From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
The
hard problem of consciousness is the problem of explaining how and why we have
qualia or
phenomenal experiences—how sensations acquire characteristics, such as colors and tastes.
[1] The philosopher
David Chalmers, who introduced the term "hard problem" of
consciousness,
[2]
contrasts this with the "easy problems" of explaining the ability to
discriminate, integrate information, report mental states, focus
attention, etc. Easy problems are easy because all that is required for
their solution is to specify a mechanism that can perform the function.
That is, their proposed solutions, regardless of how complex or poorly
understood they may be, can be entirely consistent with the modern
materialistic
conception of natural phenomena. Chalmers claims that the problem of
experience is distinct from this set, and he argues that the problem of
experience will "persist even when the performance of all the relevant
functions is explained".
[3]
The existence of a "hard problem" is controversial and has been disputed by philosophers such as
Daniel Dennett[4] and
cognitive neuroscientists such as
Stanislas Dehaene.
[5] Clinical neurologist and
skeptic Steven Novella refers to it as "the hard non-problem".
[6]
Formulation of the problem
Chalmers' formulation
In
Facing Up to the Problem of Consciousness (1995), Chalmers wrote:
[3]
It is undeniable that some organisms are subjects of experience. But
the question of how it is that these systems are subjects of experience
is perplexing. Why is it that when our cognitive systems engage in
visual and auditory information-processing, we have visual or auditory
experience: the quality of deep blue, the sensation of middle C? How can
we explain why there is something it is like to entertain a mental
image, or to experience an emotion? It is widely agreed that experience
arises from a physical basis, but we have no good explanation of why and
how it so arises. Why should physical processing give rise to a rich
inner life at all? It seems objectively unreasonable that it should, and
yet it does.
In the same paper, he also wrote:
The really hard problem of consciousness is the problem of
experience. When we think and perceive there is a whir of information
processing, but there is also a subjective aspect.
The philosopher Raamy Majeed noted in 2016 that the hard problem is, in fact, associated with two "explanatory targets":
[7]
- [PQ] Physical processing gives rise to experiences with a phenomenal character.
- [Q] Our phenomenal qualities are thus-and-so.
The first fact concerns the relationship between the physical and the
phenomenal, whereas the second concerns the very nature of the
phenomenal itself. Most responses to the hard problem are aimed at
explaining either one of these facts or both.
Easy problems
Chalmers
contrasts the hard problem with a number of (relatively) easy problems
that consciousness presents. He emphasizes that what the easy problems
have in common is that they all represent some ability, or the
performance of some function or behavior. Examples of easy problems
include:
[8]
- the ability to discriminate, categorize, and react to environmental stimuli;
- the integration of information by a cognitive system;
- the reportability of mental states;
- the ability of a system to access its own internal states;
- the focus of attention;
- the deliberate control of behavior;
- the difference between wakefulness and sleep.
Other formulations
Other formulations of the "hard problem" include:
[citation needed]
- "How is it that some organisms are subjects of experience?"
- "Why does awareness of sensory information exist at all?"
- "Why do qualia exist?"
- "Why is there a subjective component to experience?"
- "Why aren't we philosophical zombies?"
Historical predecessors
The hard problem has scholarly antecedents considerably earlier than Chalmers, as Chalmers himself has pointed out.
[9]
The physicist and mathematician
Isaac Newton wrote in a 1672 letter to
Henry Oldenburg:
to determine by what modes or actions light produceth in our minds the phantasm of colour is not so easie.[10]
In
An Essay Concerning Human Understanding (1690), the philosopher and physician
John Locke argued:
Divide matter into as minute parts as you will (which we are apt to
imagine a sort of spiritualizing or making a thinking thing of it) vary
the figure and motion of it as much as you please—a globe, cube, cone,
prism, cylinder, etc., whose diameters are but 1,000,000th part of a
gry, will operate not otherwise upon other bodies of proportionable bulk
than those of an inch or foot diameter—and you may as rationally expect
to produce sense, thought, and knowledge, by putting together, in a
certain figure and motion, gross particles of matter, as by those that
are the very minutest that do anywhere exist. They knock, impel, and
resist one another, just as the greater do; and that is all they can
do... [I]t is impossible to conceive that matter, either with or without
motion, could have originally in and from itself sense, perception, and
knowledge; as is evident from hence that then sense, perception, and
knowledge must be a property eternally inseparable from matter and every
particle of it.[11]
The
polymath and philosopher
Gottfried Leibniz wrote in 1714, as an example also known as
Leibniz's gap:
Moreover, it must be confessed that perception and that which depends
upon it are inexplicable on mechanical grounds, that is to say, by
means of figures and motions. And supposing there were a machine, so
constructed as to think, feel, and have perception, it might be
conceived as increased in size, while keeping the same proportions, so
that one might go into it as into a mill. That being so, we should, on
examining its interior, find only parts which work one upon another, and
never anything by which to explain a perception.[12]
