In quantum mechanics, quantum logic is a set of rules for reasoning about propositions that takes the principles of quantum theory into account. This research area and its name originated in a 1936 paper by Garrett Birkhoff and John von Neumann, who were attempting to reconcile the apparent inconsistency of classical logic with the facts concerning the measurement of complementary variables in quantum mechanics, such as position and momentum.
Quantum logic can be formulated either as a modified version of propositional logic or as a noncommutative and non-associative many-valued (MV) logic.
Quantum logic has been proposed as the correct logic for propositional inference generally, most notably by the philosopher Hilary Putnam, at least at one point in his career. This thesis was an important ingredient in Putnam's 1968 paper "Is Logic Empirical?" in which he analysed the epistemological status of the rules of propositional logic. Putnam attributes the idea that anomalies associated to quantum measurements originate with anomalies in the logic of physics itself to the physicist David Finkelstein. However, this idea had been around for some time and had been revived several years earlier by George Mackey's work on group representations and symmetry.
The more common view regarding quantum logic, however, is that it provides a formalism for relating observables, system preparation filters and states. In this view, the quantum logic approach resembles more closely the C*-algebraic approach to quantum mechanics. The similarities of the quantum logic formalism to a system of deductive logic may then be regarded more as a curiosity than as a fact of fundamental philosophical importance. A more modern approach to the structure of quantum logic is to assume that it is a diagram—in the sense of category theory—of classical logics (see David Edwards).
Quantum logic can be formulated either as a modified version of propositional logic or as a noncommutative and non-associative many-valued (MV) logic.
Quantum logic has been proposed as the correct logic for propositional inference generally, most notably by the philosopher Hilary Putnam, at least at one point in his career. This thesis was an important ingredient in Putnam's 1968 paper "Is Logic Empirical?" in which he analysed the epistemological status of the rules of propositional logic. Putnam attributes the idea that anomalies associated to quantum measurements originate with anomalies in the logic of physics itself to the physicist David Finkelstein. However, this idea had been around for some time and had been revived several years earlier by George Mackey's work on group representations and symmetry.
The more common view regarding quantum logic, however, is that it provides a formalism for relating observables, system preparation filters and states. In this view, the quantum logic approach resembles more closely the C*-algebraic approach to quantum mechanics. The similarities of the quantum logic formalism to a system of deductive logic may then be regarded more as a curiosity than as a fact of fundamental philosophical importance. A more modern approach to the structure of quantum logic is to assume that it is a diagram—in the sense of category theory—of classical logics (see David Edwards).
Differences with classical logic
Quantum logic has some properties that clearly distinguish it from classical logic, most notably, the failure of the distributive law of propositional logic:
- p and (q or r) = (p and q) or (p and r),
where the symbols p, q and r are propositional
variables. To illustrate why the distributive law fails, consider a
particle moving on a line and (using some system of units where the reduced Planck's constant is 1) let
- p = "the particle has momentum in the interval [0, +1/6]"
- q = "the particle is in the interval [−1, 1]"
- r = "the particle is in the interval [1, 3]"
Note: The choice of p, q, and r in this example is intuitive but not formally valid (that is, p and (q or r) is also false here); see section "Quantum logic as the logic of observables" below for details and a valid example.
We might observe that:
- p and (q or r) = true
in other words, that the particle's momentum is between 0 and +1/6, and its position is between −1 and +3.
On the other hand, the propositions "p and q" and "p and r" are both false, since they assert tighter restrictions on simultaneous values of position and momentum than is allowed by the uncertainty principle (they each have uncertainty 1/3, which is less than the allowed minimum of 1/2). So,
- (p and q) or (p and r) = false
Thus the distributive law fails.
Introduction
In his classic 1932 treatise Mathematical Foundations of Quantum Mechanics, John von Neumann noted that projections on a Hilbert space
can be viewed as propositions about physical observables. The set of
principles for manipulating these quantum propositions was called quantum logic by von Neumann and Birkhoff in their 1936 paper. George Mackey, in his 1963 book (also called Mathematical Foundations of Quantum Mechanics), attempted to provide a set of axioms for this propositional system as an orthocomplemented lattice. Mackey viewed elements of this set as potential yes or no questions
an observer might ask about the state of a physical system, questions
that would be settled by some measurement. Moreover, Mackey defined a
physical observable in terms of these basic questions. Mackey's axiom
system is somewhat unsatisfactory though, since it assumes that the
partially ordered set is actually given as the orthocomplemented closed subspace lattice of a separable Hilbert space. Constantin Piron,
Günther Ludwig and others have attempted to give axiomatizations that
do not require such explicit relations to the lattice of subspaces.
