Participatory economics, often abbreviated ParEcon, is an economic system based on participatory decision making as the primary economic mechanism
for allocation in society. In the system, the say in decision-making is
proportional to the impact on a person or group of people.
Participatory economics is a form of socialist decentralized planned economy involving the common ownership of the means of production. It is a proposed alternative to contemporary capitalism and centralized planning. This economic model is primarily associated with political theorist Michael Albert and economist Robin Hahnel, who describe participatory economics as an anarchist economic vision.
The underlying values that parecon seeks to implement are equity, solidarity, diversity, workers' self-management, efficiency (defined as accomplishing goals without wasting valued assets) and sustainability. The institutions of parecon include workers' and consumers' councils utilizing self-managerial methods for decision-making, balanced job complexes, remuneration based on individual effort, and wide participatory planning.
The underlying values that parecon seeks to implement are equity, solidarity, diversity, workers' self-management, efficiency (defined as accomplishing goals without wasting valued assets) and sustainability. The institutions of parecon include workers' and consumers' councils utilizing self-managerial methods for decision-making, balanced job complexes, remuneration based on individual effort, and wide participatory planning.
Decision-making principle
A
primary proposition of parecon is that everyone should have a say in
decisions proportionate to the degree to which they are affected by
them. This principle is often referred to as self-management. In parecon, it constitutes a replacement for the mainstream economic conception of economic freedom, which Albert and Hahnel argue by its very vagueness has allowed it to be abused by capitalist ideologues.
Production and work
Balanced job complexes
A main goal of socialism is to create a society without classes or
hierarchy, and traditional socialist thinking identifies classes based
on ownership of the means of production (in capitalism, those are the
capitalist class and the proletarian class). However, Albert and Hahnel
identify a third class created by the particular division of labor.
Some tasks and jobs are more desirable than others; also some are more
empowering. Hahnel and Albert argue that empowering jobs, such as
accounting or management, provide access to information and skills to
formulate ideas and plans for decision making, while other jobs, such as
cleaning, do not provide these. Thus workers with disempowering jobs
can at best ratify proposals by empowered workers, and have little
reason to participate in collective decision making. Workers with
empowering jobs are a third class, "coordinator class" that does not own
the means of production but has more power than menial workers. This
class exists in current and past capitalist, socialist and cooperative
economies. Coordinator jobs include political office, management, law,
medicine, accounting, and research.
To distribute work equitably and empower all workers in decisions
in their workplace, in participatory economics each worker does tasks,
which, taken together, result in an average desirability and average
empowerment among all workers.
Compensation for effort and sacrifice
Albert
and Hahnel argue that it is inequitable and ineffective to compensate
people on the basis of luck (e.g. skills or talents that owe to their
birth or heredity), or by virtue of workers' productivity (as measured
by the value of the goods they produce). Therefore, the primary
principle of participatory economics is to reward workers for their
effort and sacrifice. For example, mining work—which is dangerous and uncomfortable—would be more highly paid than office
work for the same amount of time, thus allowing the miner to work fewer
hours for the same pay, and the burden of highly dangerous and
strenuous jobs to be shared among the populace.
Additionally, participatory economics would provide exemptions from the compensation for effort principle. People with disabilities who are unable to work, children, the elderly,
the infirm and workers who are legitimately in transitional
circumstances, can be remunerated according to need. However, every able
adult has the obligation to perform some socially useful work as a
requirement for receiving reward. However, everyone would be entitled to
free health care, education,
skills training, and the freedom to choose between various
democratically structured workplaces with balanced jobs balanced for
desirability and empowerment.
The starting point for the income of all workers in a
participatory economy is an equal share of the social product. From this
point, incomes for personal expenditures
and consumption rights for public goods can be expected to diverge by
small degrees, reflecting the choices that individuals make in between
work and leisure time, and the level of danger and difficulty of a job as judged by their immediate workplace peers.
Workplace democracy
The archetypal workplace democracy model, the Wobbly Shop was pioneered by the Industrial Workers of the World, in which the self-managing norms of grassroots democracy were applied.
Scale
While many
types of production and consumption may become more localised under
participatory economics, the model does not exclude economies of scale.
Innovation
Hahnel
has also written a detailed discussion of parecon's desirability
compared to capitalism with respect to incentives to innovate. In capitalism, patent laws, intellectual property rights and barriers to market entry
are institutional features that reward individual innovators while
limiting the use of new technologies. Hahnel notes that, in contrast,
"in a participatory economy all innovations will immediately be made
available to all enterprises, so there will never be any loss of static
efficiency.".