The philosopher and political economist
J.S. Mill wrote in
A System of Logic (1843), Book V, Chapter V, section 3:
Now I am far from pretending that it may not be capable of proof, or
that it is not an important addition to our knowledge if proved, that
certain motions in the particles of bodies are the conditions of the
production of heat or light; that certain assignable physical
modifications of the nerves may be the conditions not only of our
sensations or emotions, but even of our thoughts; that certain
mechanical and chemical conditions may, in the order of nature, be
sufficient to determine to action the physiological laws of life. All I
insist upon, in common with every thinker who entertains any clear idea
of the logic of science, is, that it shall not be supposed that by
proving these things one step would be made towards a real explanation
of heat, light, or sensation; or that the generic peculiarity of those
phenomena can be in the least degree evaded by any such discoveries,
however well established. Let it be shown, for instance, that the most
complex series of physical causes and effects succeed one another in the
eye and in the brain to produce a sensation of colour; rays falling on
the eye, refracted, converging, crossing one another, making an inverted
image on the retina, and after this a motion—let it be a vibration, or a
rush of nervous fluid, or whatever else you are pleased to suppose,
along the optic nerve—a propagation of this motion to the brain itself,
and as many more different motions as you choose; still, at the end of
these motions, there is something which is not motion, there is a
feeling or sensation of colour. Whatever number of motions we may be
able to interpolate, and whether they be real or imaginary, we shall
still find, at the end of the series, a motion antecedent and a colour
consequent. The mode in which any one of the motions produces the next,
may possibly be susceptible of explanation by some general law of
motion: but the mode in which the last motion produces the sensation of
colour, cannot be explained by any law of motion; it is the law of
colour: which is, and must always remain, a peculiar thing. Where our
consciousness recognises between two phenomena an inherent distinction;
where we are sensible of a difference which is not merely of degree, and
feel that no adding one of the phenomena to itself would produce the
other; any theory which attempts to bring either under the laws of the
other must be false; though a theory which merely treats the one as a
cause or condition of the other, may possibly be true.
The biologist
T.H. Huxley wrote in 1868:
But what consciousness is, we know not; and how it is that anything
so remarkable as a state of consciousness comes about as the result of
irritating nervous tissue, is just as unaccountable as the appearance of
the Djin when Aladdin rubbed his lamp in the story, or as any other
ultimate fact of nature.[13]
The philosopher
Thomas Nagel argued in 1974:
If physicalism is to be defended, the phenomenological features must
themselves be given a physical account. But when we examine their
subjective character it seems that such a result is impossible. The
reason is that every subjective phenomenon is essentially connected with
a single point of view, and it seems inevitable that an objective,
physical theory will abandon that point of view.[14]
Relationship to scientific frameworks
Neural correlates of consciousness
Since 1990, researchers including the molecular biologist
Francis Crick and the neuroscientist
Christof Koch
have made significant progress toward identifying which neurobiological
events occur concurrently to the experience of subjective
consciousness.
[15] These postulated events are referred to as
neural correlates of consciousness or NCCs. However, this research arguably addresses the question of
which neurobiological mechanisms are linked to consciousness but not the question of
why
they should give rise to consciousness at all, the latter being the
hard problem of consciousness as Chalmers formulated it. In "On the
Search for the Neural Correlate of Consciousness", Chalmers said he is
confident that, granting the principle that something such as what he
terms global availability can be used as an indicator of consciousness,
the neural correlates will be discovered "in a century or two".
[16] Nevertheless, he stated regarding their relationship to the hard problem of consciousness:
One can always ask why these processes of availability should give
rise to consciousness in the first place. As yet we cannot explain why
they do so, and it may well be that full details about the processes of
availability will still fail to answer this question. Certainly, nothing
in the standard methodology I have outlined answers the question; that
methodology assumes a relation between availability and consciousness,
and therefore does nothing to explain it. [...] So the hard problem
remains. But who knows: Somewhere along the line we may be led to the
relevant insights that show why the link is there, and the hard problem
may then be solved.[16]
The neuroscientist and Nobel laureate
Eric Kandel
wrote that locating the NCCs would not solve the hard problem, but
rather one of the so-called easy problems to which the hard problem is
contrasted.
[17] Kandel went on to note Crick and Koch's suggestion that once the
binding problem—understanding what accounts for the unity of experience—is solved, it will be possible to solve the hard problem empirically.
[17] However, neuroscientist
Anil Seth
argued that emphasis on the so-called hard problem is a distraction
from what he calls the "real problem": understanding the neurobiology
underlying consciousness, namely the neural correlates of various
conscious processes.
[18] This more modest goal is the focus of most scientists working on consciousness.
