The Ultimate Boeing 747 gambit is a counter-argument to modern versions of the argument from design for the existence of God. It was introduced by Richard Dawkins in chapter 4 of his 2006 book The God Delusion, "Why there almost certainly is no God".
The argument is a play on the notion of a "tornado sweeping through a junkyard to assemble a Boeing 747" employed to decry abiogenesis and evolution as vastly unlikely and better explained by the existence of a creator god. According to Dawkins, this logic is self-defeating as the theist must now account for the god's existence and explain whether or how the god was created. In his view, if the existence of highly complex life on Earth is the equivalent of the implausible junkyard Boeing 747, the existence of a highly complex god is the "ultimate Boeing 747" that truly does require the seemingly impossible to explain its existence.
The argument is a play on the notion of a "tornado sweeping through a junkyard to assemble a Boeing 747" employed to decry abiogenesis and evolution as vastly unlikely and better explained by the existence of a creator god. According to Dawkins, this logic is self-defeating as the theist must now account for the god's existence and explain whether or how the god was created. In his view, if the existence of highly complex life on Earth is the equivalent of the implausible junkyard Boeing 747, the existence of a highly complex god is the "ultimate Boeing 747" that truly does require the seemingly impossible to explain its existence.
Context and history
Richard Dawkins begins The God Delusion by making it clear that the God he talks about is the Abrahamic concept of a personal god
who is susceptible to worship. He considers the existence of such an
entity to be a scientific question, because a universe with such a god
would be significantly different from a universe without one, and he
says that the difference would be empirically
discernible. Therefore, Dawkins concludes, the same kind of reasoning
can be applied to the God hypothesis as to any other scientific
question.
After discussing some of the most common arguments for the existence of God in chapter 3, Dawkins concludes that the argument from design
is the most convincing. The extreme improbability of life and a
universe capable of hosting it requires explanation, but Dawkins
considers the God hypothesis inferior to evolution by natural selection as an explanation for the complexity of life. As part of his efforts to refute intelligent design, he redirects the argument from complexity
in order to show that God must have been designed by a superintelligent
designer, then presents his argument for the improbability of God's
existence.
Dawkins's name for the statistical demonstration that God almost
certainly does not exist is the "Ultimate Boeing 747 gambit". This is an
allusion to the junkyard tornado. Astrophysicist Fred Hoyle, who was a Darwinist, atheist, anti-theist and advocate of the panspermia theory of life,
is reported as having stated that the "probability of life originating
on Earth is no greater than the chance that a hurricane, sweeping
through a scrapyard, would have the luck to assemble a Boeing 747." Arguments against empirically based theism date back at least as far as the eighteenth-century philosopher David Hume, whose objection can be paraphrased as the question "Who designed the designer?". According to philosopher Daniel Dennett, however – one of Dawkins's fellow "brights" –
the innovation in Dawkins's argument is twofold: to show that where
design fails to explain complexity, evolution by natural selection
succeeds as the only workable solution; and to argue how this should
illuminate the confusion surrounding the anthropic principle.
Dawkins's statement
Dawkins summarizes his argument as follows; the references to "crane" and "skyhook" are to notions from Daniel Dennett's book Darwin's Dangerous Idea.
One of the greatest challenges to the human intellect, over the centuries, has been to explain how the complex, improbable appearance of design in the universe arises.The natural temptation is to attribute the appearance of design to actual design itself. In the case of a man-made artefact such as a watch, the designer really was an intelligent engineer. It is tempting to apply the same logic to an eye or a wing, a spider or a person. The temptation is a false one, because the designer hypothesis immediately raises the larger problem of who designed the designer. The whole problem we started out with was the problem of explaining statistical improbability. It is obviously no solution to postulate something even more improbable. We need a "crane", not a "skyhook"; for only a crane can do the business of working up gradually and plausibly from simplicity to otherwise improbable complexity. The most ingenious and powerful crane so far discovered is Darwinian evolution by natural selection. Darwin and his successors have shown how living creatures, with their spectacular statistical improbability and appearance of design, have evolved by slow, gradual degrees from simple beginnings. We can now safely say that the illusion of design in living creatures is just that – an illusion. We don't yet have an equivalent crane for physics. Some kind of multiverse theory could in principle do for physics the same explanatory work as Darwinism does for biology. This kind of explanation is superficially less satisfying than the biological version of Darwinism, because it makes heavier demands on luck. But the anthropic principle entitles us to postulate far more luck than our limited human intuition is comfortable with. We should not give up hope of a better crane arising in physics, something as powerful as Darwinism is for biology. But even in the absence of a strongly satisfying crane to match the biological one, the relatively weak cranes we have at present are, when abetted by the anthropic principle, self-evidently better than the self-defeating skyhook hypothesis of an intelligent designer.
