economic theory framed as a "mythical species" or word play on homo sapiens, and used in pedagogy. It stands for a portrayal of humans as agents who are consistently rational and narrowly self-interested, and who usually pursue their subjectively-defined ends optimally.
The term homo economicus, or economic man, is a caricature of
Generally, homo economicus attempts to maximize utility as a consumer and profit as a producer. As a theory on human conduct, it contrasts to the concepts of behavioral economics, which examines cognitive biases and other irrationalities, and another mythical species, homo reciprocans, a model which emphasizes human cooperation). In game theory, homo economicus is often modelled through the assumption of perfect rationality.
The notion of "homo economicus" is often used by non-economists to critique an economic approach. There are distinct concepts involved: the preferences that individuals have among outcomes; and the processes that individuals use to make decisions. The question whether individuals are in fact able to make the best choices, given their preferences, leads to the economic definition of rationality, or the so-called "rational economic man". This concept of rationality does not restrict what sort of preferences are admissible.
The notion of "homo economicus" is often used by non-economists to critique an economic approach. There are distinct concepts involved: the preferences that individuals have among outcomes; and the processes that individuals use to make decisions. The question whether individuals are in fact able to make the best choices, given their preferences, leads to the economic definition of rationality, or the so-called "rational economic man". This concept of rationality does not restrict what sort of preferences are admissible.
History of the term
The term "economic man" was used for the first time in the late nineteenth century by critics of John Stuart Mill's work on political economy. Below is a passage from Mill's work that critics referred to:
[Political economy] does not treat the whole of man’s nature as modified by the social state, nor of the whole conduct of man in society. It is concerned with him solely as a being who desires to possess wealth, and who is capable of judging the comparative efficacy of means for obtaining that end.
Later in the same work, Mill stated that he was proposing "an
arbitrary definition of man, as a being who inevitably does that by
which he may obtain the greatest amount of necessaries, conveniences,
and luxuries, with the smallest quantity of labour and physical
self-denial with which they can be obtained."
Adam Smith, in The Theory of Moral Sentiments, had claimed that individuals have sympathy for the well-being of others. On the other hand, in The Wealth of Nations, Smith wrote:
It is not from the benevolence of the butcher, the brewer, or the baker that we expect our dinner, but from their regard to their own interest.
This comment now suggests the same sort of rational, self-interested, labor-averse individual that Mill proposed. Aristotle's Politics had discussed the nature of self-interest in Book II, Part V.
Again, how immeasurably greater is the pleasure, when a man feels a thing to be his own; for surely the love of self is a feeling implanted by nature and not given in vain, although selfishness is rightly censured; this, however, is not the mere love of self, but the love of self in excess, like the miser's love of money; for all, or almost all, men love money and other such objects in a measure. And further, there is the greatest pleasure in doing a kindness or service to friends or guests or companions, which can only be rendered when a man has private property.
Economists in the late 19th century—such as Francis Edgeworth, William Stanley Jevons, Léon Walras, and Vilfredo Pareto—built mathematical models on these economic assumptions. In the 20th century, the rational choice theory of Lionel Robbins
came to dominate mainstream economics. The term "economic man" then
took on a more specific meaning: a person who acted rationally on
complete knowledge out of self-interest and the desire for wealth.
Model
Homo economicus is a term used for an approximation or model of Homo sapiens
that acts to obtain the highest possible well-being for him or herself
given available information about opportunities and other constraints,
both natural and institutional, on his ability to achieve his predetermined goals. This approach has been formalized in certain social sciences models, particularly in economics.
Homo economicus is seen as "rational" in the sense that well-being as defined by the utility function
is optimized given perceived opportunities. That is, the individual
seeks to attain very specific and predetermined goals to the greatest
extent with the least possible cost. Note that this kind of
"rationality" does not say that the individual's actual goals are
"rational" in some larger ethical, social, or human sense, only that he
tries to attain them at minimal cost. Only naïve applications of the homo economicus
model assume that this hypothetical individual knows what is best for
his long-term physical and mental health and can be relied upon to
always make the right decision for himself. See rational choice theory and rational expectations for further discussion; the article on rationality widens the discussion.
As in social science, these assumptions are at best
approximations. The term is often used derogatorily in academic
literature, perhaps most commonly by sociologists, many of whom tend to prefer structural explanations to ones based on rational action by individuals.
The use of the Latin form homo economicus is certainly long established; Persky traces it back to Pareto (1906) but notes that it may be older. The English term economic man can be found even earlier, in John Kells Ingram's A History of Political Economy (1888). The Oxford English Dictionary (O.E.D.) cites the use of homo oeconomicus by C. S. Devas in his 1883 work The Groundwork of Economics in reference to Mill's writings, as one of a number of phrases that imitate the scientific name for the human species:
Mill has only examined the homo oeconomicus, or dollar-hunting animal.
