The principle has a variety of expressions, all of which are perhaps best summarized by the following:
For every entity X, if X exists, then there is a sufficient explanation for why X exists.
For every event E, if E occurs, then there is a sufficient explanation for why E occurs.
For every proposition P, if P is true, then there is a sufficient explanation for why P is true.
A sufficient explanation may be understood either in terms of reasons or causes,
for like many philosophers of the period, Leibniz did not carefully
distinguish between the two. The resulting principle is very different,
however, depending on which interpretation is given (see Payne's summary of Schopenhauer's Fourfold Root).
It is an open question whether the principle of sufficient reason can be applied to axioms
within a logic construction like a mathematical or a physical theory,
because axioms are propositions accepted as having no justification
possible within the system. The principle declares that all propositions considered to be true within a system should be deducible
from the set axioms at the base of the construction (i.e., that they
ensue necessarily if we assume the system's axioms to be true). However, Gödel has shown that for every sufficiently expressive
deductive system a proposition exists that can neither be proved nor
disproved (see Gödel's incompleteness theorems).
Different views
Leibniz's view
Leibniz
identified two kinds of truth, necessary and contingent truths. And he
claimed that all truths are based upon two principles: (1) non-contradiction, and (2) sufficient reason. In the Monadology, he says,
Our reasonings are grounded upon two great principles,
that of contradiction, in virtue of which we judge false that which
involves a contradiction, and true that which is opposed or
contradictory to the false;
And that of sufficient reason, in virtue of which we hold that there can
be no fact real or existing, no statement true, unless there be a
sufficient reason, why it should be so and not otherwise, although these
reasons usually cannot be known by us (paragraphs 31 and 32).
Necessary truths can be derived from the law of identity (and the principle of non-contradiction):
"Necessary truths are those that can be demonstrated through an
analysis of terms, so that in the end they become identities, just as in
Algebra an equation expressing an identity ultimately results from the
substitution of values [for variables]. That is, necessary truths depend
upon the principle of contradiction." The sufficient reason for a necessary truth is that its negation is a contradiction.
Leibniz admitted contingent truths, that is, facts in the world
that are not necessarily true, but that are nonetheless true. Even these
contingent truths, according to Leibniz, can only exist on the basis of
sufficient reasons. Since the sufficient reasons for contingent truths
are largely unknown to humans, Leibniz made appeal to infinitary sufficient reasons, to which God uniquely has access:
In contingent truths, even though the predicate is in the
subject, this can never be demonstrated, nor can a proposition ever be
reduced to an equality or to an identity, but the resolution proceeds to
infinity, God alone seeing, not the end of the resolution, of course,
which does not exist, but the connection of the terms or the containment
of the predicate in the subject, since he sees whatever is in the
series.
Without this qualification, the principle can be seen as a description of a certain notion of closed system, in which there is no 'outside' to provide unexplained events with causes. It is also in tension with the paradox of Buridan's ass,
because although the facts supposed in the paradox would present a
counterexample to the claim that all contingent truths are determined by
sufficient reasons, the key premise of the paradox must be rejected
when one considers Leibniz's typical infinitary conception of the world.
In consequence of this, the case also of Buridan's ass
between two meadows, impelled equally towards both of them, is a fiction
that cannot occur in the universe....For the universe cannot be halved
by a plane drawn through the middle of the ass, which is cut vertically
through its length, so that all is equal and alike on both
sides.....Neither the parts of the universe nor the viscera of the
animal are alike nor are they evenly placed on both sides of this
vertical plane. There will therefore always be many things in the ass
and outside the ass, although they be not apparent to us, which will
determine him to go on one side rather than the other. And although man
is free, and the ass is not, nevertheless for the same reason it must be
true that in man likewise the case of a perfect equipoise between two
courses is impossible. (Theodicy, pg. 150)
Leibniz also used the principle of sufficient reason to refute the idea of absolute space:
I say then, that if space is an absolute being, there
would be something for which it would be impossible there should be a
sufficient reason. Which is against my axiom. And I prove it thus. Space
is something absolutely uniform; and without the things placed in it,
one point in space does not absolutely differ in any respect whatsoever
from another point of space. Now from hence it follows, (supposing
space to be something in itself, beside the order of bodies among
themselves,) that 'tis impossible that there should be a reason why God,
preserving the same situation of bodies among themselves, should have
placed them in space after one particular manner, and not otherwise; why
everything was not placed the quite contrary way, for instance, by
changing East into West.
Hamilton's fourth law: "Infer nothing without ground or reason"
Here is how William Hamilton, circa 1837–1838, expressed his "fourth law" in his LECT. V. LOGIC. 60–61:
I now go on to the fourth law.
Par. XVII. Law of Sufficient Reason, or of Reason and Consequent:
XVII. The thinking of an object, as actually characterized by
positive or by negative attributes, is not left to the caprice of
Understanding – the faculty of thought; but that faculty must be
necessitated to this or that determinate act of thinking by a knowledge
of something different from, and independent of; the process of thinking
itself. This condition of our understanding is expressed by the law, as
it is called, of Sufficient Reason (principium Rationis Sufficientis); but it is more properly denominated the law of Reason and Consequent (principium Rationis et Consecutionis). That knowledge by which the mind is necessitated to affirm or posit something else, is called the logical reason ground, or antecedent; that something else which the mind is necessitated to affirm or posit, is called the logical consequent; and the relation between the reason and consequent, is called the logical connection or consequence. This law is expressed in the formula – Infer nothing without a ground or reason.
Relations between Reason and Consequent: The relations between Reason and Consequent, when comprehended in a pure thought, are the following:
When a reason is explicitly or implicitly given, then there must exist a consequent; and, vice versa, when a consequent is given, there must also exist a reason.
Where there is no reason there can be no consequent; and, vice versa,
where there is no consequent (either implicitly or explicitly) there
can be no reason. That is, the concepts of reason and of consequent, as
reciprocally relative, involve and suppose each other.
The logical significance of this law: The logical significance
of the law of Reason and Consequent lies in this, – That in virtue of
it, thought is constituted into a series of acts all indissolubly
connected; each necessarily inferring the other. Thus it is that the
distinction and opposition of possible, actual and necessary matter,
which has been introduced into Logic, is a doctrine wholly extraneous to
this science."
First Form: The Principle of Sufficient Reason of Becoming
(principium rationis sufficientis fiendi); appears as the law of
causality in the understanding.
Second Form: The Principle of Sufficient Reason of Knowing
(principium rationis sufficientis cognoscendi); asserts that if a
judgment is to express a piece of knowledge, it must have a sufficient
ground or reason, in which case it receives the predicate true.
Third Form: The Principle of Sufficient Reason of Being
(principium rationis sufficientis essendi); the law whereby the parts of
space and time determine one another as regards those relations. Example in arithmetic: Each number presupposes the preceding numbers
as grounds or reasons of its being; "I can reach ten only by going
through all the preceding numbers; and only by virtue of this insight
into the ground of being, do I know that where there are ten, so are
there eight, six, four."