A central thesis of the argument is that compared to supernatural
abiogenesis, evolution by natural selection requires the supposition of
fewer hypothetical processes; according to Occam's razor, therefore, it is a better explanation. Dawkins cites a paragraph where Richard Swinburne
agrees that a simpler explanation is better but reasons that theism is
simpler because it only invokes a single substance (God) as a cause and
maintainer of every other object. This cause is seen as omnipotent, omniscient
and totally "free". Dawkins argues that an entity that monitors and
controls every particle in the universe and listens to all thoughts and
prayers cannot be simple. Its existence would require a "mammoth
explanation" of its own. The theory of natural selection is much simpler
– and thus preferable – than a theory of the existence of such a
complex being.
Dawkins then turns to a discussion of Keith Ward's views on divine simplicity
to show the difficulty "the theological mind has in grasping where the
complexity of life comes from." Dawkins writes that Ward is sceptical of
Arthur Peacocke's
ideas that evolution is directed by other forces than only natural
selection and that these processes may have a propensity toward
increasing complexity. Dawkins says that this scepticism is justified,
because complexity does not come from biased mutations. Dawkins writes:
[Natural selection], as far as we know, is the only process ultimately capable of generating complexity out of simplicity. The theory of natural selection is genuinely simple. So is the origin from which it starts. That which it explains, on the other hand, is complex almost beyond telling: more complex than anything we can imagine, save a God capable of designing it.
Assessment and criticism
Theist authors have presented extensive opposition, most notably by theologian Alister McGrath (in The Dawkins Delusion?) and philosophers Alvin Plantinga and Richard Swinburne. Another negative review, by biologist H. Allen Orr, sparked heated debate, prompting, for example, the mathematician Norman Levitt to ask why theologians are assumed to have the exclusive right to write about who "rules" the universe. Daniel Dennett also took exception to Orr's review, leading to an exchange of open letters between himself and Orr. The philosopher Sir Anthony Kenny also considers this argument to be flawed. Cosmologist Stephen Barr responded as follows: "Paley finds a watch and asks how
such a thing could have come to be there by chance. Dawkins finds an
immense automated factory that blindly constructs watches, and feels
that he has completely answered Paley's point."
Simplicity of God and materialist assumptions
Both
Alvin Plantinga and Richard Swinburne raise the objection that God is
not complex. Swinburne gives two reasons why a God that controls every
particle can be simple: first, a person, as indicated by phenomena such
as split-brains,
is not the same as their highly complex brain but "is something
simpler" that can "control" that brain; and second, simplicity is a quality that is intrinsic to a hypothesis, not related to its empirical consequences.
Plantinga writes:
So first, according to classical theology, God is simple, not complex. More remarkable, perhaps, is that according to Dawkins's own definition of complexity, God is not complex. According to his definition (set out in The Blind Watchmaker), something is complex if it has parts that are "arranged in a way that is unlikely to have arisen by chance alone." But of course God is a spirit, not a material object at all, and hence has no parts. A fortiori (as philosophers like to say) God doesn't have parts arranged in ways unlikely to have arisen by chance. Therefore, given the definition of complexity Dawkins himself proposes, God is not complex."
He continues:
"But second, suppose we concede, at least for purposes of argument, that God is complex. Perhaps we think the more a being knows, the more complex it is; God, being omniscient, would then be highly complex. Given materialism and the idea that the ultimate objects in our universe are the elementary particles of physics, perhaps a being that knew a great deal would be improbable – how could those particles get arranged in such a way as to constitute a being with all that knowledge? Of course we aren't given materialism.
In other words, Plantinga concludes that this argument, to be valid,
would require materialism to be true; but, as materialism is not
compatible with traditional theology, the argument begs the question by requiring its premise to assume God's non-existence.
