The watchmaker analogy or watchmaker argument is a teleological argument which states, by way of an analogy, that a design implies a designer. The analogy has played a prominent role in natural theology and the "argument from design," where it was used to support arguments for the existence of God and for the intelligent design of the universe, in both Christianity and Deism.
Sir Isaac Newton, among other leaders in the scientific revolution, including René Descartes, upheld "that the physical laws he had uncovered revealed the mechanical perfection of the workings of the universe to be akin to a watch, wherein the watchmaker is God."
The 1859 publication of Charles Darwin's theory of natural selection put forward an explanation for complexity and adaptation, which reflects scientific consensus on the origins of biological diversity. In the eyes of some, this provided a counter-argument to the watchmaker analogy: for example, the evolutionary biologist Richard Dawkins referred to the analogy in his 1986 book The Blind Watchmaker giving his explanation of evolution. Others, however, consider the watchmaker analogy to be compatible with evolutionary creation, opining that the two concepts are not mutually exclusive. In the 19th century, deists, who championed the watchmaker analogy, held that Darwin's theory fit with "the principle of uniformitarianism—the idea that all processes in the world occur now as they have in the past" and that deistic evolution "provided an explanatory framework for understanding species variation in a mechanical universe."
In the United States, starting in the 1960s, creationists revived versions of the argument to dispute the concepts of evolution and natural selection, and there was renewed interest in the watchmaker argument. The most famous statement of this teleological argument using the watchmaker analogy was given by William Paley in his 1802 book Natural Theology or Evidences of the Existence and Attributes of the Deity.
Sir Isaac Newton, among other leaders in the scientific revolution, including René Descartes, upheld "that the physical laws he had uncovered revealed the mechanical perfection of the workings of the universe to be akin to a watch, wherein the watchmaker is God."
The 1859 publication of Charles Darwin's theory of natural selection put forward an explanation for complexity and adaptation, which reflects scientific consensus on the origins of biological diversity. In the eyes of some, this provided a counter-argument to the watchmaker analogy: for example, the evolutionary biologist Richard Dawkins referred to the analogy in his 1986 book The Blind Watchmaker giving his explanation of evolution. Others, however, consider the watchmaker analogy to be compatible with evolutionary creation, opining that the two concepts are not mutually exclusive. In the 19th century, deists, who championed the watchmaker analogy, held that Darwin's theory fit with "the principle of uniformitarianism—the idea that all processes in the world occur now as they have in the past" and that deistic evolution "provided an explanatory framework for understanding species variation in a mechanical universe."
In the United States, starting in the 1960s, creationists revived versions of the argument to dispute the concepts of evolution and natural selection, and there was renewed interest in the watchmaker argument. The most famous statement of this teleological argument using the watchmaker analogy was given by William Paley in his 1802 book Natural Theology or Evidences of the Existence and Attributes of the Deity.
History
Scientific revolution
The scientific revolution
"nurtured a growing awareness" that "there were universal laws of
nature at work that ordered the movement of the world and its parts." James K. A. Smith and Amos Yong
write that in "astronomy, the Copernican revolution regarding the
heliocentrism of the solar system, Johannes Kepler's (1571–1630) three
laws of planetary motion, and Isaac Newton's (1642–1727) law of
universal gravitation—laws of gravitation and of motion, and notions of
absolute space and time—all combined to establish the regularities of
heavenly and earthly bodies." With such a backdrop, "deists suggested
the watchmaker analogy: just as watches are set in motion by
watchmakers, after which they operate according to their pre-established
mechanisms, so also was the world begun by the God as creator, after
which it and all its parts have operated according to their
pre-established natural laws. With these laws perfectly in place, events
have unfolded according to the prescribed plan." For Sir Isaac Newton, "the regular motion of the planets made it reasonable to believe in the continued existence of God."
Newton also upheld the idea that "like a watchmaker, God was forced to
intervene in the universe and tinker with the mechanism from time to
time to ensure that it continued operating in good working order." Like
Newton, René Descartes
viewed "the cosmos as a great time machine operating according to fixed
laws, a watch created and wound up by the great watchmaker."
William Paley
Watches and timepieces have been used as examples of complicated technology in philosophical discussions. For example, Cicero, Voltaire and René Descartes all used timepieces in arguments regarding purpose. The watchmaker analogy, as described here, was used by Bernard le Bovier de Fontenelle in 1686, but was most famously formulated by Paley.