"Now just as the subjective correlative to the first
class of representations is the understanding, that to the second the
faculty of reason, and that to the third pure sensibility, so is the
subjective correlative to this fourth class found to be the inner sense,
or generally self-consciousness."
Fourth Form: The Principle of Sufficient Reason of Acting (principium
rationis sufficientis agendi); briefly known as the law of motivation. "Any judgment that does not follow its previously existing ground or
reason" or any state that cannot be explained away as falling under the
three previous headings "must be produced by an act of will which has a
motive." As his proposition in 43 states, "Motivation is causality seen
from within."
As a law of thought
The principle was one of the four recognised laws of thought, that held a place in European pedagogy of logic and reasoning (and, to some extent, philosophy in general) in the 18th and 19th centuries. It was influential in the thinking of Leo Tolstoy, amongst others, in the elevated form that history could not be accepted as random.
A sufficient reason is sometimes described as the coincidence of
every single thing that is needed for the occurrence of an effect (i.e.
of the so-called necessary conditions).
Definitions of knowledge aim to identify the essential features of knowledge. Closely related terms are conception of knowledge, theory of knowledge, and analysis of knowledge. Some general features of knowledge are widely accepted among philosophers, for example, that it involves cognitive success and epistemic contact with reality. Despite extensive study, disagreements about the nature of knowledge persist, in part because researchers use diverging methodologies, seek definitions for distinct purposes, and have differing intuitions about the standards of knowledge.
An often-discussed definition asserts that knowledge is justified true belief. Justification means that the belief fulfills certain norms like being based on good reasons or being the product of a reliable cognitive process. This approach seeks to distinguish knowledge from mere true beliefs that arise from superstition, lucky guesses, or flawed reasoning. Critics of the justified-true-belief view, like Edmund Gettier, have proposed counterexamples
to show that some justified true beliefs do not amount to knowledge if
the justification is not genuinely connected to the truth, a condition
termed epistemic luck.
In response, some philosophers have expanded the
justified-true-belief definition with additional criteria intended to
avoid these counterexamples. Suggested criteria include that the known
fact caused the belief, that the belief manifests a cognitive virtue, that the belief is not inferred from a falsehood, and that the justification cannot be undermined.
However, not all philosophers agree that such modifications are
successful. Some propose a radical reconceptualization or hold that knowledge is a unique state not definable as a combination of other states.
Most definitions seek to understand the features of propositional knowledge, which is theoretical knowledge of a fact that can be expressed through a declarative that-clause, such as "knowing that Dave is at home". Other definitions focus on practical knowledge and knowledge by acquaintance.
Practical knowledge concerns the ability to do something, like knowing
how to swim. Knowledge by acquaintance is a familiarity with something
based on experiential contact, like knowing the taste of chocolate.
General characteristics and disagreements
Definitions of knowledge try to describe the essential features
of knowledge. This includes clarifying the distinction between knowing
something and not knowing it, for example, pointing out what is the
difference between knowing that smoking causes cancer and not knowing
this. Sometimes the expressions "conception of knowledge", "theory of knowledge", and "analysis of knowledge" are used as synonyms.Various general features of knowledge are widely accepted. For example, it can be understood as a form of cognitive
success or epistemic contact with reality, and propositional knowledge
may be characterized as "believing a true proposition in a good way".
However, such descriptions are too vague to be very useful without
further clarifications of what "cognitive success" means, what type of
success is involved, or what constitutes "good ways of believing".
The disagreements about the nature of knowledge are both numerous and deep. Some of these disagreements stem from the fact that there are different
ways of defining a term, both in relation to the goal one intends to
achieve and concerning the method used to achieve it. These difficulties are further exacerbated by the fact that the term
"knowledge" has historically been used for a great range of diverse
phenomena. These phenomena include theoretical know-that, as in knowing that Paris is in France, practical know-how, as in knowing how to swim, and knowledge by acquaintance, as in personally knowing a celebrity. It is not clear that there is one underlying essence to all of these
forms. For this reason, most definitions restrict themselves either
explicitly or implicitly to knowledge-that, also termed "propositional
knowledge", which is seen as the most paradigmatic type of knowledge.
Even when restricted to propositional knowledge, the differences
between the various definitions are usually substantial. For this
reason, the choice of one's conception of knowledge matters for
questions like whether a particular mental state constitutes knowledge,
whether knowledge is fairly common or quite rare, and whether there is
knowledge at all. The problem of the definition and analysis of knowledge has been a
subject of intense discussion within epistemology both in the 20th and
the 21st century. The branch of philosophy studying knowledge is called epistemology.
Goals
An
important reason for these disagreements is that different theorists
often have very different goals in mind when trying to define knowledge.
Some definitions are based mainly on the practical concern of being
able to find instances of knowledge. For such definitions to be
successful, it is not required that they identify all and only its
necessary features.
In many cases, easily identifiable contingent features can even be more
helpful for the search than precise but complicated formulas. On the theoretical side, on the other hand, there are so-called real definitions that aim to grasp the term's essence in order to understand its place on the conceptual map in relation to other concepts.
Real definitions are preferable on the theoretical level since they are
very precise. However, it is often very hard to find a real definition
that avoids all counterexamples. Real definitions usually presume that knowledge is a natural kind, like "human being" or "water" and unlike "candy" or "large plant". Natural kinds are clearly distinguishable on the scientific level from other phenomena. As a natural kind, knowledge may be understood as a specific type of mental state. In this regard, the term "analysis of knowledge" is used to indicate
that one seeks different components that together make up propositional
knowledge, usually in the form of its essential features or as the
conditions that are individually necessary and jointly sufficient. This may be understood in analogy to a chemist analyzing a sample to discover its chemical compositions in the form of the elements involved in it. In most cases, the proposed features of knowledge apply to many
different instances. However, the main difficulty for such a project is
to avoid all counterexamples, i.e. there should be no instances that
escape the analysis, not even in hypothetical thought experiments. By trying to avoid all possible counterexamples, the analysis of aims at arriving at a necessary truth about knowledge.
However, the assumption that knowledge is a natural kind that has
precisely definable criteria is not generally accepted and some hold
that the term "knowledge" refers to a merely conventional accomplishment
that is artificially constituted and approved by society. In this regard, it may refer to a complex situation involving various external and internal aspects. This distinction is significant because if knowledge is not a natural
kind then attempts to provide a real definition would be futile from the
start even though definitions based merely on how the word is commonly
used may still be successful. However, the term would not have much
general scientific importance except for linguists and anthropologists studying how people use language and what they value. Such usage may differ radically from one culture to another. Many epistemologists have accepted, often implicitly, that knowledge
has a real definition. But the inability to find an acceptable real
definition has led some to understand knowledge in more conventionalist terms.
Methods
Besides these differences concerning the goals of defining knowledge, there are also important methodological
differences regarding how one arrives at and justifies one's
definition. One approach simply consists in looking at various
paradigmatic cases of knowledge to determine what they all have in
common. However, this approach is faced with the problem that it is not
always clear whether knowledge is present in a particular case, even in
paradigmatic cases. This leads to a form of circularity, known as the problem of the criterion:
criteria of knowledge are needed to identify individual cases of
knowledge and cases of knowledge are needed to learn what the criteria
of knowledge are.Two approaches to this problem have been suggested: methodism and particularism.