In an extensive analysis published in Science and Christian Belief,
Patrick Richmond suggests that "Dawkins is right to object to
unexplained organised complexity in God" but that God is simply
specified and lacks the sort of composition and limitations found in
[physical] creatures; hence the theist can explain why nature exists
without granting unexplained organised complexity or the extreme
improbability of God.
Some respondents, such as Stephen Law, have suggested that God is or would indeed be complex if responsible for creating and sustaining the universe; God's omniscience would require the retention of and ability to use all knowledge. Concepts such as Kolmogorov complexity have also been used to argue that God is or would need to be complex.
Necessity of external explanations
There are many variations on how to express this objection. William F. Vallicella
holds that organized complexity as such does not need explanation,
because when in search of an ultimate explanation, one must in the end
accept an entity whose complexity has no external explanation.
Dawkins has stated that we should search for simple beginnings for
explanations, like in evolution which moves from simple to complex, and
so what we ultimately accept with no external explanation must be simple
for it to be a good explanation. And Plantinga writes that when not
in search for an ultimate explanation of organized complexity, it is
perfectly fine to explain one kind of complexity, that of terrestrial
life, in terms of another kind of complexity, namely divine activity. Dawkins addresses this point in his debate with John Lennox over The God Delusion,
saying that it would be perfectly reasonable to infer from artifacts on
earth or another planet that an intelligence existed, but that you
would still need to explain that intelligence, which evolution does,
while for God's existence there is no such explanation.
Alister McGrath suggests that the leap from the recognition of
complexity to the assertion of improbability is problematic, as a theory of everything
would be more complex than the theories it would replace, yet one would
not conclude that it is less probable. Dawkins has responded to this
point in his debate with Lennox and at other times, saying that while
physics is hard to understand, fundamentally, unlike biology, it is
simple.
McGrath then argues that probability is not relevant to the question of
existence: life on earth is highly improbable and yet we exist. The
important question in his view is not whether God is probable, but whether God is actual. In interviewing McGrath for The Root of All Evil,
Dawkins responds that the existence of life on Earth is indeed highly
improbable, but this is exactly why a theory such as evolution is
required to explain that improbability. In the case of God, Dawkins says, there is no such satisfactory explanation.
On the point of probability, Alvin Plantinga claims that if God is a necessary being,
as argued by classical theism, God is, by definition, maximally
probable; thus an argument that there is no necessary being with the
qualities attributed to God is required to demonstrate God's
improbability.
Eric MacDonald has pointed out that theists assume the coherence of
their position when they make arguments for God when, by Plantinga's
standards, they would have to present an argument that the concept of
God is not logically incoherent before discussing other arguments.
Plantinga's objection would seem to apply to all atheist arguments that
contend that God is improbable, such as evidential arguments about the problem of evil and the argument from nonbelief.
But the reason why theists and atheists do not usually address this
prior to making their arguments is because they want to go beyond merely
discussing whether God is maximally probable or impossible.
Dawkins's response to criticism in The God Delusion
Dawkins writes about his attendance at a conference in Cambridge sponsored by the Templeton Foundation,
where he challenged the theologians present to respond to the argument
that a creator of a complex universe would have to be complex and
improbable. He reports the strongest response as the claim he was imposing a scientific epistemology
on a question that lies beyond the realm of science. When theologians
hold God to be simple, who is a scientist like Dawkins "to dictate to
theologians that their God had to be complex?"
Dawkins writes that he did not feel that those employing this "evasive"
defence were being "wilfully dishonest", but that they were "defining
themselves into an epistemological safe-zone where rational argument
could not reach them because they had declared by fiat that it could not."
Theologians, Dawkins writes, demand that there be a first cause
named "God". Dawkins responds that it must have been a simple cause and
contends that unless "God" is divested of its normal associations, it
is not an appropriate name. Postulating a prime mover that is capable of
indulging in intelligent design is, in Dawkins's opinion, "a total
abdication of the responsibility to find an explanation"; instead, he
seeks a "self-bootstrapping crane" that can "lift" the universe into more complex states. This, he states, does not necessitate a narrowly scientific explanation, but does require a "crane" rather than a "skyhook" (ibid.) if it is to account for the complexity of the natural world.