According to the OED, the human genus name homo is
Used with L. or mock-L. adjs. in names imitating Homo sapiens, etc., and intended to personify some aspect of human life or behaviour (indicated by the adj.). Homo faber ("feIb@(r)) [H. Bergson L'Evolution Créatrice (1907) ii. 151], a term used to designate man as a maker of tools.) Variants are often comic: Homo insipiens; Homo turisticus.
Note that such forms should logically keep the capital for the "genus" name—i.e., Homo economicus rather than homo economicus. Actual usage is inconsistent.
Amartya Sen
has argued there are grave pitfalls in assuming that rationality is
limited to selfish rationality. Economics should build into its
assumptions the notion that people can give credible commitments to a
course of conduct. He demonstrates the absurdity with the narrowness of
the assumptions by some economists with the following example of two
strangers meeting on a street.
“ | "Where is the railway station?" he asks me. "There," I say, pointing at the post office, "and would you please post this letter for me on the way?" "Yes," he says, determined to open the envelope and check whether it contains something valuable. | ” |
Criticisms
Homo economicus bases its choices on a consideration of its own personal "utility function".
Consequently, the homo economicus assumptions have been
criticized not only by economists on the basis of logical arguments, but
also on empirical grounds by cross-cultural comparison. Economic
anthropologists such as Marshall Sahlins, Karl Polanyi, Marcel Mauss and Maurice Godelier
have demonstrated that in traditional societies, choices people make
regarding production and exchange of goods follow patterns of reciprocity which differ sharply from what the homo economicus model postulates. Such systems have been termed gift economy rather than market economy. Criticisms of the homo economicus
model put forward from the standpoint of ethics usually refer to this
traditional ethic of kinship-based reciprocity that held together
traditional societies.
Economists Thorstein Veblen, John Maynard Keynes, Herbert A. Simon, and many of the Austrian School criticise homo economicus as an actor with too great an understanding of macroeconomics and economic forecasting in his decision making. They stress uncertainty and bounded rationality
in the making of economic decisions, rather than relying on the
rational man who is fully informed of all circumstances impinging on his
decisions. They argue that perfect knowledge never exists, which means
that all economic activity implies risk. Austrian economists rather
prefer to use as a model tool the homo agens.
Empirical studies by Amos Tversky
questioned the assumption that investors are rational. In 1995, Tversky
demonstrated the tendency of investors to make risk-averse choices in
gains, and risk-seeking choices in losses. The investors appeared as
very risk-averse for small losses but indifferent for a small chance of a
very large loss. This violates economic rationality as usually
understood. Further research on this subject, showing other deviations
from conventionally defined economic rationality, is being done in the
growing field of experimental or behavioral economics. Some of the broader issues involved in this criticism are studied in decision theory, of which rational choice theory is only a subset.
Other critics of the homo economicus model of humanity, such as Bruno Frey, point to the excessive emphasis on extrinsic motivation (rewards and punishments from the social environment) as opposed to intrinsic motivation. For example, it is difficult if not impossible to understand how homo economicus would be a hero in war or would get inherent pleasure from craftsmanship.
Frey and others argue that too much emphasis on rewards and punishments
can "crowd out" (discourage) intrinsic motivation: paying a boy for
doing household tasks may push him from doing those tasks "to help the
family" to doing them simply for the reward.
Another weakness is highlighted by economic sociologists and anthropologists, who argue that homo economicus
ignores an extremely important question, i.e. the origins of tastes and
the parameters of the utility function by social influences, training,
education, and the like. The exogeneity of tastes (preferences) in this
model is the major distinction from homo sociologicus, in which tastes are taken as partially or even totally determined by the societal environment (see below).
Further critics, learning from the broadly defined psychoanalytic tradition, criticize the homo economicus model as ignoring the inner conflicts that real-world individuals suffer, as between short-term and long-term goals (e.g.,
eating chocolate cake and losing weight) or between individual goals
and societal values. Such conflicts may lead to "irrational" behavior
involving inconsistency, psychological paralysis, neurosis, and psychic
pain. Further irrational human behaviour can occur as a result of habit,
laziness, mimicry and simple obedience.