Methodists put their faith in their pre-existing intuitions or
hypotheses about the nature of knowledge and use them to identify cases
of knowledge. Particularists, on the other hand, hold that our judgments about particular cases are more reliable and use them to arrive at the general criteria. A closely related method, based more on the linguistic level, is to
study how the word "knowledge" is used. However, there are numerous
meanings ascribed to the term, many of which correspond to the different
types of knowledge. This introduces the additional difficulty of first
selecting the expressions belonging to the intended type before
analyzing their usage.
Standards of knowledge
A
further source of disagreement and difficulty in defining of knowledge
is posed by the fact that there are many different standards of
knowledge. The term "standard of knowledge" refers to how high the
requirements are for ascribing knowledge to someone. To claim that a
belief amounts to knowledge is to attribute a special epistemic status
to this belief. But exactly what status this is, i.e. what standard a
true belief has to pass to amount to knowledge, may differ from context
to context.While some theorists use very high standards, like infallibility
or absence of cognitive luck, others use very low standards by claiming
that mere true belief is sufficient for knowledge, that justification
is not necessary. For example, according to some standards, having read somewhere that the Solar System
has eight planets is a sufficient justification for knowing this fact.
According to others, a deep astronomical understanding of the relevant
measurements and the precise definition of "planet" is necessary. In the
history of philosophy, various theorists have set an even higher
standard and assumed that certainty or infallibility is necessary. For example, this is René Descartes's approach, who aims to find absolutely certain or indubitablefirst principles to act as the foundation of all subsequent knowledge. However, this outlook is uncommon in the contemporary approach. Contextualists
have argued that the standards depend on the context in which the
knowledge claim is made. For example, in a low-stake situation, a person
may know that the Solar System has 8 planets, even though the same
person lacks this knowledge in a high-stake situation.
The question of the standards of knowledge is highly relevant to
how common or rare knowledge is. According to the standards of everyday
discourse, ordinary cases of perception and memory
lead to knowledge. In this sense, even small children and animals
possess knowledge. But according to a more rigorous conception, they do
not possess knowledge since much higher standards need to be fulfilled. The standards of knowledge are also central to the question of whether skepticism,
i.e. the thesis that we have no knowledge at all, is true. If very high
standards are used, like infallibility, then skepticism becomes
plausible. In this case, the skeptic only has to show that any putative knowledge
state lacks absolute certainty, that while the actual belief is true, it
could have been false. However, the more these standards are weakened
to how the term is used in everyday language, the less plausible
skepticism becomes.
Many philosophers define knowledge as justified true belief (JTB). This definition characterizes knowledge in relation to three essential features: S knows that p if and only if (1) p is true, (2) Sbelieves that p, and (3) this belief is justified. A version of this definition was considered and rejected by Socrates in Plato's Theaetetus.Today, there is wide, though not universal, agreement among analytic
philosophers that the first two criteria are correct, i.e., that
knowledge implies true belief. Most of the controversy concerns the role
of justification: what it is, whether it is needed, and what additional
requirements it has to fulfill.
Truth
There is wide agreement that knowledge implies truth. In this regard, one cannot know things that are not true even if the corresponding belief is justified and rational. As an example, nobody can know that Winston Churchill won the 1996 US Presidential election,
since this was not the result of the election. This reflects the idea
that knowledge is a relation through which a person stands in cognitive
contact with reality. This contact implies that the known proposition is true.
Nonetheless, some theorists have also proposed that truth may not
always be necessary for knowledge. In this regard, a justified belief
that is widely held within a community may be seen as knowledge even if
it is false. Another doubt is due to some cases in everyday discourse where the term
is used to express a strong conviction. For example, a strong supporter
of Hillary Clinton might claim that they "knew" she would win the 2016
US presidential election. But such examples have not convinced many
theorists. Instead, this claim is probably better understood as an
exaggeration than as an actual knowledge claim. Such doubts are minority opinions and most theorists accept that knowledge implies truth.
Belief
Knowledge is usually understood as a form of belief: to know something implies that one believes it. This means that the agent accepts the proposition in question. However, not all theorists agree with this. This rejection is often motivated by contrasts found in ordinary language suggesting that the two are mutually exclusive, as in "I do not believe that; I know it." Some see this difference in the strength of the agent's conviction by
holding that belief is a weak affirmation while knowledge entails a
strong conviction. However, the more common approach to such expressions is to understand
them not literally but through paraphrases, for example, as "I do not merely believe that; I know it." This way, the expression is compatible with seeing knowledge as a form of belief. A more abstract counterargument defines "believing" as "thinking with
assent" or as a "commitment to something being true" and goes on to show
that this applies to knowledge as well. A different approach, sometimes termed "knowledge first", upholds the
difference between belief and knowledge based on the idea that knowledge
is unanalyzable and therefore cannot be understood in terms of the
elements that compose it. But opponents of this view may simply reject
it by denying that knowledge is unanalyzable. So despite the mentioned arguments, there is still wide agreement that knowledge is a form of belief.
A few epistemologists hold that true belief by itself is sufficient for knowledge. However, this view is not very popular and most theorists accept that
merely true beliefs do not constitute knowledge. This is based on
various counterexamples, in which a person holds a true belief in virtue
of faulty reasoning or a lucky guess.
Justification
The
third component of the JTB definition is justification. It is based on
the idea that having a true belief is not sufficient for knowledge, that
knowledge implies more than just being right about something. So
beliefs based on dogmatic opinions, blind guesses, or erroneous reasoning do not constitute knowledge even if they are true. For example, if someone believes that Machu Picchu is in Peru because both expressions end with the letter u,
this true belief does not constitute knowledge. In this regard, a
central question in epistemology concerns the additional requirements
for turning a true belief into knowledge. There are many suggestions and
deep disagreements within the academic literature about what these
additional requirements are. A common approach is to affirm that the
additional requirement is justification. So true beliefs that are based on good justification constitute
knowledge, as when the belief about Machu Picchu is based on the
individual's vivid recent memory of traveling through Peru and visiting
Machu Picchu there. This line of thought has led many theorists to the
conclusion that knowledge is nothing but true belief that is justified.
However, it has been argued that some knowledge claims in
everyday discourse do not require justification. For example, when a
teacher is asked how many of his students knew that Vienna is the capital of Austria
in their last geography test, he may just cite the number of correct
responses given without concern for whether these responses were based
on justified beliefs. Some theorists characterize this type of knowledge
as "lightweight knowledge" in order to exclude it from their discussion
of knowledge.
A further question in this regard is how strong the justification
needs to be for a true belief to amount to knowledge. So when the agent
has some weak evidence for a belief, it may be reasonable to hold that
belief even though no knowledge is involved. Some theorists hold that the justification has to be certain or
infallible. This means that the justification of the belief guarantees
the belief's truth, similar to how in a deductive argument, the truth of its premises ensures the truth of its conclusion. However, this view severely limits the extension of knowledge to very
few beliefs, if any. Such a conception of justification threatens to
lead to a full-blown skepticism denying that we know anything at all.
