From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
The Gettier problem, in the field of epistemology, is a landmark philosophical problem concerning the understanding of descriptive knowledge. Attributed to American philosopher Edmund Gettier, Gettier-type counterexamples (called "Gettier-cases") challenge the long-held justified true belief
(JTB) account of knowledge. The JTB account holds that knowledge is
equivalent to justified true belief; if all three conditions
(justification, truth, and belief) are met of a given claim, then there
is knowledge of that claim. In his 1963 three-page paper titled "Is
Justified True Belief Knowledge?", Gettier attempts to illustrate by means of two counterexamples that
there are cases where individuals can have a justified, true belief
regarding a claim but still fail to know it because the reasons for the
belief, while justified, turn out to be false. Thus, Gettier claims to
have shown that the JTB account is inadequate because it does not
account for all of the necessary and sufficient conditions for knowledge.
The terms "Gettier problem", "Gettier case", or even the
adjective "Gettiered", are sometimes used to describe any case in the
field of epistemology that purports to repudiate the JTB account of
knowledge.
Responses to Gettier's paper have been numerous. Some reject
Gettier's examples as inadequate justification, while others seek to
adjust the JTB account of knowledge and blunt the force of these
counterexamples. Gettier problems have even found their way into
sociological experiments in which researchers have studied intuitive
responses to Gettier cases from people of varying demographics.
History
The question of what constitutes "knowledge" is as old as philosophy itself. Early instances are found in Plato's dialogues, notably Meno (97a–98b) and Theaetetus. Gettier himself was not actually the first to raise the problem named after him; its existence was acknowledged by both Alexius Meinong and Bertrand Russell, the latter of which discussed the problem in his book Human knowledge: Its scope and limits. In fact, the problem has been known since the Middle Ages, and both Indian philosopher Dharmottara and scholastic logician Peter of Mantua presented examples of it.
Dharmottara, in his commentary c. 770 AD on Dharmakirti's Ascertainment of Knowledge, gives the following two examples:
A fire has just been lit to roast
some meat. The fire hasn't started sending up any smoke, but the smell
of the meat has attracted a cloud of insects. From a distance, an
observer sees the dark swarm above the horizon and mistakes it for
smoke. "There's a fire burning at that spot," the distant observer says.
Does the observer know that there is a fire burning in the distance?
A desert traveller is searching for
water. He sees, in the valley ahead, a shimmering blue expanse.
Unfortunately, it's a mirage. But fortunately, when he reaches the spot
where there appeared to be water, there actually is water, hidden under a
rock. Did the traveller know, as he stood on the hilltop hallucinating, that there was water ahead?
Various theories of knowledge, including some of the proposals that
emerged in Western philosophy after Gettier in 1963, were debated by
Indo-Tibetan epistemologists before and after Dharmottara. In particular, Gaṅgeśa in the 14th century advanced a detailed causal theory of knowledge.
Russell's case, called the stopped clock case, goes as follows: Alice sees a clock that reads two o'clock and believes that the time is
two o'clock. It is, in fact, two o'clock. There's a problem, however:
unknown to Alice, the clock she's looking at stopped twelve hours ago.
Alice thus has an accidentally true, justified belief. Russell provides
an answer of his own to the problem. Edmund Gettier's formulation of the
problem was important as it coincided with the rise of the sort of philosophical naturalism promoted by W. V. O. Quine and others, and was used as a justification for a shift towards externalist theories of justification. John L. Pollock
and Joseph Cruz have stated that the Gettier problem has "fundamentally
altered the character of contemporary epistemology" and has become "a
central problem of epistemology since it poses a clear barrier to
analyzing knowledge".
Alvin Plantinga rejects the historical analysis:
According to the inherited lore of
the epistemological tribe, the JTB [justified true belief] account
enjoyed the status of epistemological orthodoxy until 1963, when it was
shattered by Edmund Gettier... Of course, there is an interesting
historical irony here: it isn't easy to find many really explicit
statements of a JTB analysis of knowledge prior to Gettier. It is almost
as if a distinguished critic created a tradition in the very act of
destroying it.
Despite this, Plantinga does accept that some philosophers before Gettier have advanced a JTB account of knowledge, specifically C. I. Lewis and A. J. Ayer.
