Euclidean geometry is a mathematical system attributed to Alexandrian Greek mathematician Euclid, which he described in his textbook on geometry: the Elements. Euclid's method consists in assuming a small set of intuitively appealing axioms, and deducing many other propositions (theorems) from these. Although many of Euclid's results had been stated by earlier mathematicians, Euclid was the first to show how these propositions could fit into a comprehensive deductive and logical system. The Elements begins with plane geometry, still taught in secondary school (High School) as the first axiomatic system and the first examples of formal proof. It goes on to the solid geometry of three dimensions. Much of the Elements states results of what are now called algebra and number theory, explained in geometrical language.
For more than two thousand years, the adjective "Euclidean" was
unnecessary because no other sort of geometry had been conceived.
Euclid's axioms seemed so intuitively obvious (with the possible
exception of the parallel postulate) that any theorem proved from them was deemed true in an absolute, often metaphysical, sense. Today, however, many other self-consistent non-Euclidean geometries are known, the first ones having been discovered in the early 19th century. An implication of Albert Einstein's theory of general relativity is that physical space itself is not Euclidean, and Euclidean space is a good approximation for it only over short distances (relative to the strength of the gravitational field).
Euclidean geometry is an example of synthetic geometry,
in that it proceeds logically from axioms describing basic properties
of geometric objects such as points and lines, to propositions about
those objects, all without the use of coordinates to specify those objects. This is in contrast to analytic geometry, which uses coordinates to translate geometric propositions into algebraic formulas.
The Elements
The Elements is mainly a systematization of earlier knowledge
of geometry. Its improvement over earlier treatments was rapidly
recognized, with the result that there was little interest in preserving
the earlier ones, and they are now nearly all lost.
There are 13 books in the Elements:
Books I–IV and VI discuss plane geometry. Many results about
plane figures are proved, for example "In any triangle two angles taken
together in any manner are less than two right angles." (Book 1
proposition 17 ) and the Pythagorean theorem
"In right angled triangles the square on the side subtending the right
angle is equal to the squares on the sides containing the right angle."
(Book I, proposition 47)
Books V and VII–X deal with number theory, with numbers treated geometrically as lengths of line segments or areas of regions. Notions such as prime numbers and rational and irrational numbers are introduced. It is proved that there are infinitely many prime numbers.
Books XI–XIII concern solid geometry. A typical result is the 1:3 ratio between the volume of a cone and a cylinder with the same height and base. The platonic solids are constructed.
Axioms
Euclidean geometry is an axiomatic system, in which all theorems ("true statements") are derived from a small number of simple axioms. Until the advent of non-Euclidean geometry,
these axioms were considered to be obviously true in the physical
world, so that all the theorems would be equally true. However, Euclid's
reasoning from assumptions to conclusions remains valid independent of
their physical reality.
Near the beginning of the first book of the Elements, Euclid gives five postulates (axioms) for plane geometry, stated in terms of constructions (as translated by Thomas Heath):
- Let the following be postulated:
- To draw a straight line from any point to any point.
- To produce [extend] a finite straight line continuously in a straight line.
- To describe a circle with any centre and distance [radius].
- That all right angles are equal to one another.
- [The parallel postulate]: That, if a straight line falling on two straight lines make the interior angles on the same side less than two right angles, the two straight lines, if produced indefinitely, meet on that side on which the angles are less than two right angles.
Although Euclid only explicitly asserts the existence of the
constructed objects, in his reasoning they are implicitly assumed to be
unique.
The Elements also include the following five "common notions":
- Things that are equal to the same thing are also equal to one another (the Transitive property of a Euclidean relation).
- If equals are added to equals, then the wholes are equal (Addition property of equality).
- If equals are subtracted from equals, then the differences are equal (Subtraction property of equality).
- Things that coincide with one another are equal to one another (Reflexive Property).
- The whole is greater than the part.
Modern scholars agree that Euclid's postulates do not provide the
complete logical foundation that Euclid required for his presentation. Modern treatments use more extensive and complete sets of axioms.
Parallel postulate
To the ancients, the parallel postulate seemed less obvious than the
others. They aspired to create a system of absolutely certain
propositions, and to them it seemed as if the parallel line postulate
required proof from simpler statements. It is now known that such a
proof is impossible, since one can construct consistent systems of
geometry (obeying the other axioms) in which the parallel postulate is
true, and others in which it is false.