[17] Psychologist
Susan Blackmore
believes, by contrast, that the search for the neural correlates of
consciousness is futile and itself predicated on an erroneous belief in
the hard problem of consciousness.
[19]
Integrated information theory
Integrated information theory (IIT), developed by the neuroscientist and psychiatrist
Giulio Tononi
in 2004 and more recently also advocated by Koch, is one of the most
discussed models of consciousness in neuroscience and elsewhere.
[20][21] The theory proposes an
identity
between consciousness and integrated information, with the latter item
(denoted as Φ) defined mathematically and thus in principle measurable.
[21][22] The hard problem of consciousness, write Tononi and Koch, may indeed be intractable when working from matter to consciousness.
[23]
However, because IIT inverts this relationship and works from
phenomenological axioms to matter, they say it could be able to solve
the hard problem.
[23]
In this vein, proponents have said the theory goes beyond identifying
human neural correlates and can be extrapolated to all physical systems.
Tononi wrote (along with two colleagues):
While identifying the “neural correlates of consciousness” is
undoubtedly important, it is hard to see how it could ever lead to a
satisfactory explanation of what consciousness is and how it comes
about. As will be illustrated below, IIT offers a way to analyze systems
of mechanisms to determine if they are properly structured to give rise
to consciousness, how much of it, and of which kind.[24]
As part of a broader critique of IIT, Michael Cerullo suggested that
the theory's proposed explanation is in fact for what he dubs (following
Scott Aaronson)
the "Pretty Hard Problem" of methodically inferring which physical
systems are conscious—but would not solve Chalmers' hard problem.
[21] "Even if IIT is correct," he argues, "it does not explain why integrated information generates (or is) consciousness."
[21]
Responses
Consciousness is fundamental or elusive
Some philosophers, including
David Chalmers in the late 20th century and
Alfred North Whitehead earlier in the 1900s, argued that conscious experience is a fundamental constituent of the universe, a form of
panpsychism sometimes referred to as
panexperientialism.
Chalmers argued that a "rich inner life" is not logically reducible to
the functional properties of physical processes. He states that
consciousness must be described using nonphysical means. This
description involves a fundamental ingredient capable of clarifying
phenomena that have not been explained using physical means. Use of this
fundamental property, Chalmers argues, is necessary to explain certain
functions of the world, much like other fundamental features, such as
mass and time, and to explain significant principles in nature.
The philosopher
Thomas Nagel
posited in 1974 that experiences are essentially subjective (accessible
only to the individual undergoing them), while physical states are
essentially objective (accessible to multiple individuals). So at this
stage, he argued, we have no idea what it could even mean to claim that
an essentially subjective state just
is an essentially non-subjective state. In other words, we have no idea of what reductivism really amounts to.
[14]
New mysterianism, such as that of the philosopher
Colin McGinn, proposes that the human
mind, in its current form, will not be able to explain consciousness.
[25]
Deflationary accounts
Some philosophers, such as
Daniel Dennett[4] and
Peter Hacker[26]
oppose the idea that there is a hard problem. These theorists have
argued that once we really come to understand what consciousness is, we
will realize that the hard problem is unreal. For instance, Dennett
asserts that the so-called hard problem will be solved in the process of
answering the "easy" ones (which, as he has clarified, he does not
consider "easy" at all).
[4]
In contrast with Chalmers, he argues that consciousness is not a
fundamental feature of the universe and instead will eventually be fully
explained by natural phenomena. Instead of involving the nonphysical,
he says, consciousness merely plays tricks on people so that it appears
nonphysical—in other words, it simply seems like it requires nonphysical
features to account for its powers. In this way, Dennett compares
consciousness to stage magic and its capability to create extraordinary
illusions out of ordinary things.
[27]
To show how people might be commonly fooled into overstating the
powers of consciousness, Dennett describes a normal phenomenon called
change blindness, a visual process that involves failure to detect scenery changes in a series of alternating images.
[28]
He uses this concept to argue that the overestimation of the brain's
visual processing implies that the conception of our consciousness is
likely not as pervasive as we make it out to be. He claims that this
error of making consciousness more mysterious than it is could be a
misstep in any developments toward an effective explanatory theory.
Critics such as
Galen Strawson
reply that, in the case of consciousness, even a mistaken experience
retains the essential face of experience that needs to be explained,
contra Dennett.
To address the question of the hard problem, or how and why physical
processes give rise to experience, Dennett states that the phenomenon of
having experience is nothing more than the performance of functions or
the production of behavior, which can also be referred to as the easy
problems of consciousness.
[4]
He states that consciousness itself is driven simply by these
functions, and to strip them away would wipe out any ability to identify
thoughts, feelings, and consciousness altogether. So, unlike Chalmers
and other dualists, Dennett says that the easy problems and the hard
problem cannot be separated from each other. To him, the hard problem of
experience is included among—not separate from—the easy problems, and
therefore they can only be explained together as a cohesive unit.