Paley used the watchmaker analogy in his book Natural Theology, or Evidences of the Existence and Attributes of the Deity collected from the Appearances of Nature, published in 1802. In it, Paley wrote that if a pocket watch
is found on a heath, it is most reasonable to assume that someone
dropped it and that it was made by at least one watchmaker, not by
natural forces:
In crossing a heath, suppose I pitched my foot against a stone, and were asked how the stone came to be there; I might possibly answer, that, for anything I knew to the contrary, it had lain there forever: nor would it perhaps be very easy to show the absurdity of this answer. But suppose I had found a watch upon the ground, and it should be inquired how the watch happened to be in that place; I should hardly think of the answer I had before given, that for anything I knew, the watch might have always been there. ... There must have existed, at some time, and at some place or other, an artificer or artificers, who formed [the watch] for the purpose which we find it actually to answer; who comprehended its construction, and designed its use. ... Every indication of contrivance, every manifestation of design, which existed in the watch, exists in the works of nature; with the difference, on the side of nature, of being greater or more, and that in a degree which exceeds all computation.
— William Paley, Natural Theology (1802)
Paley went on to argue that the complex structures of living things
and the remarkable adaptations of plants and animals required an
intelligent designer. He believed the natural world was the creation of
God and showed the nature of the creator. According to Paley, God had
carefully designed "even the most humble and insignificant organisms"
and all of their minute features (such as the wings and antennae of earwigs). He believed, therefore, that God must care even more for humanity.
Paley recognised that there is great suffering in nature and
nature appears to be indifferent to pain. His way of reconciling that
with his belief in a benevolent God was to assume that life had more pleasure than pain.
As a side note, a charge of wholesale plagiarism from this book was brought against Paley in The Athenaeum
for 1848, but the famous illustration of the watch was not peculiar to
Nieuwentyt and had been used by many others before either Paley or
Nieuwentyt.
Joseph Butler
William Paley taught the works of Joseph Butler
and appears to have built on Butler's 1736 design arguments of
inferring a designer from evidence of design. Butler noted:
"As the manifold Appearances of Design and of final Causes, in the
Constitution of the World, prove it to be the Work of an intelligent
Mind ... The appearances of Design and of final Causes in the constitution of nature as really prove this acting agent to be an intelligent Designer... ten thousand Instances of Design, cannot but prove a Designer.".
Jean-Jacques Rousseau
Rousseau also mentioned the watchmaker theory. He wrote the following in his 1762 book, Emile:
I am like a man who sees the works of a watch for the first time; he is never weary of admiring the mechanism, though he does not know the use of the instrument and has never seen its face. I do not know what this is for, says he, but I see that each part of it is fitted to the rest, I admire the workman in the details of his work, and I am quite certain that all these wheels only work together in this fashion for some common end which I cannot perceive. Let us compare the special ends, the means, the ordered relations of every kind, then let us listen to the inner voice of feeling; what healthy mind can reject its evidence? Unless the eyes are blinded by prejudices, can they fail to see that the visible order of the universe proclaims a supreme intelligence? What sophisms must be brought together before we fail to understand the harmony of existence and the wonderful co-operation of every part for the maintenance of the rest?
Criticism
David Hume
Before Paley published his book, David Hume
(1711-1776) had already put forward a number of philosophical
criticisms of the watch analogy, and to some extent anticipated the
concept of natural selection. His criticisms can be separated into three major distinctions.
His first objection is that we have no experience of
world-making. Hume highlighted the fact that everything we claim to know
the cause of, we have derived the inductions from previous experiences
of similar objects being created or seen the object itself being created
ourselves. For example, with a watch, we know it has to be created by a
watch-maker because we can observe it being made and compare it to the
making of other similar watches or objects to deduce they have alike
causes in their creation. However, he argues that we have no experience
of the universe's creation or any other universe's creations to compare
our own universe to and never will; therefore, it would be illogical to
infer that our universe has been created by an intelligent designer in
the same way that a watch has.
The second criticism that Hume offers is about the form of the
argument as an analogy in itself. An analogical argument claims that
because object X (a watch) is like object Y (the universe) in one
respect, both are therefore probably alike in another, hidden, respect
(their cause, having to be created by an intelligent designer). He
points out that for an argument from analogy to be successful, the two
things that are being compared have to have an adequate number of
similarities that are relevant to the respect that are analogised. For
example, a kitten and a lion may be very similar in many respects, but
just because a lion makes a "roar", it would not be correct to infer a
kitten also "roars": the similarities between the two objects being not
enough and the degree of relevance to what sound they make being not
relevant enough. Hume then argues that the universe and a watch also do
not have enough relevant or close similarities to infer that they were
both created the same way. For example, the universe is made of organic
natural material, but the watch is made of artificial mechanic
materials. He claims that in the same respect, the universe could be
argued to be more analogous to something more organic such as a
vegetable (which we can observe for ourselves does not need a 'designer'
or a 'watchmaker' to be created). Although he admits the analogy of a
universe to a vegetable to seem ridiculous, he says that it is just as
ridiculous to analogize the universe with a watch.