Knowledge as justified true belief (JTB)
The
JTB account of knowledge is the claim that knowledge can be
conceptually analyzed as justified true belief, which is to say that the
meaning of sentences such as "Smith knows that it rained today" can be given with the following set of conditions, which are necessary and sufficient for knowledge to obtain:
A subject
S knows that a proposition
P is true
if and only if:
- P is true, and
- S believes that P is true, and
- S is justified in believing that P is true
The JTB account was first credited to Plato, though Plato argued against this very account of knowledge in the Theaetetus (210a). This account of knowledge is what Gettier subjected to criticism.
Gettier's two original counterexamples
Gettier's
paper used counterexamples to argue that there are cases of beliefs
that are both true and justified—therefore satisfying all three
conditions for knowledge on the JTB account—but that do not appear to be
genuine cases of knowledge. Therefore, Gettier argued, his
counterexamples show that the JTB account of knowledge is false, and
thus that a different conceptual analysis is needed to correctly track
what we mean by "knowledge".
Gettier's case is based on two counterexamples to the JTB
analysis, both involving a fictional character named Smith. Each relies
on two claims. Firstly, that justification is preserved by entailment,
and secondly that this applies coherently to Smith's putative "belief".
That is, that if Smith is justified in believing P, and Smith realizes
that the truth of P entails the truth of Q, then Smith would also be justified in believing Q. Gettier calls these counterexamples "Case I" and "Case II":
Case I
Suppose
that Smith and Jones have applied for a certain job. And suppose that
Smith has strong evidence for the following conjunctive proposition: (d)
Jones is the man who will get the job, and Jones has ten coins in his
pocket.
Smith's evidence for (d) might be that the president of the company
assured him that Jones would, in the end, be selected and that he,
Smith, had counted the coins in Jones's pocket ten minutes ago.
Proposition (d) entails: (e) The man who will get the job has ten coins
in his pocket.
Let us suppose that Smith sees the entailment from (d) to (e),
and accepts (e) on the grounds of (d), for which he has strong evidence.
In this case, Smith is clearly justified in believing that (e) is true.
But imagine, further, that unknown to Smith, he himself, not Jones, will
get the job. And, also, unknown to Smith, he himself has ten coins in
his pocket. Proposition (e) is true, though proposition (d), from which
Smith inferred (e), is false. In our example, then, all of the following
are true: (i) (e) is true, (ii) Smith believes that (e) is true, and
(iii) Smith is justified in believing that (e) is true. But it is
equally clear that Smith does not
know that (e) is true; for (e)
is true in virtue of the number of coins in Smith's pocket, while Smith
does not know how many coins are in his pocket, and bases his belief in
(e) on a count of the coins in Jones's pocket, whom he falsely believes
to be the man who will get the job.
Case II
Smith, it is claimed by the hidden
interlocutor, has a justified belief that "Jones owns a Ford". Smith therefore (justifiably) concludes (by the rule of
disjunction introduction)
that "Jones owns a Ford, or Brown is in Barcelona", even though Smith
has no information whatsoever about the location of Brown.
In fact, Jones does not own a Ford, but by sheer coincidence, Brown
really is in Barcelona. Again, Smith had a belief that was true and
justified, but not knowledge.
False premises and generalized Gettier-style problems
In both of Gettier's actual examples (see also counterfactual conditional), the justified true belief came about, if Smith's purported claims are disputable, as the result of entailment (but see also material conditional)
from justified false beliefs that "Jones will get the job" (in case I),
and that "Jones owns a Ford" (in case II). This led some early
responses to Gettier to conclude that the definition of knowledge could be easily adjusted, so that knowledge was justified true belief that does not depend on false premises.
The interesting issue that arises is then of how to know which premises
are in reality false or true when deriving a conclusion, because as in
the Gettier cases, one sees that premises can be very reasonable to
believe and be likely true, but unknown to the believer there are
confounding factors and extra information that may have been missed
while concluding something. The question that arises is therefore to
what extent would one have to be able to go about attempting to "prove"
all premises in the argument before solidifying a conclusion.
The generalized problem
In a 1966 scenario known as "The sheep in the field", Roderick Chisholm
asks us to imagine that someone, X, is standing outside a field looking
at something that looks like a sheep (although in fact, it is a dog
disguised as a sheep). X believes there is a sheep in the field, and in
fact, X is right because there is a sheep behind the hill in the middle
of the field. Hence, X has a justified true belief that there is a sheep
in the field.