Euclid himself seems to have considered it as being qualitatively
different from the others, as evidenced by the organization of the Elements: his first 28 propositions are those that can be proved without it.
Many alternative axioms can be formulated which are logically equivalent to the parallel postulate (in the context of the other axioms). For example, Playfair's axiom states:
- In a plane, through a point not on a given straight line, at most one line can be drawn that never meets the given line.
The "at most" clause is all that is needed since it can be proved
from the remaining axioms that at least one parallel line exists.
Methods of proof
Euclidean Geometry is constructive.
Postulates 1, 2, 3, and 5 assert the existence and uniqueness of
certain geometric figures, and these assertions are of a constructive
nature: that is, we are not only told that certain things exist, but are
also given methods for creating them with no more than a compass and an unmarked straightedge. In this sense, Euclidean geometry is more concrete than many modern axiomatic systems such as set theory,
which often assert the existence of objects without saying how to
construct them, or even assert the existence of objects that cannot be
constructed within the theory. Strictly speaking, the lines on paper are models
of the objects defined within the formal system, rather than instances
of those objects. For example, a Euclidean straight line has no width,
but any real drawn line will. Though nearly all modern mathematicians
consider nonconstructive methods
just as sound as constructive ones, Euclid's constructive proofs often
supplanted fallacious nonconstructive ones—e.g., some of the
Pythagoreans' proofs that involved irrational numbers, which usually
required a statement such as "Find the greatest common measure of ..."
Euclid often used proof by contradiction.
Euclidean geometry also allows the method of superposition, in which a
figure is transferred to another point in space. For example,
proposition I.4, side-angle-side congruence of triangles, is proved by
moving one of the two triangles so that one of its sides coincides with
the other triangle's equal side, and then proving that the other sides
coincide as well. Some modern treatments add a sixth postulate, the
rigidity of the triangle, which can be used as an alternative to
superposition.
System of measurement and arithmetic
Euclidean geometry has two fundamental types of measurements: angle and distance. The angle scale is absolute, and Euclid uses the right angle as his basic unit, so that, e.g., a 45-degree
angle would be referred to as half of a right angle. The distance scale
is relative; one arbitrarily picks a line segment with a certain
nonzero length as the unit, and other distances are expressed in
relation to it. Addition of distances is represented by a construction
in which one line segment is copied onto the end of another line segment
to extend its length, and similarly for subtraction.
Measurements of area and volume are derived from distances. For example, a rectangle
with a width of 3 and a length of 4 has an area that represents the
product, 12. Because this geometrical interpretation of multiplication
was limited to three dimensions, there was no direct way of interpreting
the product of four or more numbers, and Euclid avoided such products,
although they are implied, e.g., in the proof of book IX, proposition
20.
Euclid refers to a pair of lines, or a pair of planar or solid
figures, as "equal" (ἴσος) if their lengths, areas, or volumes are
equal, and similarly for angles. The stronger term "congruent"
refers to the idea that an entire figure is the same size and shape as
another figure. Alternatively, two figures are congruent if one can be
moved on top of the other so that it matches up with it exactly.
(Flipping it over is allowed.) Thus, for example, a 2x6 rectangle and a
3x4 rectangle are equal but not congruent, and the letter R is congruent
to its mirror image. Figures that would be congruent except for their
differing sizes are referred to as similar. Corresponding angles in a pair of similar shapes are congruent and corresponding sides are in proportion to each other.
Notation and terminology
Naming of points and figures
Points
are customarily named using capital letters of the alphabet. Other
figures, such as lines, triangles, or circles, are named by listing a
sufficient number of points to pick them out unambiguously from the
relevant figure, e.g., triangle ABC would typically be a triangle with
vertices at points A, B, and C.
Complementary and supplementary angles
Angles whose sum is a right angle are called complementary.
Complementary angles are formed when a ray shares the same vertex and
is pointed in a direction that is in between the two original rays that
form the right angle. The number of rays in between the two original
rays is infinite.
Angles whose sum is a straight angle are supplementary.
Supplementary angles are formed when a ray shares the same vertex and
is pointed in a direction that is in between the two original rays that
form the straight angle (180 degree angle). The number of rays in
between the two original rays is infinite.
Modern versions of Euclid's notation
Modern school textbooks often define separate figures called lines (infinite), rays (semi-infinite), and line segments
(of finite length). Euclid, rather than discussing a ray as an object
that extends to infinity in one direction, would normally use locutions
such as "if the line is extended to a sufficient length," although he
occasionally referred to "infinite lines". A "line" in Euclid could be
either straight or curved, and he used the more specific term "straight
line" when necessary.
