming event will be. These conditions, insofar as they can be known, define instead a range of possible events from among which some particular event will occur. When one exercises freedom, by his act of choice he is himself adding a factor not supplied by the physical conditions and is thus himself determining what will occur. That he does so is known only to the person himself. From the outside one can see in his act only the working of physical law. It is the inner knowledge that he is in fact doing what he intends to do that tells the actor himself that he is free.
Compton welcomed the rise of indeterminism in 20th century science, writing:
In my own thinking on this vital subject I am in a much more satisfied state of mind than I could have been at any earlier stage of science. If the statements of the laws of physics were assumed correct, one would have had to suppose (as did most philosophers) that the feeling of freedom is illusory, or if [free] choice were considered effective, that the laws of physics ... [were] unreliable. The dilemma has been an uncomfortable one.
Together with Arthur Eddington in Britain, Compton was
one of those rare distinguished physicists in the English speaking world
of the late 1920s and throughout the 1930s arguing for the “liberation
of free will” with the help of Heisenberg’s indeterminacy principle,
but their efforts had been met not only with physical and philosophical
criticism but most primarily with fierce political and ideological
campaigns.
Karl Popper
In his essay Of Clouds and Clocks, included in his book Objective Knowledge, Popper
contrasted "clouds", his metaphor for indeterministic systems, with "clocks", meaning deterministic ones.
He sided with indeterminism, writing
I believe Peirce was right in holding that all clocks are clouds to some considerable degree — even the most precise of clocks. This, I think, is the most important inversion of the mistaken determinist view that all clouds are clocks.
Popper was also a promoter of propensity probability.
Robert Kane
Kane is one of the leading contemporary philosophers on free will. Advocating what is termed within philosophical circles "libertarian
freedom", Kane argues that "(1) the existence of alternative
possibilities (or the agent's power to do otherwise) is a necessary
condition for acting freely, and (2) determinism is not compatible with
alternative possibilities (it precludes the power to do otherwise)".
It is important to note that the crux of Kane's position is grounded
not in a defense of alternative possibilities (AP) but in the notion of
what Kane refers to as ultimate responsibility (UR). Thus, AP is a
necessary but insufficient criterion for free will. It is necessary
that there be (metaphysically)
real alternatives for our actions, but that is not enough; our actions
could be random without being in our control. The control is found in
"ultimate responsibility".
What allows for ultimate responsibility of creation in Kane's
picture are what he refers to as "self-forming actions" or SFAs — those
moments of indecision during which people experience conflicting wills.
These SFAs are the undetermined, regress-stopping voluntary actions or
refrainings in the life histories of agents that are required for UR.
UR does not require that every act done of our own free will be
undetermined and thus that, for every act or choice, we could have done
otherwise; it requires only that certain of our choices and actions be
undetermined (and thus that we could have done otherwise), namely SFAs.
These form our character or nature; they inform our future choices,
reasons and motivations in action. If a person has had the opportunity
to make a character-forming decision (SFA), he is responsible for the
actions that are a result of his character.
Mark Balaguer
Mark Balaguer, in his book Free Will as an Open Scientific Problem
argues similarly to Kane. He believes that, conceptually, free will
requires indeterminism, and the question of whether the brain behaves
indeterministically is open to further empirical research. He has also written on this matter "A Scientifically Reputable Version of Indeterministic Libertarian Free Will".
Science
Mathematics
In probability theory, a stochastic process /stoʊˈkæstɪk/, or sometimes random process, is the counterpart to a deterministic process (or deterministic system).
Instead of dealing with only one possible reality of how the process
might evolve over time (as is the case, for example, for solutions of an
ordinary differential equation),
in a stochastic or random process there is some indeterminacy in its
future evolution described by probability distributions. This means that
even if the initial condition (or starting point) is known, there are
many possibilities the process might go to, but some paths may be more
probable and others less so.
Classical and relativistic physics
The idea that Newtonian physics
proved causal determinism was highly influential in the early modern
period.
"Thus physical determinism [..] became the ruling faith among
enlightened men; and everybody who did not embrace this new faith was
held to be an obscurantist and a reactionary". However: "Newton himself may be counted among the few dissenters, for he regarded the solar system as imperfect, and consequently as likely to perish".
Classical chaos is not usually considered an example of indeterminism, as it can occur in deterministic systems such as the three-body problem.
John Earman has argued that most physical theories are indeterministic. For instance, Newtonian physics admits solutions where particles accelerate continuously, heading out towards infinity. By the time reversibility
of the laws in question, particles could also head inwards, unprompted
by any pre-existing state. He calls such hypothetical particles "space invaders".
John D. Norton has suggested another indeterministic scenario, known as Norton's Dome, where a particle is initially situated on the exact apex of a dome.
Branching space-time is a theory uniting indeterminism and the special theory of relativity. The idea was originated by Nuel Belnap. The equations of general relativity admit of both indeterministic and deterministic solutions.
Boltzmann
Ludwig Boltzmann, was one of the founders of statistical mechanics and the modern atomic theory of matter. He is remembered for his discovery that the second law of thermodynamics is a statistical law stemming from disorder. He also speculated that the ordered universe we see is only a small bubble in much larger sea of chaos. The Boltzmann brain is a similar idea. He can be considered one of few indeterminists to embrace pure chance.
Evolution and biology
Darwinian evolution has an enhanced reliance on the chance element of random mutation compared to the earlier evolutionary theory of Herbert Spencer. However, the question of whether evolution requires genuine ontological indeterminism is open to debate.
In the essay Chance and Necessity (1970) Jacques Monod rejected the role of final causation in biology, instead arguing that a mixture of efficient causation and "pure chance" lead to teleonomy, or merely apparent purposefulness.