Another scenario by Brian Skyrms
is "The Pyromaniac", in which a struck match lights not for the reasons
the pyromaniac imagines but because of some unknown "Q radiation".
A different perspective on the issue is given by Alvin Goldman in the "fake barns" scenario (crediting Carl Ginet
with the example). In this one, a man is driving in the countryside,
and sees what looks exactly like a barn. Accordingly, he thinks that he
is seeing a barn. In fact, that is what he is doing. But what he does
not know is that the neighborhood generally consists of many fake barns—barn facades designed to look exactly like real barns when viewed from the road.
Since, if he had been looking at one of them, he would have been unable
to tell the difference, his "knowledge" that he was looking at a barn
would seem to be poorly founded.
Objections to the "no false premises" approach
The "no false premises" (or "no false lemmas") solution which was proposed early in the discussion has been criticized, as more general Gettier-style problems were then constructed or
contrived in which the justified true belief is said to not seem to be
the result of a chain of reasoning from a justified false belief. For
example:
After arranging to meet with Mark for help
with homework, Luke arrives at the appointed time and place. Walking
into Mark's office Luke clearly sees Mark at his desk; Luke immediately
forms the belief "Mark is in the room. He can help me with my logic
homework". Luke is justified in his belief; he clearly sees Mark at his
desk. In fact, it is
not Mark that Luke saw, but rather a
hologram, perfect in every respect, giving the appearance of Mark
diligently grading papers at his desk. Nevertheless, Mark
is in the room; he is crouched under his desk reading
Frege.
Luke's belief that Mark is in the room is true (he is in the room,
under his desk) and justified (Mark's hologram is giving the appearance
of Mark hard at work).
It is argued that it seems as though Luke does not "know" that Mark
is in the room, even though it is claimed he has a justified true belief
that Mark is in the room, but it is not nearly so clear that the perceptual belief
that "Mark is in the room" was inferred from any premises at all, let
alone any false ones, nor led to significant conclusions on its own;
Luke did not seem to be reasoning about anything; "Mark is in the room"
seems to have been part of what he seemed to see.
Constructing Gettier problems
The
main idea behind Gettier's examples is that the justification for the
belief is flawed or incorrect, but the belief turns out to be true by
sheer luck. Linda Zagzebski
shows that any analysis of knowledge in terms of true belief and some
other element of justification that is independent from truth, will be
liable to Gettier cases. She offers a formula for generating Gettier cases:
(1) start with a case of justified false belief;
(2) amend the example, making the element of justification strong enough for knowledge, but the belief false by sheer chance;
(3) amend the example again, adding another element of chance
such that the belief is true, but which leaves the element of
justification unchanged;
This will generate an example of a belief that is sufficiently
justified (on some analysis of knowledge) to be knowledge, which is
true, and which is intuitively not an example of knowledge. In other
words, Gettier cases can be generated for any analysis of knowledge that
involves a justification criterion and a truth criterion, which are
highly correlated but have some degree of independence.
Responses to Gettier
The Gettier problem is formally a problem in first-order logic, but the introduction by Gettier of terms such as believes and knows
moves the discussion into the field of epistemology. Here, the sound
(true) arguments ascribed to Smith then need also to be valid (believed)
and convincing (justified) if they are to issue in the real-world
discussion about justified true belief.
Responses to Gettier problems have fallen into three categories:
- Affirmations of the JTB account: This response affirms
the JTB account of knowledge, but rejects Gettier cases. Typically, the
proponent of this response rejects Gettier cases because, they say,
Gettier cases involve insufficient levels of justification. Knowledge
actually requires higher levels of justification than Gettier cases
involve.
- Fourth condition responses: This response accepts the problem raised by Gettier cases, and affirms that JTB is necessary (but not sufficient)
for knowledge. A proper account of knowledge, according to this type of
view, will contain at least fourth condition (JTB + ?). With the fourth
condition in place, Gettier counterexamples (and other similar
counterexamples) will not work, and we will have an adequate set of
criteria that are both necessary and sufficient for knowledge.
- Justification replacement response: This response also
accepts the problem raised by Gettier cases. However, instead of
invoking a fourth condition, it seeks to replace justification itself
with some other third condition (?TB) that will make counterexamples
obsolete.