Some important or well known results
- The Pons Asinorum or Bridge of Asses theorem states that in an isosceles triangle, α = β and γ = δ.
- The Pythagorean theorem states that the sum of the areas of the two squares on the legs (a and b) of a right triangle equals the area of the square on the hypotenuse (c).
- Thales' theorem states that if AC is a diameter, then the angle at B is a right angle.
Pons Asinorum
The Bridge of Asses (Pons Asinorum) states that in
isosceles triangles the angles at the base equal one another, and, if
the equal straight lines are produced further, then the angles under the
base equal one another. Its name may be attributed to its frequent role as the first real test in the Elements
of the intelligence of the reader and as a bridge to the harder
propositions that followed. It might also be so named because of the
geometrical figure's resemblance to a steep bridge that only a
sure-footed donkey could cross.
Congruence of triangles
Triangles are congruent if they have all three sides equal (SSS), two
sides and the angle between them equal (SAS), or two angles and a side
equal (ASA) (Book I, propositions 4, 8, and 26). Triangles with three
equal angles (AAA) are similar, but not necessarily congruent. Also,
triangles with two equal sides and an adjacent angle are not necessarily
equal or congruent.
Triangle angle sum
The sum of the angles of a triangle is equal to a straight angle (180 degrees).
This causes an equilateral triangle to have three interior angles of 60
degrees. Also, it causes every triangle to have at least two acute
angles and up to one obtuse or right angle.
Pythagorean theorem
The celebrated Pythagorean theorem
(book I, proposition 47) states that in any right triangle, the area of
the square whose side is the hypotenuse (the side opposite the right
angle) is equal to the sum of the areas of the squares whose sides are
the two legs (the two sides that meet at a right angle).
Thales' theorem
Thales' theorem, named after Thales of Miletus
states that if A, B, and C are points on a circle where the line AC is a
diameter of the circle, then the angle ABC is a right angle. Cantor
supposed that Thales proved his theorem by means of Euclid Book I, Prop.
32 after the manner of Euclid Book III, Prop. 31.
Scaling of area and volume
In modern terminology, the area of a plane figure is proportional to the square of any of its linear dimensions, , and the volume of a solid to the cube, . Euclid proved these results in various special cases such as the area of a circle and the volume of a parallelepipedal solid. Euclid determined some, but not all, of the relevant constants of proportionality. E.g., it was his successor Archimedes who proved that a sphere has 2/3 the volume of the circumscribing cylinder.
Applications
Because of Euclidean geometry's fundamental status in mathematics, it
is impractical to give more than a representative sampling of
applications here.
- A surveyor uses a level
- Sphere packing applies to a stack of oranges.
As suggested by the etymology of the word, one of the earliest reasons for interest in geometry was surveying,
and certain practical results from Euclidean geometry, such as the
right-angle property of the 3-4-5 triangle, were used long before they
were proved formally.
The fundamental types of measurements in Euclidean geometry are
distances and angles, both of which can be measured directly by a
surveyor. Historically, distances were often measured by chains, such as
Gunter's chain, and angles using graduated circles and, later, the theodolite.
An application of Euclidean solid geometry is the determination of packing arrangements, such as the problem of finding the most efficient packing of spheres in n dimensions. This problem has applications in error detection and correction.
Geometric optics uses Euclidean geometry to analyze the focusing of light by lenses and mirrors.
Geometry is used extensively in architecture.
Geometry can be used to design origami. Some classical construction problems of geometry are impossible using compass and straightedge, but can be solved using origami.
Quite a lot of CAD (computer-aided design) and CAM (computer-aided manufacturing)
is based on Euclidean geometry. Design geometry typically consists of
shapes bounded by planes, cylinders, cones, tori, etc. CAD/CAM is
essential in the design of almost everything, nowadays, including cars,
airplanes, ships, and the iPhone. A few decades ago, sophisticated
draftsmen learned some fairly advanced Euclidean geometry, including
things like Pascal's theorem and Brianchon's theorem. But now they don't
have to, because the geometric constructions are all done by CAD
programs.
As a description of the structure of space
Euclid believed that his axioms
were self-evident statements about physical reality. Euclid's proofs
depend upon assumptions perhaps not obvious in Euclid's fundamental
axioms,
in particular that certain movements of figures do not change their
geometrical properties such as the lengths of sides and interior angles,
the so-called Euclidean motions, which include translations, reflections and rotations of figures.