The emerging science of "neuroeconomics" suggests that there are serious shortcomings in the conventional theories of economic rationality. Rational economic decision making has been shown to produce high levels of cortisol, epinephrine and corticosteroids,
associated with elevated levels of stress. It seems that the dopaminic
system is only activated upon achieving the reward, and otherwise the
"pain" receptors, particularly in the pre-frontal cortex of the left
hemisphere of the brain show a high level of activation. Serotonin and oxytocin
levels are minimised, and the general immune system shows a level of
suppression. Such a pattern is associated with a generalised reduction
in the levels of trust. Unsolicited "gift giving", considered
irrational from the point of view of homo-economicus, by comparison,
shows an elevated stimulation of the pleasure circuits of the whole
brain, reduction in the levels of stress, optimal functioning of the
immune system, reduction in cortico-steroids and epinephrine and
cortisol, activation of the substantia nigra, the striatum and the nucleus acumbens (associated with the placebo effect, all associated with the building of social trust. Mirror neurons result in a win-win positive sum game in which the person giving the gift receives a pleasure equivalent to the person receiving it. This confirms the findings of anthropology which suggest that a "gift economy" preceded the more recent market systems where win-lose or risk-avoidance lose-lose calculations apply.
Responses
Economists tend to disagree with these critiques, arguing that it may be relevant to analyze the consequences of enlightened egoism
just as it may be worthwhile to consider altruistic or social behavior.
Others argue that we need to understand the consequences of such
narrow-minded greed even if only a small percentage of the population
embraces such motives. Free riders, for example, would have a major negative impact on the provision of public goods.
However, economists' supply and demand predictions might obtain even if
only a significant minority of market participants act like homo economicus. In this view, the assumption of homo economicus can and should be simply a preliminary step on the road to a more sophisticated model.
Yet others argue that homo economicus is a reasonable
approximation for behavior within market institutions, since the
individualized nature of human action in such social settings encourages
individualistic behavior. Not only do market settings encourage the
application of a simple cost-benefit calculus by individuals, but they
reward and thus attract the more individualistic people. It can be
difficult to apply social values (as opposed to following self-interest)
in an extremely competitive market; a company that refuses to pollute,
for example, may find itself bankrupt.
Defenders of the homo economicus model see many critics of the dominant school as using a straw man
technique. For example, it is common for critics to argue that real
people do not have cost-less access to infinite information and an
innate ability to instantly process it. However, in advanced-level
theoretical economics, scholars have found ways of addressing these
problems, modifying models enough to more realistically depict real-life
decision-making. For example, models of individual behavior under bounded rationality and of people suffering from envy can be found in the literature.
It is primarily when targeting the limiting assumptions made in
constructing undergraduate models that the criticisms listed above are
valid. These criticisms are especially valid to the extent that the
professor asserts that the simplifying assumptions are true or uses them
in a propagandistic way.
The more sophisticated economists are quite conscious of the empirical limitations of the homo economicus model. In theory, the views of the critics can be combined with the homo economicus model to attain a more accurate model.
Perspectives
According to Sergio Caruso, when talking of Homo economicus,
one should distinguish between the purely “methodological” versions,
aimed at practical use in the economic sphere (e.g. economic calculus),
and the” anthropological” versions, more ambitiously aimed at depicting a
certain type of man (supposed to be actually existing), or even human
nature in general. The former, traditionally founded on a merely
speculative psychology, have proved unrealistic and frankly wrong as
descriptive models of economic behaviour (therefore not applicable for
normative purposes either); however, they are liable to be corrected
resorting to the new empirically based economic psychology,
which turns quite other than the philosophers’ psychology that
economists have used until yesterday. Among the latter (i.e. the
anthropological versions), one can make a further distinction between
the weak versions, more plausible, and the strong ones, irreparably
ideological. Depicting different types of “economic man” (each depending
on the social context) is in fact possible with the help of cultural anthropology, and social psychology
(a branch of psychology economists have strangely ignored), if only
those types are contrived as socially and/or historically determined
abstractions (such as Weber's, Korsch's, and Fromm's concepts of Idealtypus, “historical specification”, and “social character”). Even a Marxist theoretician such as Gramsci—reminds Caruso—admitted of the homo economicus as a useful abstraction on the ground of economic theory, provided that we grant there be as many homines oeconomici as the modes of production. On the contrary, when one concept of homo economicus
claims to grasp the eternal essence of what is human, at the same time
putting aside all other aspects of human nature (such as homo faber, homo loquens, homo ludens, homo reciprocans,
and so on), then the concept leaves the field of good philosophy, not
to speak of social science, and is ready to enter a political doctrine
as the most dangerous of its ideological ingredients.
Homo sociologicus
Comparisons between economics and sociology have resulted in a corresponding term homo sociologicus (introduced by German sociologist Ralf Dahrendorf
in 1958), to parody the image of human nature given in some
sociological models that attempt to limit the social forces that
determine individual tastes and social values. (The alternative or additional source of these would be biology.) Hirsch et al. say that homo sociologicus is largely a tabula rasa upon which societies and cultures write values and goals; unlike economicus, sociologicus acts not to pursue selfish interests but to fulfill social roles (though the fulfillment of social roles may have a selfish rationale—e.g. politicians or socialites). This "individual" may appear to be all society and no individual.