The more common approach in the contemporary discourse is to allow
fallible justification that makes the justified belief rationally
convincing without ensuring its truth. This is similar to how ampliative arguments work, in contrast to deductive arguments. The problem with fallibilism is that the strength of justification
comes in degrees: the evidence may make it somewhat likely, quite
likely, or extremely likely that the belief is true. This poses the
question of how strong the justification needs to be in the case of
knowledge. The required degree may also depend on the context: knowledge
claims in low-stakes situations, such as among drinking buddies, have
lower standards than knowledge claims in high-stakes situations, such as
among experts in the academic discourse.
Internalism and externalism
Besides the issue about the strength of justification, there is also the more general question about its nature. Theories of justification are often divided into internalism
and externalism depending on whether only factors internal to the
subject are responsible for justification. Commonly, an internalist
conception is defended. This means that internal mental states of the subject justify beliefs. These states are usually understood as reasons or evidence possessed, like perceptual experiences, memories, rational intuition, or other justified beliefs.
One particular form of this position is evidentialism, which bases justification exclusively on the possession of evidence. It can be expressed by the claim that "Person S is justified in believing proposition p at time t if and only if S's evidence for p at t supports believing p". Some philosophers stipulate as an additional requirement to the
possession of evidence that the belief is actually based on this
evidence, i.e. that there is some kind of mental or causal link between
the evidence and belief. This is often referred to as "doxastic
justification". In contrast to this, having sufficient evidence for a
true belief but coming to hold this belief based on superstition is a
case of mere "propositional justification". Such a belief may not amount to knowledge even though the relevant
evidence is possessed. A particularly strict version of internalism is
access internalism. It holds that only states introspectively available
to the subject's experience are relevant to justification. This means
that deep unconscious states cannot act as justification. A closely related issue concerns the question of the internal structure
of these states or how they are linked to each other. According to foundationalists, some mental states constitute basic reasons that can justify without being themselves in need of justification. Coherentists
defend a more egalitarian position: what matters is not a privileged
epistemic status of some special states but the relation to all other
states. This means that a belief is justified if it fits into the
person's full network of beliefs as a coherent part.
Philosophers have commonly espoused an internalist conception of
justification. Various problems with internalism have led some
contemporary philosophers to modify the internalist account of knowledge
by using externalist conceptions of justification. Externalists include factors external to the person as well, such as the existence of a causal relation to the believed fact or to a reliable belief formation process. A prominent theory in this field is reliabilism, the theory that a true
belief is justified if it was brought about by a reliable cognitive
process that is likely to result in true beliefs. On this view, a true belief based on standard perceptual processes or
good reasoning constitutes knowledge. But this is not the case if wishful thinking or emotional attachment is the cause.
However, not all externalists understand their theories as
versions of the JTB account of knowledge. Some theorists defend an
externalist conception of justification while others use a narrow notion
of "justification" and understand externalism as implying that
justification is not required for knowledge, for example, that the
feature of being produced by a reliable process is not a form of justification but its surrogate. The same ambiguity is also found in the causal theory of knowledge.
In ancient philosophy
In Plato's Theaetetus, Socrates
considers a number of theories as to what knowledge is, first excluding
merely true belief as an adequate account. For example, an ill person
with no medical training, but with a generally optimistic attitude,
might believe that he will recover from his illness quickly.
Nevertheless, even if this belief turned out to be true, the patient
would not have known that he would get well since his belief
lacked justification. The last account that Plato considers is that
knowledge is true belief "with an account" that explains or defines it
in some way. According to Edmund Gettier, the view that Plato is describing here is that knowledge is justified true belief.
The truth of this view would entail that in order to know that a given
proposition is true, one must not only believe the relevant true
proposition, but must also have a good reason for doing so. One implication of this would be that no one would gain knowledge just by believing something that happened to be true.
Gettier problem and cognitive luck
The JTB definition of knowledge was already rejected in Plato's Theaetetus. The JTB definition came under severe criticism in the 20th century, mainly due to a series of counterexamples given by Edmund Gettier. This is commonly known as the Gettier problem
and includes cases in which a justified belief is true because of lucky
circumstances, i.e. where the person's reason for the belief is
irrelevant to its truth. A well-known example involves a person driving along a country road with many barn facades.
The driver does not know this and finally stops in front of the only
real barn. The idea of this case is that they have a justified true
belief that the object in front of them is a barn even though this does
not constitute knowledge. The reason is that it was just a lucky
coincidence that they stopped here and not in front of one of the many
fake barns, in which case they wouldn't have been able to tell the
difference either.
This and similar counterexamples aim to show that justification
alone is not sufficient, i.e. that there are some justified true beliefs
that do not amount to knowledge. A common explanation of such cases is
based on cognitive or epistemic luck.
The idea is that it is a lucky coincidence or a fortuitous accident
that the justified belief is true. So the justification is in some sense
faulty, not because it relies on weak evidence, but because the
justification is not responsible for the belief's truth. Various theorists have responded to this problem by talking about warranted
true belief instead. In this regard, warrant implies that the
corresponding belief is not accepted on the basis of mere cognitive luck
or accident.However, not everyone agrees that this and similar cases actually
constitute counterexamples to the JTB definition: some have argued that,
in these cases, the agent actually knows the fact in question, e.g.
that the driver in the fake barn example knows that the object in front
of them is a barn despite the luck involved. A similar defense is based
on the idea that to insist on the absence of cognitive luck leads to a
form of infallibilism about justification, i.e. that justification has
to guarantee the belief's truth. However, most knowledge claims are not
that strict and allow instead that the justification involved may be
fallible.
An Euler diagram
representing a version of the Justified True Belief definition of
knowledge that is adapted to the Gettier problem. This problem gives us
reason to think that not all justified true beliefs constitute
knowledge.
Edmund Gettier
is best known for his 1963 paper entitled "Is Justified True Belief
Knowledge?", which called into question the common conception of
knowledge as justified true belief. In just two and a half pages, Gettier argued that there are situations
in which one's belief may be justified and true, yet fail to count as
knowledge. That is, Gettier contended that while justified belief in a
true proposition is necessary for that proposition to be known, it is
not sufficient.
According to Gettier, there are certain circumstances in which
one does not have knowledge, even when all of the above conditions are
met. Gettier proposed two thought experiments, which have become known as Gettier cases, as counterexamples to the classical account of knowledge. One of the cases involves two men, Smith and Jones, who are awaiting
the results of their applications for the same job. Each man has ten
coins in his pocket. Smith has excellent reasons to believe that Jones
will get the job (the head of the company told him); and furthermore,
Smith knows that Jones has ten coins in his pocket (he recently counted
them). From this Smith infers: "The man who will get the job has ten
coins in his pocket." However, Smith is unaware that he also has
ten coins in his own pocket. Furthermore, it turns out that Smith, not
Jones, is going to get the job. While Smith has strong evidence to
believe that Jones will get the job, he is wrong. Smith therefore has a
justified true belief that the man who will get the job has ten coins in
his pocket; however, according to Gettier, Smith does not know
that the man who will get the job has ten coins in his pocket, because
Smith's belief is "...true by virtue of the number of coins in Jones's
pocket, while Smith does not know how many coins are in Smith's pocket,
and bases his belief... on a count of the coins in Jones's pocket, whom
he falsely believes to be the man who will get the job."