Taken as a physical description of space, postulate 2 (extending a
line) asserts that space does not have holes or boundaries (in other
words, space is homogeneous and unbounded); postulate 4 (equality of right angles) says that space is isotropic and figures may be moved to any location while maintaining congruence; and postulate 5 (the parallel postulate) that space is flat (has no intrinsic curvature).
As discussed in more detail below, Einstein's theory of relativity significantly modifies this view.
The ambiguous character of the axioms as originally formulated by
Euclid makes it possible for different commentators to disagree about
some of their other implications for the structure of space, such as
whether or not it is infinite (see below) and what its topology is. Modern, more rigorous reformulations of the system
typically aim for a cleaner separation of these issues. Interpreting
Euclid's axioms in the spirit of this more modern approach, axioms 1-4
are consistent with either infinite or finite space (as in elliptic geometry), and all five axioms are consistent with a variety of topologies (e.g., a plane, a cylinder, or a torus for two-dimensional Euclidean geometry).
Later work
Archimedes and Apollonius
Archimedes
(c. 287 BCE – c. 212 BCE), a colorful figure about whom many historical
anecdotes are recorded, is remembered along with Euclid as one of the
greatest of ancient mathematicians. Although the foundations of his work
were put in place by Euclid, his work, unlike Euclid's, is believed to
have been entirely original. He proved equations for the volumes and areas of various figures in two and three dimensions, and enunciated the Archimedean property of finite numbers.
Apollonius of Perga (c. 262 BCE – c. 190 BCE) is mainly known for his investigation of conic sections.
17th century: Descartes
René Descartes (1596–1650) developed analytic geometry, an alternative method for formalizing geometry which focused on turning geometry into algebra.
In this approach, a point on a plane is represented by its Cartesian (x, y) coordinates, a line is represented by its equation, and so on.
In Euclid's original approach, the Pythagorean theorem
follows from Euclid's axioms. In the Cartesian approach, the axioms are
the axioms of algebra, and the equation expressing the Pythagorean
theorem is then a definition of one of the terms in Euclid's axioms,
which are now considered theorems.
The equation
defining the distance between two points P = (px, py) and Q = (qx, qy) is then known as the Euclidean metric, and other metrics define non-Euclidean geometries.
In terms of analytic geometry, the restriction of classical
geometry to compass and straightedge constructions means a restriction
to first- and second-order equations, e.g., y = 2x + 1 (a line), or x2 + y2 = 7 (a circle).
Also in the 17th century, Girard Desargues, motivated by the theory of perspective,
introduced the concept of idealized points, lines, and planes at
infinity. The result can be considered as a type of generalized
geometry, projective geometry, but it can also be used to produce proofs in ordinary Euclidean geometry in which the number of special cases is reduced.
18th century
Geometers
of the 18th century struggled to define the boundaries of the Euclidean
system. Many tried in vain to prove the fifth postulate from the first
four. By 1763, at least 28 different proofs had been published, but all
were found incorrect.
Leading up to this period, geometers also tried to determine what
constructions could be accomplished in Euclidean geometry. For example,
the problem of trisecting an angle
with a compass and straightedge is one that naturally occurs within the
theory, since the axioms refer to constructive operations that can be
carried out with those tools. However, centuries of efforts failed to
find a solution to this problem, until Pierre Wantzel published a proof in 1837 that such a construction was impossible. Other constructions that were proved impossible include doubling the cube and squaring the circle.
In the case of doubling the cube, the impossibility of the construction
originates from the fact that the compass and straightedge method
involve equations whose order is an integral power of two, while doubling a cube requires the solution of a third-order equation.
Euler discussed a generalization of Euclidean geometry called affine geometry,
which retains the fifth postulate unmodified while weakening postulates
three and four in a way that eliminates the notions of angle (whence
right triangles become meaningless) and of equality of length of line
segments in general (whence circles become meaningless) while retaining
the notions of parallelism as an equivalence relation between lines, and
equality of length of parallel line segments (so line segments continue
to have a midpoint).
19th century and non-Euclidean geometry
In the early 19th century, Carnot and Möbius systematically developed the use of signed angles and line segments as a way of simplifying and unifying results.
The century's most significant development in geometry occurred when, around 1830, János Bolyai and Nikolai Ivanovich Lobachevsky separately published work on non-Euclidean geometry, in which the parallel postulate is not valid.