[27]
Like Dennett, Hacker argues that the hard problem is fundamentally
incoherent and that "consciousness studies", as it exists today, is
"literally a total waste of time":
[26]
The whole endeavour of the consciousness studies community is
absurd—they are in pursuit of a chimera. They misunderstand the nature
of consciousness. The conception of consciousness which they have is
incoherent. The questions they are asking don't make sense. They have to
go back to the drawing board and start all over again.
Critics of Dennett's approach, such as Chalmers and Nagel, argue that
Dennett's argument misses the point of the inquiry by merely
re-defining consciousness as an external property and ignoring the
subjective aspect completely. This has led detractors to refer to
Dennett's book
Consciousness Explained as
Consciousness Ignored or
Consciousness Explained Away.
[4] Dennett discussed this at the end of his book with a section entitled
Consciousness Explained or Explained Away?[28]
Though the most common arguments against deflationary accounts and
eliminative materialism
are the argument from qualia and the argument that conscious
experiences are irreducible to physical states—or that current popular
definitions of "physical" are incomplete—the objection follows that the
one and same reality can appear in different ways, and that the
numerical difference of these ways is consistent with a unitary mode of
existence of the reality.
[citation needed]
Critics of the deflationary approach object that qualia are a case
where a single reality cannot have multiple appearances. For example,
the philosopher
John Searle pointed out: "where consciousness is concerned, the existence of the appearance is the reality".
[29]
A notable deflationary account is the
higher-order theories of consciousness.
[30] In 2005, the philosopher
Peter Carruthers
wrote about "recognitional concepts of experience", that is, "a
capacity to recognize [a] type of experience when it occurs in one's own
mental life", and suggested that such a capacity does not depend upon
qualia.
[31]
The philosophers Glenn Carruthers and Elizabeth Schier said in 2012 that the main arguments for the existence of a hard problem—
philosophical zombies,
Mary's room, and
Nagel's bats—are
only persuasive if one already assumes that "consciousness must be
independent of the structure and function of mental states, i.e. that
there is a hard problem". Hence, the arguments
beg the question.
The authors suggest that "instead of letting our conclusions on the
thought experiments guide our theories of consciousness, we should let
our theories of consciousness guide our conclusions from the thought
experiments".
In 2013, the philosopher Elizabeth Irvine pointed out that both science and
folk psychology do not treat
mental states
as having phenomenal properties, and therefore "the hard problem of
consciousness may not be a genuine problem for non-philosophers (despite
its overwhelming obviousness to philosophers), and questions about
consciousness may well 'shatter' into more specific questions about
particular capacities".
[33]
The philosopher
Massimo Pigliucci
distances himself from eliminativism, but he said in 2013 that the hard
problem is still misguided, resulting from a "category mistake":
[34]
Of course an explanation isn't the same as an experience, but that's
because the two are completely independent categories, like colors and
triangles. It is obvious that I cannot experience what it is like to be
you, but I can potentially have a complete explanation of how and why it
is possible to be you.
The source of illusion
A complete reductionistic or mechanistic theory of consciousness must include the description of a
mechanism
by which the subjective aspect of consciousness is perceived and
reported by people. Philosophers such as Chalmers or Nagel have rejected
reductionist theories of consciousness because they believe that the
reports of subjective experience constitute a vast and important body of
empirical evidence which is ignored by modern reductionist theories of
consciousness.
[9]
Dennett argued that solving the easy problem of consciousness, that
is finding out how the brain works, will eventually lead to the solution
of the hard problem of consciousness.
[4]
In particular, the solution can be achieved by identifying the stimuli
and neurological pathways whose operation generates evidence of
subjective experience.
Neuroscientist
Michael Graziano, in his book
Consciousness and the Social Brain, advocates what he calls
attention schema theory,
in which our perception of being conscious is merely an error in
perception, held by brains which evolved to hold erroneous and
incomplete models of their own internal workings, just as they hold
erroneous and incomplete models of their own bodies and of the external
world.
[35][36]
Cognitive neuroscientist
Stanislas Dehaene, in his 2014 book
Consciousness and the Brain,
summarized the previous decades of experimental consciousness research
involving reports of subjective experience, and argued that Chalmers'
"easy problems" of consciousness are actually the hard problems and the
"hard problems" are based only upon ill-defined intuitions that,
according to Dehaene, are continually shifting as understanding evolves:
[5]
Once our intuitions are educated by cognitive neuroscience and
computer simulations, Chalmers' hard problem will evaporate. The
hypothetical concept of qualia, pure mental experience, detached from
any information-processing role, will be viewed as a peculiar idea of
the prescientific era, much like vitalism...
[Just as science dispatched vitalism] the science of consciousness will
keep eating away at the hard problem of consciousness until it
vanishes.