These cases fail to be knowledge because the subject's belief is
justified, but only happens to be true by virtue of luck. In other
words, he made the correct choice (believing that the man who will get
the job has ten coins in his pocket) for the wrong reasons. Gettier then
goes on to offer a second similar case, providing the means by which
the specifics of his examples can be generalized into a broader problem
for defining knowledge in terms of justified true belief.
There have been various notable responses to the Gettier problem.
Typically, they have involved substantial attempts to provide a new
definition of knowledge that is not susceptible to Gettier-style
objections, either by providing an additional fourth condition that
justified true beliefs must meet to constitute knowledge, or proposing a
completely new set of necessary and sufficient conditions
for knowledge. While there have been far too many published responses
for all of them to be mentioned, some of the most notable responses are
discussed below.
Responses and alternative definitions
The
problems with the JTB definition of knowledge have provoked diverse
responses. Strictly speaking, most contemporary philosophers deny the
JTB definition of knowledge, at least in its exact form. Edmund Gettier's counterexamples were very influential in shaping this contemporary outlook. They usually involve some form of cognitive luck whereby the
justification is not responsible or relevant to the belief being true. Some responses stay within the standard definition and try to make
smaller modifications to mitigate the problems, for example, concerning
how justification is defined. Others see the problems as insurmountable
and propose radical new conceptions of knowledge, many of which do not
require justification at all. Between these two extremes, various
epistemologists have settled for a moderate departure from the standard
definition. They usually accept that it is a step in the right
direction: justified true belief is necessary for knowledge. However,
they deny that it is sufficient. This means that knowledge always
implies justified true belief but that not every justified true belief
constitutes knowledge.Instead, they propose an additional fourth criterion needed for
sufficiency. The resulting definitions are sometimes referred to as
JTB+X accounts of knowledge. A closely related approach is to replace justification with warrant, which is then defined as justification together with whatever else is needed to amount to knowledge.
The goal of introducing an additional criterion is to avoid
counterexamples in the form of Gettier cases. Numerous suggestions for
such a fourth feature have been made, for example, the requirement that
the belief is not inferred from a falsehood. While alternative accounts are often successful at avoiding many
specific cases, it has been argued that most of them fail to avoid all
counterexamples because they leave open the possibility of cognitive
luck. So while introducing an additional criterion may help exclude various
known examples of cognitive luck, the resulting definition is often
still susceptible to new cases. The only way to avoid this problem is to
ensure that the additional criterion excludes cognitive luck. This is
often understood in the sense that the presence of the feature has to
entail the belief's truth. So if it is possible that a belief has this
feature without being true, then cases of cognitive luck are possible in
which a true belief has this feature but is not true because of this
feature. The problem is avoided by defining knowledge as
non-accidentally true belief. A similar approach introduces an anti-luck condition: the belief is not
true merely by luck. But it is not clear how useful these definitions
are unless a more precise definition of "non-accidental" or "absence of
luck" could be provided. This vagueness makes the application to non-obvious cases difficult. A closely related and more precise definition requires that the belief is safely formed,
i.e. that the process responsible would not have produced the
corresponding belief if it was not true. This means that, whatever the
given situation is like, this process tracks the fact. Richard Kirkham suggests that our definition of knowledge requires that the evidence for the belief necessitates its truth.
Defeasibility theory
Defeasibility
theories of knowledge introduce an additional condition based on
defeasibility in order to avoid the different problems faced by the JTB
accounts. They emphasize that, besides having a good reason for holding
the belief, it is also necessary that there is no defeating evidence
against it. This is usually understood in a very wide sense: a justified true
belief does not amount to knowledge when there is a truth that would
constitute a defeating reason
of the belief if the person knew about it. This wide sense is necessary
to avoid Gettier cases of cognitive luck. So in the barn example above,
it explains that the belief does not amount to knowledge because, if
the person were aware of the prevalence of fake barns in this area, this
awareness would act as a defeater of the belief that this one
particular building is a real barn. In this way, the defeasibility
theory can identify accidentally justified beliefs as unwarranted. One
of its problems is that it excludes too many beliefs from knowledge.
This concerns specifically misleading defeaters, i.e. truths that would give the false impression to the agent that one of their reasons was defeated. According to Keith Lehrer,
cases of cognitive luck can be avoided by requiring that the
justification does not depend on any false statement. On his view, "S knows that p if and only if (i) it is true that p, (ii) S accepts that p, (iii) S is justified in accepting that p, and (iv) S is justified in accepting p in some way that does not depend on any false statement".
Reliabilism and causal theory
Reliabilistic
and causal theories are forms of externalism. Some versions only modify
the JTB definition of knowledge by reconceptualizing what justification
means. Others constitute further departures by holding that
justification is not necessary, that reliability or the right causal
connections act as replacements of justification. According to
reliabilism, a true belief constitutes knowledge if it was produced by a
reliable process or method. Putative examples of reliable processes are regular perception under normal circumstances and the scientific method. Defenders of this approach affirm that reliability acts as a safeguard against lucky coincidence. Virtue reliabilism is a special form of reliabilism in which
intellectual virtues, such as properly functioning cognitive faculties,
are responsible for producing knowledge.
Reliabilists have struggled to give an explicit and plausible
account of when a process is reliable. One approach defines it through a
high success rate:
a belief-forming process is reliable within a certain area if it
produces a high ratio of true beliefs in this area. Another approach
understands reliability in terms of how the process would fare in counterfactual
scenarios. Arguments against both of these definitions have been
presented. A further criticism is based on the claim that reliability is
not sufficient in cases where the agent is not in possession of any
reasons justifying the belief even though the responsible process is
reliable.
The causal theory of knowledge holds that the believed fact has
to cause the true belief in the right way for the belief to amount to
knowledge.For example, the belief that there is a bird in the tree may constitute
knowledge if the bird and the tree caused the corresponding perception
and belief. The causal connection helps to avoid some cases of cognitive
luck since the belief is not accidental anymore. However, it does not
avoid all of them, as can be seen in the fake barn example above, where
the perception of the real barn caused the belief about the real barn
even though it was a lucky coincidence. Another shortcoming of the
causal theory is that various beliefs are knowledge even though a causal
connection to the represented facts does not exist or may not be
possible. This is the case for beliefs in mathematical propositions, like that "2
+ 2 = 4", and in certain general propositions, like that "no elephant
is smaller than a kitten".
Virtue-theoretic definition
Virtue-theoretic approaches try to avoid the problem of cognitive luck by seeing knowledge as a manifestation of intellectual virtues. On this view, virtues are properties of a person that aim at some good.