Innovation is sometimes the outcome of cumulative creativity, which
pareconomists believe may not be legitimately attributed to individuals.
Allocation
Participatory planning is the allocation mechanism in a participatory
economy, and is meant to provide a workable alternative to market
competition and centralized planning. The planning procedure is
conceived as an iterative process in which, (1) production proposals
made by workers councils and (2) consumption proposals made by
individuals and their neighborhood councils,
are submitted and revised through multiple rounds of pricing updates
until the process converges on a feasible plan for the upcoming year.
The process begins when the facilitation board
(see below) announces a list of indicative prices for each final
consumer good, as well as for each capital good, natural resource, and
category of labor that is available to society. These indicative prices
are calculated to reflect the estimated opportunity costs for producing
various goods and services, and incorporate both social costs and
pollution impacts. In response to this list of prices, individuals draft
an annual consumption plan for goods/services they wish to consume in
the coming year, and also meet in their neighborhood councils to
deliberate and democratically arrive at a plan for the consumption of
public goods (e.g. obtaining resources to build a public playground). As
workers, individuals also meet in their workplaces to determine what
outputs they will produce and what inputs they will consume in the
production process, as well as how much they would each like to work.
Thus, workers and consumers (as well as any federations of workers or
consumers) submit their initial requests to the facilitation board,
which aggregates this information.
Because the conclusion of the first round of this process will
almost certainly not be a workable plan, the facilitation board proceeds
to update the list of indicative prices for each good up or down, in
proportion to the excess demand and supply for each, so that the updated
prices reflect a more accurate estimate of the social opportunity costs
of each item. The announcement of updated indicative prices then
initiates the second round of the planning process, in which consumers
and workers revise and resubmit their proposals in light of the new
information. In particular, consumption proposals in which the
individual's proposed effort rating does not warrant the proposed level
of consumption will need to be adjusted, so that the individual will
either have to reduce his/her consumption requests, shift them to less
costly products, or increase his/her projected work-hours for the coming
year. Other consumers may discover that their initial proposals were
too modest, and can revise their consumption upwards, if they choose, or
they can revise their projected effort rating downwards by proposing to
work fewer hours and increasing leisure time.
Production proposals are also summarized and evaluated on a
quantitative basis, in this case by the ratio of social benefits to
social costs. (The social benefit part of the ratio is calculated by
multiplying the proposed quantity of outputs from a workplace by their
indicative prices, adding negative prices for any proposed pollution
emissions and summing. The social costs are calculated by multiplying
the quantity of requested inputs by their indicative prices and
summing.) Proposals with a benefits-to-cost ratio below one will need to
make adjustments in order to gain approval in the next round, either by
switching to a less polluting technology, producing a more socially
desirable set of outputs, or using less costly inputs.
After receiving the revised proposals, the facilitation board
once again updates the list of indicative prices. After several rounds
of this revision and re-submission process, the result is convergence to
a feasible plan in which workers and consumers are able to accomplish
the activities that they detailed in their final submissions. Even after
a feasible plan is achieved, flexible mid-year revisions of
consumer/worker proposals can also be incorporated into the planning
process.
In academic work, Albert and Hahnel (1991) prove that participatory planning arrives at a Pareto optimum,
and does so under less restrictive assumptions than markets; that is,
participatory planning is Pareto optimal even though it incorporates
both public goods and externalities, whereas markets do not achieve
Pareto optimality with these two assumptions).
A feature of participatory planning which differs from other
modes of democratic planning is that all deliberation on proposals
occurs within councils, but does not take place between councils. That
is, under parecon, a feasible economic plan is constructed due to an
iterative adjustment of prices (participatory planning) based on
councils' self-activity proposals, rather than owing to a procedure of
deliberation among delegates across workplaces/industries. This is
potentially desirable by cutting down on the meeting time and
bureaucratic burdens needed to converge on an annual plan.
Facilitation boards
In a proposed participatory economy, key information relevant to converging on an economic plan would be made available by Iteration Facilitation Boards
(IFBs), which, based on proposals from worker/consumer councils and
economic data, present indicative prices and economic projections at
each round of the planning process.
The IFB has no decision-making authority. In theory, the IFB's
activity can consist mainly of computers performing the (agreed upon)
algorithms for adjusting prices and forecasts, with little human
involvement.