The axioms of an orthocomplemented lattice are most commonly stated as algebraic equations concerning the poset and its operations. A set of axioms using instead disjunction (denoted as ) and negation (denoted as ) is as follows:
- is commutative and associative.
- There is a maximal element , and for any .
- .
An orthomodular lattice satisfies the above axioms, and additionally the following one:
- The orthomodular law: If then .
Alternative formulations include sequent calculi, and tableaux systems.
The remainder of this article assumes the reader is familiar with the spectral theory of self-adjoint operators on a Hilbert space. However, the main ideas can be understood using the finite-dimensional spectral theorem.
Quantum logic as the logic of observables
One
semantics of quantum logic is that quantum logic is the logic of
boolean observables in quantum mechanics, where an observable p is associated with the set of quantum states for which p (when measured) is true with probability 1 (this completely characterizes the observable). From there,
- ¬p is the orthogonal complement of p (since for those states, the probability of observing p, P(p) = 0),
- p∧q is the intersection of p and q, and
- p∨q = ¬(¬p∧¬q) refers to states that are a superposition of p and q.
Thus, expressions in quantum logic describe observables using a
syntax that resembles classical logic. However, unlike classical logic,
the distributive law a ∧ (b ∨ c) = (a ∧ b) ∨ (a ∧ c)
fails when dealing with noncommuting observables, such as position and
momentum. This occurs because measurement affects the system, and
measurement of whether a disjunction holds does not measure which of the
disjuncts is true.
For an example, consider a simple one-dimensional particle with position denoted by x and momentum by p, and define observables:
- a — |p| ≤ 1 (in some units)
- b — x < 0
- c — x ≥ 0
Now, position and momentum are Fourier transforms of each other, and the Fourier transform of a square-integrable nonzero function with a compact support is entire and hence does not have non-isolated zeroes. Therefore, there is no wave function that vanishes at x ≥ 0 with P(|p|≤1) = 1. Thus, a ∧ b and similarly a ∧ c are false, so (a ∧ b) ∨ (a ∧ c) is false. However, a ∧ (b ∨ c) equals a and might be true.
To understand more, let p1 and p2 be the momenta for the restriction of the particle wave function to x < 0 and x ≥ 0 respectively (with the wave function zero outside of the restriction). Let be the restriction of |p| to momenta that are (in absolute value) >1.
(a ∧ b) ∨ (a ∧ c) corresponds to states with and (this holds even if we defined p differently so as to make such states possible; also, a ∧ b corresponds to and ). As an operator, , and nonzero and might interfere to produce zero . Such interference is key to the richness of quantum logic and quantum mechanics.
The propositional lattice of a classical system
The so-called Hamiltonian formulations of classical mechanics have three ingredients: states, observables and dynamics. In the simplest case of a single particle moving in R3, the state space is the position-momentum space R6. We will merely note here that an observable is some real-valued function f
on the state space. Examples of observables are position, momentum or
energy of a particle. For classical systems, the value f(x), that is the value of f for some particular system state x, is obtained by a process of measurement of f. The propositions concerning a classical system are generated from basic statements of the form
- "Measurement of f yields a value in the interval [a, b] for some real numbers a, b."
It follows easily from this characterization of propositions in
classical systems that the corresponding logic is identical to that of
some Boolean algebra
of subsets of the state space. By logic in this context we mean the
rules that relate set operations and ordering relations, such as de Morgan's laws.
These are analogous to the rules relating boolean conjunctives and
material implication in classical propositional logic. For technical
reasons, we will also assume that the algebra of subsets of the state
space is that of all Borel sets.
The set of propositions is ordered by the natural ordering of sets and
has a complementation operation. In terms of observables, the complement
of the proposition {f ≥ a} is {f < a}.
We summarize these remarks as follows: The proposition system of a classical system is a lattice with a distinguished orthocomplementation operation: The lattice operations of meet and join
are respectively set intersection and set union. The
orthocomplementation operation is set complement. Moreover, this
lattice is sequentially complete, in the sense that any sequence {Ei}i of elements of the lattice has a least upper bound, specifically the set-theoretic union:
The propositional lattice of a quantum mechanical system
In the Hilbert space
formulation of quantum mechanics as presented by von Neumann, a
physical observable is represented by some (possibly unbounded) densely
defined self-adjoint operator A on a Hilbert space H. A has a spectral decomposition, which is a projection-valued measure E defined on the Borel subsets of R. In particular, for any bounded Borel function f on R, the following extension of f to operators can be made:
In case f is the indicator function of an interval [a, b], the operator f(A) is a self-adjoint projection, and can be interpreted as the quantum analogue of the classical proposition
- Measurement of A yields a value in the interval [a, b].