One response, therefore, is that in none of the above cases was the
belief justified because it is impossible to justify anything that is
not true. Conversely, the fact that a proposition turns out to be untrue
is proof that it was not sufficiently justified in the first place.
Under this interpretation, the JTB definition of knowledge survives.
This shifts the problem to a definition of justification, rather than
knowledge. Another view is that justification and non-justification are
not in binary opposition.
Instead, justification is a matter of degree, with an idea being more
or less justified. This account of justification is supported by
philosophers such as Paul Boghossian and Stephen Hicks.
In common sense usage, an idea can not only be more justified or less
justified but it can also be partially justified (Smith's boss told him
X) and partially unjustified (Smith's boss is a liar). Gettier's cases
involve propositions that were true, believed, but which had weak
justification. In case 1, the premise that the testimony of Smith's boss
is "strong evidence" is rejected. The case itself depends on the boss
being either wrong or deceitful (Jones did not get the job) and
therefore unreliable. In case 2, Smith again has accepted a questionable
idea (Jones owns a Ford) with unspecified justification. Without
justification, both cases do not undermine the JTB account of knowledge.
Other epistemologists accept Gettier's conclusion. Their
responses to the Gettier problem, therefore, consist of trying to find
alternative analyses of knowledge.
The fourth condition (JTB + G) approaches
The
most common direction for this sort of response to take is what might
be called a "JTB + G" analysis: that is, an analysis based on finding
some fourth condition—a "no-Gettier-problem" condition—which,
when added to the conditions of justification, truth, and belief, will
yield a set of separately necessary and jointly sufficient conditions.
Goldman's causal theory
One such response is that of Alvin Goldman (1967), who suggested the addition of a causal condition: a subject's belief is justified, for Goldman, only if the truth of a belief has caused
the subject to have that belief (in the appropriate way); and for a
justified true belief to count as knowledge, the subject must also
be able to "correctly reconstruct" (mentally) that causal chain.
Goldman's analysis would rule out Gettier cases in that Smith's beliefs
are not caused by the truths of those beliefs; it is merely accidental
that Smith's beliefs in the Gettier cases happen to be true, or that
the prediction made by Smith: "The winner of the job will have 10
coins", on the basis of his putative belief, (see also bundling)
came true in this one case. This theory is challenged by the difficulty
of giving a principled explanation of how an appropriate causal
relationship differs from an inappropriate one (without the circular
response of saying that the appropriate sort of causal relationship is
the knowledge-producing one); or retreating to a position in which
justified true belief is weakly defined as the consensus of learned
opinion. The latter would be useful, but not as useful nor desirable as
the unchanging definitions of scientific concepts such as momentum.
Thus, adopting a causal response to the Gettier problem usually requires
one to adopt (as Goldman gladly does) some form of reliabilism about justification.
Lehrer–Paxson's defeasibility condition
Keith Lehrer and Thomas Paxson (1969) proposed another response, by adding a defeasibility condition to the JTB analysis. On their account, knowledge is undefeated justified true belief—which
is to say that a justified true belief counts as knowledge if and only
if it is also the case that there is no further truth that, had the
subject known it, would have defeated their present justification for
the belief. (Thus, for example, Smith's justification for believing
that the person who will get the job has ten coins in his pocket is his
justified belief that Jones will get the job, combined with his
justified belief that Jones has ten coins in his pocket. But if Smith
had known the truth that Jones will not get the job, that would have defeated the justification for his belief.)
Pragmatism
Pragmatism was developed as a philosophical doctrine by C.S. Peirce and William James
(1842–1910). In Peirce's view, the truth is nominally defined as a
sign's correspondence to its object and pragmatically defined as the
ideal final opinion to which sufficient investigation would lead sooner or later. James' epistemological model of truth was that which works in the way of belief, and a belief was true if in the long run it worked for all of us, and guided us expeditiously through our semihospitable world. Peirce argued that metaphysics could be cleaned up by a pragmatic approach.
Consider what effects that might conceivably have practical bearings you conceive the objects of your conception to have. Then, your conception of those effects is the whole of your conception of the object.