Opposition to central planning and capitalism
Robin Hahnel
has argued that "participatory planning is not central planning",
stating "The procedures are completely different and the incentives are
completely different. And one of the important ways in which it is
different from central planning is that it is incentive compatible, that
is, actors have an incentive to report truthfully rather than an
incentive to misrepresent their capabilities or preferences."
Unlike historical examples of central planning, the parecon proposal
advocates the use and adjustment of price information reflecting
marginal social opportunity costs and benefits as integral elements of
the planning process. Hahnel has argued emphatically against Milton
Friedman's a priori tendency to deny the possibility of alternatives:
Friedman assumes away the best solution for coordinating economic activities. He simply asserts "there are only two ways of coordinating the economic activities of millions—central direction involving the use of coercion—and voluntary cooperation, the technique of the marketplace." [...] a participatory economy can permit all to partake in economic decision making in proportion to the degree they are affected by outcomes. Since a participatory system uses a system of participatory planning instead of markets to coordinate economic activities, Friedman would have us believe that participatory planning must fall into the category of "central direction involving the use of coercion."
Albert and Hahnel have voiced detailed critiques of centrally-planned
economies in theory and practice, but are also highly-critical of
capitalism. Hahnel claims "the truth is capitalism aggravates prejudice,
is the most inequitable economy ever devised, is grossly
inefficient—even if highly energetic—and is incompatible with both
economic and political democracy. In the present era of free-market
triumphalism it is useful to organize a sober evaluation of capitalism
responding to Friedman's claims one by one."
Critique of markets
Mainstream economists largely acknowledge the problem of externalities but believe they can be addressed either through Coasian bargaining or the use of Pigovian taxes—extra taxes on goods that have externalities.
According to economic theory, if Pigovian taxes are set so that the
after-tax cost of the goods is equal to the social cost of the goods,
the direct cost of production plus cost of externalities, then
quantities produced will tend toward a socially optimal level. Hahnel
observes, "more and more economists outside the mainstream are
challenging this assumption, and a growing number of skeptics now dare
to suggest that externalities are prevalent, and often substantial". Or,
as E.K. Hunt put it: externalities are the rule rather than the
exception, and therefore markets often work as if they were guided by a
"malevolent invisible foot" that keeps kicking us to produce more of
some things, and less of others than is socially efficient."
As long as a market economy is in place, Albert and Hahnel favour
Pigovian taxes over other solutions to environmental problems such as command and control,
or the issuance of marketable permits. However, Hahnel, who teaches
ecological economics at American University, argues that in a market
economy businesses try to avoid the "polluter pays principle" by
shifting the burden of the costs for their polluting activities to
consumers. In terms of incentives he argues this might be considered a
positive development because it would penalize consumers for "dirty"
consumption. However it also has regressive implications since tax incidence
studies show that ultimately it would be poor people who would bear a
great deal of the burden of many pollution taxes. "In other words, many
pollution taxes would be highly regressive and therefore aggravate
economic injustice." He therefore recommends that pollution taxes be linked to cuts in regressive taxes such as social security taxes.
Hahnel argues that Pigovian taxes, along with associated
corrective measures advanced by market economists, ultimately fall far
short of adequately or fairly addressing externalities. He argues such
methods are incapable of attaining accurate assessments of social costs:
Markets corrected by pollution taxes only lead to the efficient amount of pollution and satisfy the polluter pays principle if the taxes are set equal to the magnitude of the damage victims suffer. But because markets are not incentive compatible for polluters and pollution victims, markets provide no reliable way to estimate the magnitudes of efficient taxes for pollutants. Ambiguity over who has the property right, polluters or pollution victims, free rider problems among multiple victims, and the transaction costs of forming and maintaining an effective coalition of pollution victims, each of whom is affected to a small but unequal degree, all combine to render market systems incapable of eliciting accurate information from pollution victims about the damages they suffer, or acting upon that information even if it were known.
Class and hierarchy
Advocates of parecon say the intention is that the four main ingredients of parecon be implemented with a minimum of hierarchy
and a maximum of transparency in all discussions and decision-making.
This model is designed to eliminate secrecy in economic decision-making,
and instead encourage friendly cooperation and mutual support. This
avoidance of power hierarchies puts parecon in the libertarian socialist political tradition. Stephen Shalom has produced a political system meant to complement parecon, called parpolity.
Although parecon falls under left-wing
political tradition, it is designed to avoid the creation of powerful
intellectual elites or the rule of a bureaucracy, which is perceived as
the major problem of the economies of the communist states of the 20th century. In their book Looking Forward Albert and Hanhel termed this situation 'coordinatorism'.