The third criticism that Hume offers is that even if the argument
did give evidence for a designer; it still gives no evidence for the
traditional 'omnipotent', 'benevolent' (all-powerful and all-loving) God
of traditional Christian theism. One of the main assumptions of Paley's
argument is that 'like effects have like causes'; or that machines
(like the watch) and the universe have similar features of design and so
both also have the same cause of their existence: they must both have
an intelligent designer. However, Hume points out that what Paley does
not comprehend is to what extent 'like causes' extend: how similar the
creation of a universe is to the creation of a watch. Instead, Paley
moves straight to the conclusion that this designer of the universe is
the 'God' he believes in of traditional Christianity. Hume, however
takes the idea of 'like causes' and points out some potential
absurdities in how far the 'likeness' of these causes could extend to if
the argument were taken further as to explain this. One example that he
uses is how a machine or a watch is usually designed by a whole team of
people rather than just one person. Surely, if we are analogizing the
two in this way, it would point to there being a group of gods who
created the universe, not just a single being. Another example he uses
is that complex machines are usually the result of many years of trial
and error with every new machine being an improved version of the last.
Also by analogy of the two, would that not hint that the universe could
also have been just one of many of God's 'trials' and that there are
much better universes out there? However, if that were taken to be true,
surely the 'creator' of it all would not be 'all loving' and 'all
powerful' if they had to carry out the process of 'trial and error' when
creating the universe?
Hume also points out there is still a possibility that the
universe could have been created by random chance but still show
evidence of design as the universe is eternal and would have an infinite
amount of time to be able to form a universe so complex and ordered as
our own. He called that the 'Epicurean hypothesis'. It argued that when
the universe was first created, the universe was random and chaotic, but
if the universe is eternal, over an unlimited period of time, natural
forces could have naturally 'evolved' by random particles coming
together over time into the incredibly ordered system we can observe
today without the need of an intelligent designer as an explanation.
The last objection that he makes draws on the widely discussed problem of evil.
He argues that all the daily unnecessary suffering that goes on
everywhere within the world is yet another factor that pulls away from
the idea that God is an 'omnipotent' 'benevolent' being.
Charles Darwin
Charles Darwin's theory provided another explanation.
When Darwin completed his studies of theology at Christ's College, Cambridge in 1831, he read Paley's Natural Theology and believed that the work gave rational proof of the existence of God. That was because living beings showed complexity and were exquisitely fitted to their places in a happy world.
Subsequently, on the voyage of the Beagle, Darwin found that nature was not so beneficent, and the distribution of species did not support ideas of divine creation. In 1838, shortly after his return, Darwin conceived his theory that natural selection,
rather than divine design, was the best explanation for gradual change
in populations over many generations. He published the theory in On the Origin of Species in 1859, and in later editions, he noted responses that he had received:
It can hardly be supposed that a false theory would explain, in so satisfactory a manner as does the theory of natural selection, the several large classes of facts above specified. It has recently been objected that this is an unsafe method of arguing; but it is a method used in judging of the common events of life, and has often been used by the greatest natural philosophers ... I see no good reason why the views given in this volume should shock the religious feelings of any one. It is satisfactory, as showing how transient such impressions are, to remember that the greatest discovery ever made by man, namely, the law of the attraction of gravity, was also attacked by Leibnitz, "as subversive of natural, and inferentially of revealed, religion." A celebrated author and divine has written to me that "he has gradually learnt to see that it is just as noble a conception of the Deity to believe that He created a few original forms capable of self-development into other and needful forms, as to believe that He required a fresh act of creation to supply the voids caused by the action of His laws."
— Charles Darwin, The Origin of Species (1859)
Darwin reviewed the implications of this finding in his autobiography:
Although I did not think much about the existence of a personal God until a considerably later period of my life, I will here give the vague conclusions to which I have been driven. The old argument of design in nature, as given by Paley, which formerly seemed to me so conclusive, fails, now that the law of natural selection has been discovered. We can no longer argue that, for instance, the beautiful hinge of a bivalve shell must have been made by an intelligent being, like the hinge of a door by man. There seems to be no more design in the variability of organic beings and in the action of natural selection, than in the course which the wind blows. Everything in nature is the result of fixed laws.
— Charles Darwin, The Autobiography of Charles Darwin 1809–1882. With the original omissions restored.
The idea that nature was governed by laws was already common, and in 1833, William Whewell as a proponent of the natural theology
that Paley had inspired had written that "with regard to the material
world, we can at least go so far as this—we can perceive that events are
brought about not by insulated interpositions of Divine power, exerted
in each particular case, but by the establishment of general laws." Darwin, who spoke of the "fixed laws" concurred with Whewell, writing in his second edition of On The Origin of Species:
There is grandeur in this view of life, with its several powers, having been originally breathed by the Creator into a few forms or into one; and that, whilst this planet has gone cycling on according to the fixed law of gravity, from so simple a beginning endless forms most beautiful and most wonderful have been, and are being, evolved.