In the case of intellectual virtues, the principal good is truth. In
this regard, Linda Zagzebski defines knowledge as "cognitive contact with reality arising out of acts of intellectual virtue". A closely related approach understands intellectual virtues in analogy
to the successful manifestation of skills. This is helpful to clarify
how cognitive luck is avoided. For example, an archer may hit the bull's
eye due to luck or because of their skill. Based on this line of
thought, Ernest Sosa defines knowledge as a belief that "is true in a way manifesting, or attributable to, the believer's skill".
One of the earliest suggested replies to Gettier, and perhaps the
most intuitive way to respond to the Gettier problem, is the "no false
premises" response, sometimes also called the "no false lemmas" response. Most notably, this reply was defended by David Malet Armstrong in his 1973 book, Belief, Truth, and Knowledge. The basic form of the response is to assert that the person who holds
the justified true belief (for instance, Smith in Gettier's first case)
made the mistake of inferring a true belief (e.g. "The person who will
get the job has ten coins in his pocket") from a false belief (e.g.
"Jones will get the job"). Proponents of this response therefore propose
that we add a fourth necessary and sufficient condition for knowledge,
namely, "the justified true belief must not have been inferred from a
false belief".
This reply to the Gettier problem is simple, direct, and appears
to isolate what goes wrong in forming the relevant beliefs in Gettier
cases. However, the general consensus is that it fails. This is because while the original formulation by Gettier includes a
person who infers a true belief from a false belief, there are many
alternate formulations in which this is not the case. Take, for
instance, a case where an observer sees what appears to be a dog walking
through a park and forms the belief "There is a dog in the park". In
fact, it turns out that the observer is not looking at a dog at all, but
rather a very lifelike robotic facsimile of a dog. However, unbeknownst
to the observer, there is in fact a dog in the park, albeit one
standing behind the robotic facsimile of a dog. Since the belief "There
is a dog in the park" does not involve a faulty inference, but is
instead formed as the result of misleading perceptual information, there
is no inference made from a false premise. It therefore seems that
while the observer does in fact have a true belief that her perceptual
experience provides justification for holding, she does not actually know that there is a dog in the park. Instead, she just seems to have formed a "lucky" justified true belief.
Infallibilist response
One less common response to the Gettier problem is defended by Richard Kirkham, who has argued that the only definition of knowledge that could ever be immune to all counterexamples is the infallibilist definition. To qualify as an item of knowledge, goes the theory, a belief must not
only be true and justified, the justification of the belief must necessitate its truth. In other words, the justification for the belief must be infallible.
While infallibilism is indeed an internally coherent response to
the Gettier problem, it is incompatible with our everyday knowledge
ascriptions. For instance, as the Cartesian skeptic
will point out, all of my perceptual experiences are compatible with a
skeptical scenario in which I am completely deceived about the existence
of the external world, in which case most (if not all) of my beliefs
would be false. The typical conclusion to draw from this is that it is possible to
doubt most (if not all) of my everyday beliefs, meaning that if I am
indeed justified in holding those beliefs, that justification is not
infallible. For the justification to be infallible, my reasons for
holding my everyday beliefs would need to completely exclude the
possibility that those beliefs were false. Consequently, if a belief
must be infallibly justified in order to constitute knowledge, then it
must be the case that we are mistaken in most (if not all) instances in
which we claim to have knowledge in everyday situations. While it is indeed possible to bite the bullet and accept this
conclusion, most philosophers find it implausible to suggest that we
know nothing or almost nothing, and therefore reject the infallibilist
response as collapsing into radical skepticism.
Tracking condition
Robert Nozick has offered a definition of knowledge according to which S knows that P if and only if:
P is true;
S believes that P;
if P were false, S would not believe that P;
if P were true, S would believe that P.
Nozick argues that the third of these conditions serves to address
cases of the sort described by Gettier. Nozick further claims this
condition addresses a case of the sort described by D.M. Armstrong: A father believes his daughter is innocent of committing a particular
crime, both because of faith in his baby girl and (now) because he has
seen presented in the courtroom a conclusive demonstration of his
daughter's innocence. His belief via the method of the courtroom
satisfies the four subjunctive conditions, but his faith-based belief
does not. If his daughter were guilty, he would still believe her
innocence, on the basis of faith in his daughter; this would violate the
third condition.
The British philosopher Simon Blackburn
has criticized this formulation by suggesting that we do not want to
accept as knowledge beliefs which, while they "track the truth" (as
Nozick's account requires), are not held for appropriate reasons. In addition to this, externalist accounts of knowledge, such as
Nozick's, are often forced to reject closure in cases where it is
intuitively valid.
An account similar to Nozick's has also been offered by Fred Dretske,
although his view focuses more on relevant alternatives that might have
obtained if things had turned out differently. Views of both the Nozick
variety and the Dretske variety have faced serious problems suggested
by Saul Kripke.
Knowledge-first response
Timothy Williamson
has advanced a theory of knowledge according to which knowledge is not
justified true belief plus some extra conditions, but primary. In his
book Knowledge and its Limits,
Williamson argues that the concept of knowledge cannot be broken down
into a set of other concepts through analysis—instead, it is sui generis. Thus, according to Williamson, justification, truth, and belief are necessary but not sufficient for knowledge. Williamson is also known for being one of the only philosophers who take knowledge to be a mental state; most epistemologists assert that belief (as opposed to knowledge) is a
mental state. As such, Williamson's claim has been seen to be highly
counterintuitive.
Merely true belief
In his 1991 paper, "Knowledge is Merely True Belief", Crispin Sartwell argues that justification is an unnecessary criterion for knowledge. He argues that common counterexample cases of "lucky guesses" are not
in fact beliefs at all, as "no belief stands in isolation... the claim
that someone believes something entails that that person has some degree
of serious commitment to the claim." He gives the example of a
mathematician working on a problem who subconsciously, in a "flash of
insight", sees the answer, but is unable to comprehensively justify his
belief, and says that in such a case the mathematician still knows the
answer, despite not being able to give a step-by-step explanation of how
he got to it. He also argues that if beliefs require justification to
constitute knowledge, then foundational beliefs can never be knowledge,
and, as these are the beliefs upon which all our other beliefs depend
for their justification, we can thus never have knowledge at all.
Nyaya philosophy
Nyaya is one of the six traditional schools of Indian philosophy with a particular interest in epistemology. The Indian philosopher B.K. Matilal drew on the Navya-Nyāyafallibilist tradition to respond to the Gettier problem. Nyaya theory distinguishes between know p and know that one knows p—these
are different events, with different causal conditions. The second
level is a sort of implicit inference that usually follows immediately
the episode of knowing p (knowledge simpliciter). The Gettier case is examined by referring to a view of Gangesha Upadhyaya
(late 12th century), who takes any true belief to be knowledge; thus a
true belief acquired through a wrong route may just be regarded as
knowledge simpliciter on this view. The question of justification arises
only at the second level, when one considers the knowledge-hood of the
acquired belief. Initially, there is lack of uncertainty, so it becomes a
true belief. But at the very next moment, when the hearer is about to
embark upon the venture of knowing whether he knows p, doubts may
arise. "If, in some Gettier-like cases, I am wrong in my inference
about the knowledge-hood of the given occurrent belief (for the evidence
may be pseudo-evidence), then I am mistaken about the truth of my
belief—and this is in accordance with Nyaya fallibilism: not all
knowledge-claims can be sustained."