Since non-Euclidean geometry is provably relatively consistent with
Euclidean geometry, the parallel postulate cannot be proved from the
other postulates.
In the 19th century, it was also realized that Euclid's ten
axioms and common notions do not suffice to prove all of the theorems
stated in the Elements. For example, Euclid assumed implicitly
that any line contains at least two points, but this assumption cannot
be proved from the other axioms, and therefore must be an axiom itself.
The very first geometric proof in the Elements, shown in the
figure above, is that any line segment is part of a triangle; Euclid
constructs this in the usual way, by drawing circles around both
endpoints and taking their intersection as the third vertex.
His axioms, however, do not guarantee that the circles actually
intersect, because they do not assert the geometrical property of
continuity, which in Cartesian terms is equivalent to the completeness property of the real numbers. Starting with Moritz Pasch in 1882, many improved axiomatic systems for geometry have been proposed, the best known being those of Hilbert, George Birkhoff, and Tarski.
20th century and general relativity
Einstein's theory of general relativity shows that the true geometry of spacetime is not Euclidean geometry.
For example, if a triangle is constructed out of three rays of light,
then in general the interior angles do not add up to 180 degrees due to
gravity. A relatively weak gravitational field, such as the Earth's or
the sun's, is represented by a metric that is approximately, but not
exactly, Euclidean. Until the 20th century, there was no technology
capable of detecting the deviations from Euclidean geometry, but
Einstein predicted that such deviations would exist. They were later
verified by observations such as the slight bending of starlight by the
Sun during a solar eclipse in 1919, and such considerations are now an
integral part of the software that runs the GPS system.
It is possible to object to this interpretation of general relativity
on the grounds that light rays might be improper physical models of
Euclid's lines, or that relativity could be rephrased so as to avoid the
geometrical interpretations. However, one of the consequences of
Einstein's theory is that there is no possible physical test that can
distinguish between a beam of light as a model of a geometrical line and
any other physical model. Thus, the only logical possibilities are to
accept non-Euclidean geometry as physically real, or to reject the
entire notion of physical tests of the axioms of geometry, which can
then be imagined as a formal system without any intrinsic real-world
meaning.
Treatment of infinity
Infinite objects
Euclid sometimes distinguished explicitly between "finite lines" (e.g., Postulate 2) and "infinite
lines" (book I, proposition 12). However, he typically did not make
such distinctions unless they were necessary. The postulates do not
explicitly refer to infinite lines, although for example some
commentators interpret postulate 3, existence of a circle with any
radius, as implying that space is infinite.
The notion of infinitesimal quantities had previously been discussed extensively by the Eleatic School, but nobody had been able to put them on a firm logical basis, with paradoxes such as Zeno's paradox occurring that had not been resolved to universal satisfaction. Euclid used the method of exhaustion rather than infinitesimals.
Later ancient commentators, such as Proclus
(410–485 CE), treated many questions about infinity as issues demanding
proof and, e.g., Proclus claimed to prove the infinite divisibility of a
line, based on a proof by contradiction in which he considered the
cases of even and odd numbers of points constituting it.
At the turn of the 20th century, Otto Stolz, Paul du Bois-Reymond, Giuseppe Veronese, and others produced controversial work on non-Archimedean models of Euclidean geometry, in which the distance between two points may be infinite or infinitesimal, in the Newton–Leibniz sense. Fifty years later, Abraham Robinson provided a rigorous logical foundation for Veronese's work.
Infinite processes
One
reason that the ancients treated the parallel postulate as less certain
than the others is that verifying it physically would require us to
inspect two lines to check that they never intersected, even at some
very distant point, and this inspection could potentially take an
infinite amount of time.
The modern formulation of proof by induction
was not developed until the 17th century, but some later commentators
consider it implicit in some of Euclid's proofs, e.g., the proof of the
infinitude of primes.
Supposed paradoxes involving infinite series, such as Zeno's paradox, predated Euclid. Euclid avoided such discussions, giving, for example, the expression for the partial sums of the geometric series in IX.35 without commenting on the possibility of letting the number of terms become infinite.
Logical basis
Classical logic
Euclid frequently used the method of proof by contradiction, and therefore the traditional presentation of Euclidean geometry assumes classical logic,
in which every proposition is either true or false, i.e., for any
proposition P, the proposition "P or not P" is automatically true.