From a pragmatic viewpoint of the kind often ascribed to James,
defining on a particular occasion whether a particular belief can
rightly be said to be both true and justified is seen as no more than an
exercise in pedantry, but being able to discern whether that belief led to fruitful outcomes is a fruitful enterprise. Peirce emphasized fallibilism, considered the assertion of absolute certainty a barrier to inquiry, and in 1901 defined truth as follows: "Truth is that concordance of an
abstract statement with the ideal limit towards which endless
investigation would tend to bring scientific belief, which concordance
the abstract statement may possess by virtue of the confession of its
inaccuracy and one-sidedness, and this confession is an essential
ingredient of truth." In other words, any unqualified assertion is likely to be at least a
little wrong or, if right, still right for not entirely the right
reasons. Therefore, one is more veracious by being Socratic, including
recognition of one's own ignorance and knowing one may be proved wrong.
This is the case, even though in practical matters one sometimes must
act, if one is to act at all, with a decision and complete confidence.
Revisions of JTB approaches
The
difficulties involved in producing a viable fourth condition have led
to claims that attempting to repair the JTB account is a deficient
strategy. For example, one might argue that what the Gettier problem
shows is not the need for a fourth independent condition in addition to
the original three, but rather that the attempt to build up an account
of knowledge by conjoining a set of independent conditions was misguided
from the outset. Those who have adopted this approach generally argue
that epistemological terms like justification, evidence, certainty, etc. should be analyzed in terms of a primitive notion of knowledge, rather than vice versa. Knowledge is understood as factive,
that is, as embodying a sort of epistemological "tie" between a truth
and a belief. The JTB account is then criticized for trying to get and
encapsulate the factivity of knowledge "on the cheap", as it were, or
via a circular argument, by replacing an irreducible notion of factivity
with the conjunction of some of the properties that accompany it (in
particular, truth and justification). Of course, the introduction of
irreducible primitives into a philosophical theory is always
problematical (some would say a sign of desperation),
and such anti-reductionist accounts are unlikely to please those who
have other reasons to hold fast to the method behind JTB+G accounts.
Fred Dretske's conclusive reasons and Robert Nozick's truth-tracking
Fred Dretske developed an account of knowledge which he called "conclusive reasons", revived by Robert Nozick as what he called the subjunctive or truth-tracking account. Nozick's formulation posits that proposition p is an instance of knowledge when:
- p is true
- S believes that p
- if p were true, S would believe that p
- if p weren't true, S wouldn't believe that p
Nozick's definition is intended to preserve Goldman's intuition that
Gettier cases should be ruled out by disacknowledging "accidentally"
true justified beliefs, but without risking the potentially onerous
consequences of building a causal requirement into the analysis. This
tactic though, invites the riposte that Nozick's account merely hides
the problem and does not solve it, for it leaves open the question of why
Smith would not have had his belief if it had been false. The most
promising answer seems to be that it is because Smith's belief was caused
by the truth of what he believes; but that puts us back in the
causalist camp. The third condition has come to be known as
epistemological safety, while the fourth has come to be known as epistemological sensitivity.
Criticisms and counter examples (notably the Grandma case) prompted a revision, which resulted in the alteration of (3) and (4) to limit themselves to the same method (i.e. vision):
- p is true
- S believes that p
- if p were true, S (using method M) would believe that p
- if p weren't true, S (using method M) wouldn't believe that p
Saul Kripke has pointed out that this view remains problematic and uses a counterexample called the Fake Barn Country example,
which describes a certain locality containing a number of fake barns or
facades of barns. In the midst of these fake barns is one real barn,
which is painted red. All the fake barns are not painted red.
Jones is driving along the highway, looks up and happens to see the real barn, and so forms the belief:
Though Jones has gotten lucky, he could have just as easily been
deceived and not have known it. Therefore, it doesn't fulfill condition
4, for if Jones had seen a fake barn he wouldn't have had any idea it
was a fake barn. So, even on the revised account, Jones does not know
that he sees a barn.
However, Jones could look up and form the belief:
This meets all four conditions of Nozick’s account, and therefore
Jones knows that he sees a red barn. Thus, Nozick is committed to the
view that Jones knows that he sees a red barn, but does not know that he
sees a barn. This violates the principle of epistemic closure,
which states that one is always in a position to know the consequences
of what one knows. Thus, since Jones knows that he sees a red barn, and
it is a consequence of him seeing a red barn that he sees a barn, by
epistemic closure he should be in a position to know that he sees a barn
— but Nozick denies this. Adopting Nozick’s view therefore requires
rejecting epistemic closure, which is often seen as an unacceptable
cost.