Other definitions
According to J. L. Austin, to know just means to be able to make correct assertions about the subject in question. On this pragmatic view, the internal mental states of the knower do not matter.
Philosopher Barry Allen also downplayed the role of mental states
in knowledge and defined knowledge as "superlative artifactual
performance", that is, exemplary performance with artifacts, including
language but also technological objects like bridges, satellites, and
diagrams. Allen criticized typical epistemology for its "propositional bias"
(treating propositions as prototypical knowledge), its "analytic bias"
(treating knowledge as prototypically mental or conceptual), and its
"discursive bias" (treating knowledge as prototypically discursive). He considered knowledge to be too diverse to characterize in terms of necessary and sufficient conditions. He claimed not to be substituting knowledge-how for knowledge-that, but
instead proposing a definition that is more general than both. For Allen, knowledge is "deeper than language, different from belief, more valuable than truth".
A different approach characterizes knowledge in relation to the
role it plays, for example, regarding the reasons it provides or
constitutes for doing or thinking something. In this sense, it can be
understood as what entitles the agent to assert a fact, to use this fact
as a premise when reasoning, or to act as a trustworthy informant
concerning this fact. This definition has been adopted in some argumentation theory.
Paul Silva's "awareness first" epistemology posits that the common core of knowledge is awareness, providing a definition that accounts for both beliefless knowledge and knowledge grounded in belief.
Within anthropology, knowledge is often defined in a very broad sense as equivalent to understanding or culture. This includes the idea that knowledge consists in the affirmation of
meaning contents and depends on a substrate, such as a brain. Knowledge
characterizes social groups in the sense that different individuals
belonging to the same social niche tend to be very similar concerning
what they know and how they organize information. This topic is of specific interest to the subfield known as the anthropology of knowledge,
which uses this and similar definitions to study how knowledge is
reproduced and how it changes on the social level in different cultural
contexts.
Non-propositional knowledge
Propositional
knowledge, also termed factual knowledge or knowledge-that, is the most
paradigmatic form of knowledge in analytic philosophy, and most
definitions of knowledge in philosophy have this form in mind. It refers to the possession of certain information.
The distinction to other types of knowledge is often drawn based on the
differences between the linguistic formulations used to express them. It is termed knowledge-that since it can usually be expressed using a that-clause, as in "I know that Dave is at home". In everyday discourse, the term "knowledge" can also refer to various
other phenomena as forms of non-propositional knowledge. Some theorists
distinguish knowledge-wh from knowledge-that. Knowledge-wh is expressed
using a wh-clause, such as knowing why smoke causes cancer or knowing who killed John F. Kennedy. However, the more common approach is to understand knowledge-wh as a
type of knowledge-that since the corresponding expressions can usually
be paraphrased using a that-clause.
A clearer contrast is between knowledge-that and knowledge-how (know-how). Know-how is also referred to as practical knowledge or ability knowledge. It is expressed in formulations like, "I know how to ride a bike." All forms of practical knowledge involve some type of competence, i.e., having the ability
to do something. So to know how to play the guitar means to have the
competence to play it or to know the multiplication table is to be able
to recite products of numbers. For this reason, know-how may be defined as having the corresponding competence, skills, or abilities. Some forms of know-how include knowledge-that as well and some
theorists even argue that practical and propositional knowledge are of
the same type. However, propositional knowledge is usually reserved only to humans
while practical knowledge is more common in the animal kingdom. For
example, an ant knows how to walk but it presumably does not know that
it is currently walking in someone's kitchen. The more common view is, therefore, to see knowledge-how and knowledge-that as two distinct types of knowledge.
Another often-discussed alternative type of knowledge is knowledge by acquaintance.
It is defined as a direct familiarity with an individual, often with a
person, and only arises if one has met this individual personally. In this regard, it constitutes a relation not to a proposition but to
an object. Acquaintance implies that one has had a direct perceptual
experience with the object of knowledge and is therefore familiar with
it. Bertrand Russell contrasts it with knowledge by description,
which refers to knowledge of things that the subject has not
immediately experienced, such as learning through a documentary about a
country one has not yet visited. Knowledge by acquaintance can be expressed using a direct object,
such as, "I know Dave." It differs in this regard from knowledge-that
since no that-clause is needed. One can know facts about an individual
without direct acquaintance with that individual. For example, the
reader may know that Napoleon was a French military leader without knowing Napoleon personally. There is controversy whether knowledge by acquaintance is a form of
non-propositional knowledge. Some theorists deny this and contend that
it is just a grammatically different way of expressing propositional
knowledge.
In logic and mathematics, necessity and sufficiency are terms used to describe a conditional or implicational relationship between two statements. For example, in the conditional statement: "If P then Q", Q is necessary for P, because the truth of Q is "necessarily" guaranteed by the truth of P. (Equivalently, it is impossible to have P without Q, or the falsity of Q ensures the falsity of P.) Similarly, P is sufficient for Q, because P being true always or "sufficiently" implies that Q is true, but P not being true does not always imply that Q is not true.
In general, a necessary condition is one (possibly one of several
conditions) that must be present in order for another condition to
occur, while a sufficient condition is one that produces the said
condition.[3] The assertion that a statement is a "necessary and sufficient" condition of another means that the former statement is true if and only if the latter is true. That is, the two statements must be either simultaneously true, or simultaneously false.
In ordinary English (also natural language)
"necessary" and "sufficient" often indicate relations between
conditions or states of affairs, not statements. For example, being
round is a necessary condition for being a circle, but is not sufficient
since ovals and ellipses are round but not circles – while being a
circle is a sufficient condition for being round. Any conditional
statement consists of at least one sufficient condition and at least one
necessary condition.
In the conditional statement, "if S, then N", the expression represented by S is called the antecedent, and the expression represented by N is called the consequent. This conditional statement may be written in several equivalent ways, such as "N if S", "S only if N", "S implies N", "N is implied by S", S → N, S ⇒ N and "N whenever S".
In the above situation of "N whenever S", N is said to be a necessary condition for S. In common language, this is equivalent to saying that if the conditional statement is a true statement, then the consequent Nmust be true—if S is to be true (see third column of "truth table" immediately below). In other words, the antecedent S cannot be true without N being true. For example, in order for someone to be called Socrates, it is necessary for that someone to be Named. Similarly, in order for human beings to live, it is necessary that they have air.
One can also say S is a sufficient condition for N (refer again to the third column of the truth table immediately below). If the conditional statement is true, then if S is true, N
must be true; whereas if the conditional statement is true and N is
true, then S may be true or be false. In common terms, "the truth of S guarantees the truth of N". For example, carrying on from the previous example, one can say that knowing that someone is called Socrates is sufficient to know that someone has a Name.