— Charles Darwin, The Origin of Species (1860)
By the time that Darwin published his theory, theologians of liberal Christianity
were already supporting such ideas, and by the late 19th century, their
modernist approach was predominant in theology. In science, evolution theory incorporating Darwin's natural selection became completely accepted.
Richard Dawkins
In The Blind Watchmaker, Richard Dawkins
argues that the watch analogy conflates the complexity that arises from
living organisms that are able to reproduce themselves (and may become
more complex over time) with the complexity of inanimate objects, unable
to pass on any reproductive changes (such as the multitude of parts
manufactured in a watch). The comparison breaks down because of this
important distinction.
In a BBC Horizon episode, also entitled The Blind Watchmaker,
Dawkins described Paley's argument as being "as mistaken as it is
elegant". In both contexts, he saw Paley as having made an incorrect
proposal as to a certain problem's solution, but Dawkins did not
disrespect him. In his essay The Big Bang, Steven Pinker
discusses Dawkins's coverage of Paley's argument, adding: "Biologists
today do not disagree with Paley's laying out of the problem. They
disagree only with his solution."
In his book The God Delusion,
Dawkins argues that life was the result of complex biological
processes. He makes the argument that the comparison to the lucky
construction of a watch is fallacious because proponents of evolution do
not consider evolution "lucky". Rather than luck, the evolution of
human life is the result of billions of years of natural selection. He
concludes that evolution is a fair contestant to replace God in the role
of watchmaker.
In addition, he argues that the watchmaker's creation of the
watch implies that the watchmaker must be more complex than the watch.
Design is top-down, someone or something more complex designs something
less complex.
To follow the line upwards demands that the watch was designed by a
(necessarily more complex) watchmaker, the watchmaker must have been
created by a more complex being than himself. So the question becomes
who designed the designer?
Dawkins argues that (a) this line continues ad infinitum, and (b) it
does not explain anything.
Evolution, on the other hand, takes a bottom-up approach; it
explains how more complexity can arise gradually by building on or
combining lesser complexity.
In response to such claims, Nathan Schneider writes, "Paley died decades before The Origin of Species
was published, and ever since his views have been so repeatedly set in
opposition to Darwin's that Richard Dawkins titled one of his books on
evolution The Blind Watchmaker. A closer look at Paley's own
thinking reveals, however, a God who works through the laws of nature,
not beyond them like the modern ID theorists' designer. Paley had no
objection to species changing over time. It's only in today's highly
polarized culture-war climate that we don't bother to notice that one of
the forefathers of intelligent design theory might have been perfectly
comfortable with evolution."
Richerson and Boyd
Biologist Peter Richerson and anthropologist Robert Boyd
offer an oblique criticism by arguing that watches were not "hopeful
monsters created by single inventors," but were created by watchmakers
building up their skills in a cumulative fashion over time, each
contributing to a watch-making tradition from which any individual
watchmaker draws their designs.
Contemporary usage
In the early 20th century, the modernist theology of higher criticism was contested in the United States by Biblical literalists, who campaigned successfully against the teaching of evolution and began calling themselves creationists in the 1920s. When teaching of evolution was reintroduced into public schools in the 1960s, they adopted what they called creation science that had a central concept of design in similar terms to Paley's argument. That idea was then relabeled intelligent design,
which presents the same analogy as an argument against evolution by
natural selection without explicitly stating that the "intelligent
designer" was God. The argument from the complexity of biological
organisms was now presented as the irreducible complexity argument, the most notable proponent of which was Michael Behe, and, leveraging off the verbiage of information theory, the specified complexity argument, the most notable proponent of which was William Dembski.
The watchmaker analogy was referenced in the 2005 Kitzmiller v. Dover Area School District trial. Throughout the trial, Paley was mentioned several times. The defense's expert witness John Haught noted that both Intelligent Design and the watchmaker analogy are "reformulations" of the same theological argument.
On day 21 of the trial, Mr. Harvey walked Dr. Minnich through a
modernized version of Paley's argument, substituting a cell phone for
the watch.
In his ruling, the judge stated that the use of the argument from design
by intelligent design proponents "is merely a restatement of the
Reverend William Paley's argument applied at the cell level,"
adding "Minnich, Behe, and Paley reach the same conclusion, that
complex organisms must have been designed using the same reasoning,
except that Professors Behe and Minnich refuse to identify the designer,
whereas Paley inferred from the presence of design that it was God."
The judge ruled that such an inductive argument is not accepted as
science because it is unfalsifiable.