The Japanese theoretical population geneticist Motoo Kimura emphasises the role of indeterminism in evolution. According to neutral theory of molecular evolution: "at the molecular level most evolutionary change is caused by random drift of gene mutants that are equivalent in the face of selection.
Prigogine
In his 1997 book, The End of Certainty,
Prigogine contends that determinism is no longer a viable scientific
belief. "The more we know about our universe, the more difficult it
becomes to believe in determinism." This is a major departure from the
approach of Newton, Einstein and Schrödinger,
all of whom expressed their theories in terms of deterministic
equations. According to Prigogine, determinism loses its explanatory
power in the face of irreversibility and instability.
Prigogine traces the dispute over determinism back to Darwin, whose attempt to explain individual variability according to evolving populations inspired Ludwig Boltzmann to explain the behavior of gases in terms of populations of particles rather than individual particles. This led to the field of statistical mechanics
and the realization that gases undergo irreversible processes. In
deterministic physics, all processes are time-reversible, meaning that
they can proceed backward as well as forward through time. As Prigogine
explains, determinism is fundamentally a denial of the arrow of time.
With no arrow of time, there is no longer a privileged moment known as
the "present," which follows a determined "past" and precedes an
undetermined "future." All of time is simply given, with the future as
determined or undetermined as the past. With irreversibility, the arrow
of time is reintroduced to physics. Prigogine notes numerous examples of
irreversibility, including diffusion, radioactive decay, solar radiation, weather and the emergence and evolution of life. Like weather systems, organisms are unstable systems existing far from thermodynamic equilibrium.
Instability resists standard deterministic explanation. Instead, due to
sensitivity to initial conditions, unstable systems can only be
explained statistically, that is, in terms of probability.
Prigogine asserts that Newtonian physics has now been "extended" three times, first with the use of the wave function in quantum mechanics, then with the introduction of spacetime in general relativity and finally with the recognition of indeterminism in the study of unstable systems.
Quantum mechanics
At one time, it was assumed in the physical sciences that if the
behavior observed in a system cannot be predicted, the problem is due to
lack of fine-grained information, so that a sufficiently detailed
investigation would eventually result in a deterministic theory ("If you
knew exactly all the forces acting on the dice, you would be able to
predict which number comes up").
However, the advent of quantum mechanics removed the underpinning from that approach, with the claim that (at least according to the Copenhagen interpretation) the most basic constituents of matter at times behave indeterministically. This comes from the collapse of the wave function, in which the state of a system upon measurement
cannot in general be predicted. Quantum mechanics only predicts the
probabilities of possible outcomes, which are given by the Born rule. Non-deterministic behavior upon wave function collapse is not only a feature of the Copenhagen interpretation, with its observer-dependence, but also of objective collapse theories.
Opponents of quantum indeterminism suggested that determinism
could be restored by formulating a new theory in which additional
information, so-called hidden variables, would allow definite outcomes to be determined. For instance, in 1935, Einstein, Podolsky and Rosen wrote a paper titled "Can Quantum-Mechanical Description of Physical Reality Be Considered Complete?" arguing that such a theory was in fact necessary to preserve the principle of locality.
In 1964, John S. Bell was able to define a theoretical test for these local hidden variable theories, which was reformulated as a workable experimental test through the work of Clauser, Horne, Shimony and Holt. The negative result of the 1980s tests by Alain Aspect ruled such theories out, provided certain assumptions about the experiment hold. Thus any interpretation of quantum mechanics, including deterministic reformulations, must either reject locality or reject counterfactual definiteness altogether. David Bohm's theory is the main example of a non-local deterministic quantum theory.
The many-worlds interpretation
is said to be deterministic, but experimental results still cannot be
predicted: experimenters do not know which 'world' they will end up in.
Technically, counterfactual definiteness is lacking.
A notable consequence of quantum indeterminism is the Heisenberg uncertainty principle, which prevents the simultaneous accurate measurement of all a particle's properties.
Cosmology
Primordial fluctuations are density variations in the early universe which are considered the seeds of all structure in the universe. Currently, the most widely accepted explanation for their origin is in the context of cosmic inflation. According to the inflationary paradigm, the exponential growth of the scale factor during inflation caused quantum fluctuations of the inflaton field to be stretched to macroscopic scales, and, upon leaving the horizon, to "freeze in".
At the later stages of radiation- and matter-domination, these fluctuations re-entered the horizon, and thus set the initial conditions for structure formation.
Neuroscience
Neuroscientists such as Bjoern Brembs and Christof Koch believe thermodynamically stochastic processes in the brain are the basis of free will, and that even very simple organisms such as flies have a form of free will. Similar ideas are put forward by some philosophers such as Robert Kane.
Despite recognizing indeterminism to be a very low-level,
necessary prerequisite, Bjoern Brembs says that it's not even close to
being sufficient for addressing things like morality and responsibility. Edward O. Wilson does not extrapolate from bugs to people, and Corina E. Tarnita
alerts against trying to draw parallels between people and insects,
since human selflessness and cooperation, however, is of a different
sort, also involving the interaction of culture and sentience, not just
genetics and environment.
Other views
Against Einstein and others who advocated determinism, indeterminism—as championed by the English astronomer Sir Arthur Eddington—says that a physical object has an ontologically undetermined component that is not due to the epistemological limitations of physicists' understanding. The uncertainty principle, then, would not necessarily be due to hidden variables but to an indeterminism in nature itself.
Determinism and indeterminism are examined in Causality and Chance in Modern Physics by David Bohm. He speculates that, since determinism can emerge from underlying indeterminism (via the law of large numbers), and that indeterminism can emerge from determinism (for instance, from classical chaos), the universe could be conceived of as having alternating layers of causality and chaos.