A necessary and sufficient condition requires that both of the implications and (the latter of which can also be written as ) hold. The first implication suggests that S is a sufficient condition for N, while the second implication suggests that S is a necessary condition for N. This is expressed as "S is necessary and sufficient for N ", "Sif and only ifN", or .
Truth table
S
N
T
T
T
T
T
T
F
F
T
F
F
T
T
F
F
F
F
T
T
T
Necessity
The
sun being above the horizon is a necessary condition for direct
sunlight; but it is not a sufficient condition, as something else may be
casting a shadow, e.g., the moon in the case of an eclipse.
The assertion that Q is necessary for P is colloquially equivalent to "P cannot be true unless Q is true" or "if Q is false, then P is false". By contraposition, this is the same thing as "whenever P is true, so is Q".
The logical relation between P and Q is expressed as "if P, then Q" and denoted "P ⇒ Q" (PimpliesQ). It may also be expressed as any of "P only if Q", "Q, if P", "Q whenever P", and "Q when P".
One often finds, in mathematical prose for instance, several necessary
conditions that, taken together, constitute a sufficient condition
(i.e., individually necessary and jointly sufficient), as shown in Example 5.
Example 1
For it to be true that "John is a bachelor", it is necessary that it be also true that he is
unmarried,
male,
adult,
since to state "John is a bachelor" implies John has each of those three additional predicates.
Example 2
For the whole numbers greater than two, being odd is necessary to
being prime, since two is the only whole number that is both even and
prime.
Example 3
Consider thunder, the sound caused by lightning. One says that
thunder is necessary for lightning, since lightning never occurs without
thunder. Whenever there is lightning, there is thunder. The thunder does not cause
the lightning (since lightning causes thunder), but because lightning
always comes with thunder, we say that thunder is necessary for
lightning. (That is, in its formal sense, necessity doesn't imply
causality.)
Example 4
Being at least 30 years old is necessary for serving in the U.S.
Senate. If you are under 30 years old, then it is impossible for you to
be a senator. That is, if you are a senator, it follows that you must be
at least 30 years old.
Example 5
In algebra, for some setS together with an operation to form a group, it is necessary that be associative. It is also necessary that S include a special element e such that for every x in S, it is the case that ex and xe both equal x. It is also necessary that for every x in S there exist a corresponding element x″, such that both xx″ and x″ x equal the special element e. None of these three necessary conditions by itself is sufficient, but the conjunction of the three is.
Sufficiency
That
a train runs on schedule is a sufficient condition for a traveller
arriving on time (if one boards the train and it departs on time, then
one will arrive on time); but it is not a necessary condition, since
there are other ways to travel (if the train does not run to time, one
could still arrive on time through other means of transport).
If P is sufficient for Q, then knowing P to be true is adequate grounds to conclude that Q is true; however, knowing P to be false does not meet a minimal need to conclude that Q is false.
The logical relation is, as before, expressed as "if P, then Q" or "P ⇒ Q". This can also be expressed as "P only if Q", "P implies Q"
or several other variants. It may be the case that several sufficient
conditions, when taken together, constitute a single necessary condition
(i.e., individually sufficient and jointly necessary), as illustrated
in example 5.
Example 1
"John is a king" implies that John is male. So knowing that John is a king is sufficient to knowing that he is a male.
Example 2
A number's being divisible by 4 is sufficient (but not necessary)
for it to be even, but being divisible by 2 is both sufficient and
necessary for it to be even.
Example 3
An occurrence of thunder is a sufficient condition for the
occurrence of lightning in the sense that hearing thunder, and
unambiguously recognizing it as such, justifies concluding that there
has been a lightning bolt.
Example 4
If the U.S. Congress passes a bill, the president's signing of the
bill is sufficient to make it law. Note that the case whereby the
president did not sign the bill, e.g. through exercising a presidential veto, does not mean that the bill has not become a law (for example, it could still have become a law through a congressional override).
Example 5
That the center of a playing card
should be marked with a single large spade (♠) is sufficient for the
card to be an ace. Three other sufficient conditions are that the center
of the card be marked with a single diamond (♦), heart (♥), or club
(♣). None of these conditions is necessary to the card's being an ace,
but their disjunction is, since no card can be an ace without fulfilling at least (in fact, exactly) one of these conditions.
Relationship between necessity and sufficiency
Being
in the purple region is sufficient for being in A, but not necessary.
Being in A is necessary for being in the purple region, but not
sufficient. Being in A and being in B is necessary and sufficient for
being in the purple region.
A condition can be either necessary or sufficient without being the other. For instance, being a mammal (N) is necessary but not sufficient to being human (S), and that a number is rational (S) is sufficient but not necessary to being a real number (N) (since there are real numbers that are not rational).
A condition can be both necessary and sufficient. For example, at present, "today is the Fourth of July" is a necessary and sufficient condition for "today is Independence Day in the United States". Similarly, a necessary and sufficient condition for invertibility of a matrixM is that M has a nonzero determinant.
Mathematically speaking, necessity and sufficiency are dual to one another. For any statements S and N, the assertion that "N is necessary for S" is equivalent to the assertion that "S is sufficient for N".
Another facet of this duality is that, as illustrated above,
conjunctions (using "and") of necessary conditions may achieve
sufficiency, while disjunctions (using "or") of sufficient conditions
may achieve necessity. For a third facet, identify every mathematical predicateN with the set T(N) of objects, events, or statements for which N holds true; then asserting the necessity of N for S is equivalent to claiming that T(N) is a superset of T(S), while asserting the sufficiency of S for N is equivalent to claiming that T(S) is a subset of T(N).
Psychologically speaking, necessity and sufficiency are both key
aspects of the classical view of concepts. Under the classical theory of
concepts, how human minds represent a category X, gives rise to a set
of individually necessary conditions that define X. Together, these
individually necessary conditions are sufficient to be X. This contrasts with the probabilistic theory of concepts which states
that no defining feature is necessary or sufficient, rather that
categories resemble a family tree structure.
To say that P is necessary and sufficient for Q is to say two things:
that P is necessary for Q, , and that P is sufficient for Q, .
equivalently, it may be understood to say that P and Q is necessary for the other, , which can also be stated as each is sufficient for or implies the other.
One may summarize any, and thus all, of these cases by the statement "Pif and only ifQ", which is denoted by , whereas cases tell us that is identical to .
For example, in graph theory a graph G is called bipartite if it is possible to assign to each of its vertices the color black or white in such a way that every edge of G
has one endpoint of each color. And for any graph to be bipartite, it
is a necessary and sufficient condition that it contain no odd-length cycles. Thus, discovering whether a graph has any odd cycles tells one whether it is bipartite and conversely. A philosopher might characterize this state of affairs thus: "Although the concepts of bipartiteness and absence of odd cycles differ in intension, they have identical extension.
In mathematics, theorems are often stated in the form "P is true if and only if Q is true".
Because, as explained in previous section, necessity of one for
the other is equivalent to sufficiency of the other for the first one,
e.g. is equivalent to, if P is necessary and sufficient for Q, then Q is necessary and sufficient for P. We can write and say that the statements "P is true if and only ifQ, is true" and "Q is true if and only if P is true" are equivalent.