Modern standards of rigor
Placing Euclidean geometry on a solid axiomatic basis was a preoccupation of mathematicians for centuries. The role of primitive notions, or undefined concepts, was clearly put forward by Alessandro Padoa of the Peano delegation at the 1900 Paris conference:
...when we begin to formulate the theory, we can imagine that the undefined symbols are completely devoid of meaning and that the unproved propositions are simply conditions imposed upon the undefined symbols.
Then, the system of ideas that we have initially chosen is simply one interpretation of the undefined symbols; but..this interpretation can be ignored by the reader, who is free to replace it in his mind by another interpretation.. that satisfies the conditions...
Logical questions thus become completely independent of empirical or psychological questions...
The system of undefined symbols can then be regarded as the abstraction obtained from the specialized theories that result when...the system of undefined symbols is successively replaced by each of the interpretations...
— Padoa, Essai d'une théorie algébrique des nombre entiers, avec une Introduction logique à une théorie déductive quelconque
That is, mathematics is context-independent knowledge within a hierarchical framework. As said by Bertrand Russell:
If our hypothesis is about anything, and not about some one or more particular things, then our deductions constitute mathematics. Thus, mathematics may be defined as the subject in which we never know what we are talking about, nor whether what we are saying is true.
— Bertrand Russell, Mathematics and the metaphysicians
Such foundational approaches range between foundationalism and formalism.
Axiomatic formulations
Geometry is the science of correct reasoning on incorrect figures.
— George Polyá, How to Solve It, p. 208
- Euclid's axioms: In his dissertation to Trinity College, Cambridge, Bertrand Russell summarized the changing role of Euclid's geometry in the minds of philosophers up to that time. It was a conflict between certain knowledge, independent of experiment, and empiricism, requiring experimental input. This issue became clear as it was discovered that the parallel postulate was not necessarily valid and its applicability was an empirical matter, deciding whether the applicable geometry was Euclidean or non-Euclidean.
- Hilbert's axioms: Hilbert's axioms had the goal of identifying a simple and complete set of independent axioms from which the most important geometric theorems could be deduced. The outstanding objectives were to make Euclidean geometry rigorous (avoiding hidden assumptions) and to make clear the ramifications of the parallel postulate.
- Birkhoff's axioms: Birkhoff proposed four postulates for Euclidean geometry that can be confirmed experimentally with scale and protractor. This system relies heavily on the properties of the real numbers. The notions of angle and distance become primitive concepts.
- Tarski's axioms: Alfred Tarski (1902–1983) and his students defined elementary Euclidean geometry as the geometry that can be expressed in first-order logic and does not depend on set theory for its logical basis, in contrast to Hilbert's axioms, which involve point sets. Tarski proved that his axiomatic formulation of elementary Euclidean geometry is consistent and complete in a certain sense: there is an algorithm that, for every proposition, can be shown either true or false. (This doesn't violate Gödel's theorem, because Euclidean geometry cannot describe a sufficient amount of arithmetic for the theorem to apply.) This is equivalent to the decidability of real closed fields, of which elementary Euclidean geometry is a model.
Constructive approaches and pedagogy
The process of abstract axiomatization as exemplified by Hilbert's axioms reduces geometry to theorem proving or predicate logic. In contrast, the Greeks used construction postulates, and emphasized problem solving.
For the Greeks, constructions are more primitive than existence
propositions, and can be used to prove existence propositions, but not vice versa. To describe problem solving adequately requires a richer system of logical concepts. The contrast in approach may be summarized:
- Axiomatic proof: Proofs are deductive derivations of propositions from primitive premises that are ‘true’ in some sense. The aim is to justify the proposition.
- Analytic proof: Proofs are non-deductive derivations of hypotheses from problems. The aim is to find hypotheses capable of giving a solution to the problem. One can argue that Euclid's axioms were arrived upon in this manner. In particular, it is thought that Euclid felt the parallel postulate was forced upon him, as indicated by his reluctance to make use of it, and his arrival upon it by the method of contradiction.
Andrei Nicholaevich Kolmogorov proposed a problem solving basis for geometry. This work was a precursor of a modern formulation in terms of constructive type theory. This development has implications for pedagogy as well.
If proof simply follows conviction of truth rather than contributing to its construction and is only experienced as a demonstration of something already known to be true, it is likely to remain meaningless and purposeless in the eyes of students.— Celia Hoyles, The curricular shaping of students' approach to proof