This suggests the following quantum mechanical replacement for the
orthocomplemented lattice of propositions in classical mechanics. This
is essentially Mackey's Axiom VII:
- The orthocomplemented lattice Q of propositions of a quantum mechanical system is the lattice of closed subspaces of a complex Hilbert space H where orthocomplementation of V is the orthogonal complement V⊥.
Q is also sequentially complete: any pairwise disjoint sequence{Vi}i of elements of Q has a least upper bound. Here disjointness of W1 and W2 means W2 is a subspace of W1⊥. The least upper bound of {Vi}i is the closed internal direct sum.
Henceforth we identify elements of Q with self-adjoint projections on the Hilbert space H.
The structure of Q immediately points to a difference with
the partial order structure of a classical proposition system. In the
classical case, given a proposition p, the equations
have exactly one solution, namely the set-theoretic complement of p. In these equations I refers to the atomic proposition that is identically true and 0
the atomic proposition that is identically false. In the case of the
lattice of projections there are infinitely many solutions to the above
equations (any closed, algebraic complement of p solves it; it need not be the orthocomplement).
Having made these preliminary remarks, we turn everything around
and attempt to define observables within the projection lattice
framework and using this definition establish the correspondence between
self-adjoint operators and observables: A Mackey observable is a countably additive homomorphism from the orthocomplemented lattice of the Borel subsets of R to Q. To say the mapping φ is a countably additive homomorphism means that for any sequence {Si}i of pairwise disjoint Borel subsets of R, {φ(Si)}i are pairwise orthogonal projections and
Effectively, then, a Mackey observable is a projection-valued measure on R.
Theorem. There is a bijective correspondence between Mackey observables and densely defined self-adjoint operators on H.
This is the content of the spectral theorem as stated in terms of spectral measures.
Statistical structure
Imagine a forensics lab that has some apparatus to measure the speed
of a bullet fired from a gun. Under carefully controlled conditions of
temperature, humidity, pressure and so on the same gun is fired
repeatedly and speed measurements taken. This produces some distribution
of speeds. Though we will not get exactly the same value for each
individual measurement, for each cluster of measurements, we would
expect the experiment to lead to the same distribution of speeds. In
particular, we can expect to assign probability distributions to propositions such as {a ≤ speed ≤ b}.
This leads naturally to propose that under controlled conditions of
preparation, the measurement of a classical system can be described by a
probability measure on the state space. This same statistical
structure is also present in quantum mechanics.
A quantum probability measure is a function P defined on Q with values in [0,1] such that P(0)=0, P(I)=1 and if {Ei}i is a sequence of pairwise orthogonal elements of Q then
The following highly non-trivial theorem is due to Andrew Gleason:
Theorem. Suppose Q is a separable Hilbert space of complex dimension at least 3. Then for any quantum probability measure P on Q there exists a unique trace class operator S such that
for any self-adjoint projection E in Q.
The operator S is necessarily non-negative (that is all eigenvalues are non-negative) and of trace 1. Such an operator is often called a density operator.
Physicists commonly regard a density operator as being represented by a (possibly infinite) density matrix relative to some orthonormal basis.
For more information on statistics of quantum systems, see quantum statistical mechanics.
Automorphisms
An automorphism of Q is a bijective mapping α:Q → Q that preserves the orthocomplemented structure of Q, that is
for any sequence {Ei}i of
pairwise orthogonal self-adjoint projections. Note that this property
implies monotonicity of α. If P is a quantum probability measure on Q, then E → α(E) is also a quantum probability measure on Q. By the Gleason theorem
characterizing quantum probability measures quoted above, any
automorphism α induces a mapping α* on the density operators by the
following formula:
The mapping α* is bijective and preserves convex combinations of density operators. This means
whenever 1 = r1 + r2 and r1, r2 are non-negative real numbers. Now we use a theorem of Richard V. Kadison:
Theorem. Suppose β is a bijective map from density
operators to density operators that is convexity preserving. Then there
is an operator U on the Hilbert space that is either linear or conjugate-linear, preserves the inner product and is such that
for every density operator S. In the first case we say U is unitary, in the second case U is anti-unitary.
Remark. This note is included for technical accuracy only, and should not concern most readers. The result quoted above is not directly stated in Kadison's paper, but can be reduced to it by noting first that β extends to a positive trace preserving map on the trace class operators, then applying duality and finally applying a result of Kadison's paper.
The operator U is not quite unique; if r is a complex scalar of modulus 1, then r U will be unitary or anti-unitary if U is and will implement the same automorphism. In fact, this is the only ambiguity possible.
It follows that automorphisms of Q are in bijective
correspondence to unitary or anti-unitary operators modulo
multiplication by scalars of modulus 1. Moreover, we can regard
automorphisms in two equivalent ways: as operating on states
(represented as density operators) or as operating on Q.
