The philosophy of perception is concerned with the nature of perceptual experience and the status of perceptual data, in particular how they relate to beliefs about, or knowledge of, the world. Any explicit account of perception requires a commitment to one of a variety of ontological or metaphysical views. Philosophers distinguish internalist accounts, which assume that perceptions of objects, and knowledge or beliefs about them, are aspects of an individual's mind, and externalist accounts, which state that they constitute real aspects of the world external to the individual. The position of naïve realism—the
'everyday' impression of physical objects constituting what is
perceived—is to some extent contradicted by the occurrence of perceptual
illusions and hallucinations and the relativity of perceptual experience as well as certain insights in science. Realist conceptions include phenomenalism and direct and indirect realism. Anti-realist conceptions include idealism and skepticism.
Categories of perception
We may categorize perception as internal or external.
- Internal perception (proprioception) tells us what is going on in our bodies; where our limbs are, whether we are sitting or standing, whether we are depressed, hungry, tired and so forth.
- External or sensory perception (exteroception), tells us about the world outside our bodies. Using our senses of sight, hearing, touch, smell, and taste, we perceive colors, sounds, textures, etc. of the world at large. There is a growing body of knowledge of the mechanics of sensory processes in cognitive psychology.
- Mixed internal and external perception (e.g., emotion and certain moods) tells us about what is going on in our bodies and about the perceived cause of our bodily perceptions.
The philosophy of perception is mainly concerned with exteroception.
Scientific accounts of perception
An
object at some distance from an observer will reflect light in all
directions, some of which will fall upon the corneas of the eyes, where it will be focused upon each retina,
forming an image. The disparity between the electrical output of these
two slightly different images is resolved either at the level of the lateral geniculate nucleus or in a part of the visual cortex
called 'V1'. The resolved data is further processed in the visual
cortex where some areas have specialized functions, for instance area V5
is involved in the modelling of motion and V4 in adding color. The
resulting single image that subjects report as their experience is
called a 'percept'. Studies involving rapidly changing scenes show the
percept derives from numerous processes that involve time delays. Recent fMRI studies
show that dreams, imaginings and perceptions of things such as faces
are accompanied by activity in many of the same areas of brain as are
involved with physical sight. Imagery that originates from the senses
and internally generated imagery may have a shared ontology at higher levels of cortical processing.
Sound is analyzed in term of pressure waves sensed by the cochlea
in the ear. Data from the eyes and ears is combined to form a 'bound'
percept. The problem of how this is produced, known as the binding problem.
Perception is analyzed as a cognitive process in which information processing
is used to transfer information into the mind where it is related to
other information. Some psychologists propose that this processing gives
rise to particular mental states (cognitivism) whilst others envisage a direct path back into the external world in the form of action (radical behaviorism). Behaviorists such as John B. Watson and B.F. Skinner have proposed that perception acts largely as a process between a stimulus and a response but have noted that Gilbert Ryle's "ghost in the machine
of the brain" still seems to exist. "The objection to inner states is
not that they do not exist, but that they are not relevant in a
functional analysis". This view, in which experience is thought to be an incidental by-product of information processing, is known as epiphenomenalism.
Contrary to the behavioralist approach to understanding the elements of cognitive processes, gestalt psychology sought to understand their organization as a whole, studying perception as a process of figure and ground.
Philosophical accounts of perception
Important philosophical problems derive from the epistemology of perception—how we can gain knowledge via perception—such as the question of the nature of qualia. Within the biological study of perception naive realism is unusable. However, outside biology modified forms of naive realism are defended. Thomas Reid, the eighteenth-century founder of the Scottish School of Common Sense,
formulated the idea that sensation was composed of a set of data
transfers but also declared that there is still a direct connection
between perception and the world. This idea, called direct realism, has
again become popular in recent years with the rise of postmodernism.
The succession of data transfers involved in perception suggests that sense data are somehow available to a perceiving subject that is the substrate of the percept. Indirect realism, the view held by John Locke and Nicolas Malebranche, proposes that we can only be aware of mental representations
of objects. However, this may imply an infinite regress (a perceiver
within a perceiver within a perceiver...), though a finite regress is
perfectly possible.
It also assumes that perception is entirely due to data transfer and
information processing, an argument that can be avoided by proposing
that the percept does not depend wholly upon the transfer and
rearrangement of data. This still involves basic ontological issues of
the sort raised by Leibniz, Locke, Hume, Whitehead and others, which remain outstanding particularly in relation to the binding problem,
the question of how different perceptions (e.g. color and contour in
vision) are "bound" to the same object when they are processed by
separate areas of the brain.
Indirect realism (representational views) provides an account of issues such as perceptual contents, qualia, dreams, imaginings, hallucinations, illusions, the resolution of binocular rivalry, the resolution of multistable perception,
the modelling of motion that allows us to watch TV, the sensations that
result from direct brain stimulation, the update of the mental image by
saccades of the eyes and the referral of events backwards in time.
Direct realists must either argue that these experiences do not occur or
else refuse to define them as perceptions.
Idealism holds that reality is limited to mental qualities while
skepticism challenges our ability to know anything outside our minds.
One of the most influential proponents of idealism was George Berkeley who maintained that everything was mind or dependent upon mind. Berkeley's idealism has two main strands, phenomenalism in which physical events are viewed as a special kind of mental event and subjective idealism. David Hume is probably the most influential proponent of skepticism.
A fourth theory of perception in opposition to naive realism, enactivism, attempts to find a middle path between direct realist and indirect realist theories, positing that cognition
arises as a result of the dynamic interplay between an organism's
sensory-motor capabilities and its environment. Instead of seeing
perception as a passive process determined entirely by the features of
an independently existing world, enactivism suggests that organism and
environment are structurally coupled and co-determining. The theory was
first formalized by Francisco Varela, Evan Thompson, and Eleanor Rosch
in "The Embodied Mind".
Spatial representation
An aspect of perception that is common to both realists and anti-realists is the idea of mental or perceptual space. David Hume
concluded that things appear extended because they have attributes of
colour and solidity. A popular modern philosophical view is that the
brain cannot contain images so our sense of space must be due to the
actual space occupied by physical things. However, as René Descartes
noticed, perceptual space has a projective geometry, things within it
appear as if they are viewed from a point. The phenomenon of perspective was closely studied by artists and architects in the Renaissance, who relied mainly on the 11th century polymath, Alhazen (Ibn al-Haytham), who affirmed the visibility of perceptual space in geometric structuring projections. Mathematicians now know of many types of projective geometry such as complex Minkowski space
that might describe the layout of things in perception (see Peters
(2000)) and it has also emerged that parts of the brain contain patterns
of electrical activity that correspond closely to the layout of the
retinal image (this is known as retinotopy). How or whether these become conscious experience is still unknown (see McGinn (1995)).