Robert Fogelin's perspectival account
In the first chapter of his book Pyrronian Reflexions on Truth and Justification, Robert Fogelin
gives a diagnosis that leads to a dialogical solution to Gettier's
problem. The problem always arises when the given justification has
nothing to do with what really makes the proposition true. Now, he notes
that in such cases there is always a mismatch between the information
available to the person who makes the knowledge-claim of some
proposition p and the information available to the evaluator of this
knowledge-claim (even if the evaluator is the same person in a later
time). A Gettierian counterexample arises when the justification given
by the person who makes the knowledge-claim cannot be accepted by the
knowledge evaluator because it does not fit with his wider informational
setting. For instance, in the case of the fake barn the evaluator knows
that a superficial inspection from someone who does not know the
peculiar circumstances involved isn't a justification acceptable as
making the proposition p (that it is a real barn) true.
Richard Kirkham's skepticism
Richard Kirkham
has proposed that it is best to start with a definition of knowledge so
strong that giving a counterexample to it is logically impossible.
Whether it can be weakened without becoming subject to a counterexample
should then be checked. He concludes that there will always be a
counterexample to any definition of knowledge in which the believer's
evidence does not logically necessitate the belief. Since in most cases
the believer's evidence does not necessitate a belief, Kirkham embraces
skepticism about knowledge; but he notes that a belief can still be
rational even if it is not an item of knowledge.
Attempts to dissolve the problem
One
might respond to Gettier by finding a way to avoid his conclusion(s) in
the first place. However, it can hardly be argued that knowledge is
justified true belief if there are cases that are justified true belief
without being knowledge; thus, those who want to avoid Gettier's
conclusions have to find some way to defuse Gettier's counterexamples.
In order to do so, within the parameters of the particular
counter-example or exemplar, they must then either accept that
- Gettier's cases are not really cases of justified true belief, or
- Gettier's cases really are cases of knowledge after all,
or, demonstrate a case in which it is possible to circumvent
surrender to the exemplar by eliminating any necessity for it to be
considered that JTB apply in just those areas that Gettier has rendered
obscure, without thereby lessening the force of JTB to apply in those
cases where it actually is crucial. Then, though Gettier's cases stipulate
that Smith has a certain belief and that his belief is true, it seems
that in order to propose (1), one must argue that Gettier, (or, that is,
the writer responsible for the particular form of words on this present
occasion known as case (1), and who makes assertion's about Smith's
"putative" beliefs), goes wrong because he has the wrong notion of justification. Such an argument often depends on an externalist
account on which "justification" is understood in such a way that
whether or not a belief is "justified" depends not just on the internal
state of the believer, but also on how that internal state is related to
the outside world. Externalist accounts typically are constructed such
that Smith's putative beliefs in Case I and Case II are not really
justified (even though it seems to Smith that they are), because his
beliefs are not lined up with the world in the right way, or that it is
possible to show that it is invalid to assert that "Smith" has any
significant "particular" belief at all, in terms of JTB or otherwise.
Such accounts, of course, face the same burden as causalist responses to
Gettier: they have to explain what sort of relationship between the
world and the believer counts as a justificatory relationship.
Those who accept (2) are by far in the minority in analytic
philosophy; generally, those who are willing to accept it are those who
have independent reasons to say that more things count as knowledge than
the intuitions that led to the JTB account would acknowledge. Chief among these is epistemic minimalists, Crispin Sartwell, who hold that all true belief, including both Gettier's cases and lucky guesses, counts as knowledge.
For his part, Nolbert Briceño, a Venezuelan lawyer, wrote an article entitled "Refutation of the Gettier Problem", where he analyzes Edmund Gettier's reasoning as expressed in his
article and claims to demonstrate the errors committed by the latter,
thus defending the definition of knowledge given by Plato.
Experimental research
Some early work in the field of
experimental philosophy suggested that traditional intuitions about Gettier cases might vary cross-culturally. However, subsequent studies have consistently failed to replicate these
results, instead finding that participants from different cultures do
share the traditional intuition. More recent studies have been providing evidence for the opposite
hypothesis, that people from a variety of different cultures have
similar intuitions in these cases.