Parecon advocates recognize that monopolization of empowering labor, in
addition to private ownership, can be a source of class division. Thus,
a three-class view of the economy (capitalists, coordinators, and
workers) is stressed, in contrast to the traditional two-class view of
Marxism. The coordinator class, emphasized in parecon, refers to those
who have a monopoly on empowering skills and knowledge, and corresponds
to the doctors, lawyers, managers, engineers, and other professionals in
present economies. Parecon advocates argue that, historically, Marxism
ignored the ability of coordinators to become a new ruling class in a
post-capitalist society.
Limitations
Participatory
economics is not in itself intended to provide a general political
system. Its practical implementation would depend on an accompanying
political system.
According to Albert and Hahnel, parecon addresses only an
alternative economic theory and must be accompanied by equally important
alternatives in the fields of politics, culture and kinship. The authors have also discussed elements of anarchism in the field of politics, polyculturalism in the field of culture, and feminism
in the field of family and gender relations as being possible
foundations for future alternative visions in these other spheres of
society. Stephen R. Shalom has begun work on a participatory political vision he calls "par polity". Both systems together make up the political philosophy of Participism.
Criticism
David Schweickart suggests participatory economics would be undesirable even if it was possible:
It is a system obsessed with comparison (Is your job complex more empowering than mine?), with monitoring (You are not working at average intensity, mate—get with the program), with the details of consumption (How many rolls of toilet paper will I need next year? Why are some of my neighbors still using the kind not made of recycled paper?)
Other criticism raised by Schweickart include:
- Difficulty with creating balanced job complexes and ensuring they do not suffer from inefficiency.
- A system based on peer evaluation may not work as workers could slack off and there would be little incentive for colleagues to damage their relationships by giving them bad reviews. Alternatively it may cause workers to become suspicious of one another, undermining solidarity.
- A compensation system based on effort would be difficult to measure and would need to be based on an average rating system of effort.
- Parecon's compensation system would be overly egalitarian and likely cause resentment among workers who work harder while also discouraging them from putting in extra effort since they will gain no greater compensation.
- Parecon would likely produce an onerous and tiresome requirement to list off all things people want produced, which would likely suffer from uncertainty given people do not always know what they desire, as well as issues with how much information they should be required to supply and complexities with the negotiations required between worker and consumer councils.
Planning
Participatory economics would create a large amount of administrative
work for individual workers, who would have to plan their consumption
in advance, and a new bureaucratic class. Proponents of parecon argue
that capitalist economies are hardly free of bureaucracy or meetings,
and a parecon would eliminate banks, advertising, stock market, tax
returns and long-term financial planning. Albert and Hahnel claim that
it is probable that a similar number of workers will be involved in a
parecon bureaucracy as in a capitalist bureaucracy,
with much of the voting achieved by computer rather than meeting, and
those who are not interested in the collective consumption proposals not
required to attend.
Critics suggest that proposals require consideration of an unfeasibly large set of policy choices,
and that lessons from planned societies show that peoples' daily needs
cannot be established well in advance simply by asking people what they
want. Albert and Hahnel note that markets themselves hardly adjust prices instantaneously, and suggest that in a participatory economy facilitation boards
could modify prices on a regular basis. According to Hahnel these act
according to democratically decided guidelines, can be composed of
members from other regions and are impossible to bribe due to parecon's
non-transferable currency. However, Takis Fotopoulos
argues that "no kind of economic organisation based on planning alone,
however democratic and decentralised it is, can secure real
self-management and freedom of choice."
Loss of efficiency
Parecon
might reduce efficiency in the workplace. For one, expert and
exceptional workers (e.g. exceptional surgeons and scientists) would not
be performing their tasks full-time. Participatory economics would
expect them to share in "disempowering work" and would not offer
opportunities to seek additional compensation for their high ability or
finding solutions to problems. In a lecture at Willamette University in
Oregon in 2015, Hahnel responded to this criticism by explaining that
these jobs could be filled by machines, which are underutilized in
capitalist economic systems due to the lowered rates of profit, and also
division of labor wouldn't exist under a participatory economic system
as much as it does under capitalism, so people would not always have the
same jobs.
Theodore Burczak
argues that it is impossible for workers to give the unbiased
assessments of the "largely unobservable" characteristics of effort
proposed as the basis for salary levels, and the absence of market
exchange mechanisms likewise makes calculating social costs of
production and consumption impossible.
Influence
In
2012, the International Organization for a Participatory Society was
founded advocating for a participatory society including participatory
economics, also referred to as participism.