Non-relativistic dynamics
In
non-relativistic physical systems, there is no ambiguity in referring
to time evolution since there is a global time parameter. Moreover, an
isolated quantum system evolves in a deterministic way: if the system is in a state S at time t then at time s > t, the system is in a state Fs,t(S). Moreover, we assume
- The dependence is reversible: The operators Fs,t are bijective.
- The dependence is homogeneous: Fs,t = Fs − t,0.
- The dependence is convexity preserving: That is, each Fs,t(S) is convexity preserving.
- The dependence is weakly continuous: The mapping R→ R given by t → Tr(Fs,t(S) E) is continuous for every E in Q.
By Kadison's theorem, there is a 1-parameter family of unitary or anti-unitary operators {Ut}t such that
In fact.
Theorem. Under the above assumptions, there is a strongly continuous 1-parameter group of unitary operators {Ut}t such that the above equation holds.
Note that it follows easily from uniqueness from Kadison's theorem that
where σ(t,s) has modulus 1. Now the square of an anti-unitary is a unitary, so that all the Ut are unitary. The remainder of the argument shows that σ(t,s) can be chosen to be 1 (by modifying each Ut by a scalar of modulus 1.)
Pure states
A convex combination of statistical states S1 and S2 is a state of the form S = p1 S1 +p2 S2 where p1, p2 are non-negative and p1 + p2
=1. Considering the statistical state of system as specified by lab
conditions used for its preparation, the convex combination S can be regarded as the state formed in the following way: toss a biased coin with outcome probabilities p1, p2 and depending on outcome choose system prepared to S1 or S2.
Density operators form a convex set. The convex set of density operators has extreme points;
these are the density operators given by a projection onto a
one-dimensional space. To see that any extreme point is such a
projection, note that by the spectral theorem S can be represented by a diagonal matrix; since S is non-negative all the entries are non-negative and since S
has trace 1, the diagonal entries must add up to 1. Now if it happens
that the diagonal matrix has more than one non-zero entry it is clear
that we can express it as a convex combination of other density
operators.
The extreme points of the set of density operators are called pure states. If S is the projection on the 1-dimensional space generated by a vector ψ of norm 1 then
for any E in Q. In physics jargon, if
where ψ has norm 1, then
Thus pure states can be identified with rays in the Hilbert space H.
The measurement process
Consider a quantum mechanical system with lattice Q that is in some statistical state given by a density operator S.
This essentially means an ensemble of systems specified by a repeatable
lab preparation process. The result of a cluster of measurements
intended to determine the truth value of proposition E, is just as in the classical case, a probability distribution of truth values T and F. Say the probabilities are p for T and q = 1 − p for F. By the previous section p = Tr(S E) and q = Tr(S (I − E)).
Perhaps the most fundamental difference between classical and
quantum systems is the following: regardless of what process is used to
determine E immediately after the measurement the system will be in one of two statistical states:
- If the result of the measurement is T
- If the result of the measurement is F
(We leave to the reader the handling of the degenerate cases in which
the denominators may be 0.) We now form the convex combination of
these two ensembles using the relative frequencies p and q. We thus obtain the result that the measurement process applied to a statistical ensemble in state S yields another ensemble in statistical state:
We see that a pure ensemble becomes a mixed ensemble after measurement. Measurement, as described above, is a special case of quantum operations.
Limitations
Quantum
logic derived from propositional logic provides a satisfactory
foundation for a theory of reversible quantum processes. Examples of
such processes are the covariance transformations relating two frames of
reference, such as change of time parameter or the transformations of
special relativity. Quantum logic also provides a satisfactory
understanding of density matrices. Quantum logic can be stretched to
account for some kinds of measurement processes corresponding to
answering yes–no questions about the state of a quantum system. However,
for more general kinds of measurement operations (that is quantum
operations), a more complete theory of filtering processes is necessary.
Such a theory of quantum filtering was developed in the late 1970s and 1980s by Belavkin (see also Bouten et al.). A similar approach is provided by the consistent histories formalism. On the other hand, quantum logics derived from many-valued logic extend its range of applicability to irreversible quantum processes or 'open' quantum systems.
In any case, these quantum logic formalisms must be generalized
in order to deal with super-geometry (which is needed to handle
Fermi-fields) and non-commutative geometry (which is needed in string
theory and quantum gravity theory). Both of these theories use a partial
algebra with an "integral" or "trace". The elements of the partial
algebra are not observables; instead the "trace" yields "greens
functions", which generate scattering amplitudes. One thus obtains a
local S-matrix theory (see D. Edwards).
In 2004, Prakash Panangaden described how to capture the kinematics of quantum causal evolution using System BV, a deep inference logic originally developed for use in structural proof theory. Alessio Guglielmi, Lutz Straßburger, and Richard Blute have also done work in this area.