Social ownership is any of various forms of ownership for the means of production in socialist economic systems, encompassing public ownership, employee ownership, cooperative ownership, citizen ownership of equity, common ownership and collective ownership. Historically social ownership implied that capital and factor markets
would cease to exist under the assumption that market exchanges within
the production process would be made redundant if capital goods were
owned by a single entity or network of entities representing society, but the articulation of models of market socialism
where factor markets are utilized for allocating capital goods between
socially owned enterprises broadened the definition to include
autonomous entities within a market economy. Social ownership of the
means of production is the common defining characteristic of all the
various forms of socialism.
The two major forms of social ownership are society-wide public
ownership and cooperative ownership. The distinction between these two
forms lies in the distribution of the surplus product. With society-wide public ownership, the surplus is distributed to all members of the public through a social dividend,
whereas with co-operative ownership the economic surplus of an
enterprise is controlled by all the worker-members of that specific
enterprise.
The goal of social ownership is to eliminate the distinction between the class of private owners who are the recipients of passive property income and workers who are the recipients of labor income (wages, salaries and commissions), so that the surplus product (or economic profits in the case of market socialism) belong either to society as a whole or to the members of a given enterprise. Social ownership would enable productivity gains from labor automation to progressively reduce the average length of the working day instead of creating job insecurity and unemployment. Reduction of necessary work time is central to the Marxist concept of human freedom and overcoming alienation, a concept widely shared by Marxist and non-Marxist socialists alike.
The term "socialization" refers to the process of restructuring the economic framework, organizational structure and institutions of an economy on a socialist basis. The comprehensive notion of socialization and the public ownership form of social ownership implies an end to the operation of the laws of capitalism, capital accumulation and the use of money and financial valuation in the production process, along with a restructuring of workplace-level organization.
The goal of social ownership is to eliminate the distinction between the class of private owners who are the recipients of passive property income and workers who are the recipients of labor income (wages, salaries and commissions), so that the surplus product (or economic profits in the case of market socialism) belong either to society as a whole or to the members of a given enterprise. Social ownership would enable productivity gains from labor automation to progressively reduce the average length of the working day instead of creating job insecurity and unemployment. Reduction of necessary work time is central to the Marxist concept of human freedom and overcoming alienation, a concept widely shared by Marxist and non-Marxist socialists alike.
The term "socialization" refers to the process of restructuring the economic framework, organizational structure and institutions of an economy on a socialist basis. The comprehensive notion of socialization and the public ownership form of social ownership implies an end to the operation of the laws of capitalism, capital accumulation and the use of money and financial valuation in the production process, along with a restructuring of workplace-level organization.
Objectives
Social ownership is variously advocated to end the Marxian concept of exploitation, to ensure that income distribution reflects individual contributions to the social product, to eliminate unemployment arising from technological change, to ensure a more egalitarian distribution of the economy's surplus, or to create the foundations for a non-market socialist economy.
In Karl Marx's
analysis of capitalism, social ownership of the means of production
emerges in response to the contradictions between socialized production
and private appropriation of surplus value in capitalism. Marx argued
that productivity gains arising from the substitution of variable capital (labor inputs) for constant capital
(capital inputs) would cause labor displacement to outstrip the demand
for labor. This process would lead to stagnant wages and rising
unemployment for the working class alongside rising property income for
the capitalist class, further leading to an over-accumulation of capital.
Marx argued that this dynamic would reach a point where social
ownership of the highly automated means of production would be
necessitated to resolve this contradiction and resulting social strife.
Thus the Marxist case for social ownership and socialism is not based on
any moral critique of the distribution of property income (wealth) in
capitalism, but rather the Marxist case for socialism is based on a
systematic analysis of the development and limits of the dynamic of
capital accumulation.
For Marx, social ownership would lay the foundations for the
transcendence of the capitalist law of value and the accumulation of
capital, thereby creating the foundation for socialist planning. The
ultimate goal of social ownership of productive property for Marx was to
expand the "realm of freedom" by shortening average work hours so that
individuals would have progressively larger portion of their time to
pursue their genuine and creative interests. Thus the end goal of social
ownership is the transcendence of the Marxist concept of alienation.
The economist David McMullen identifies five major benefits of
social ownership, where he defines it as society-wide ownership of
productive property: first, workers would be more productive and have
greater motivation since they would directly benefit from increased
productivity, secondly this ownership stake would enable greater
accountability on the part of individuals and organizations, thirdly
social ownership would eliminate unemployment, fourth it would enable
the better flow of information within the economy, and finally it would
eliminate wasteful activities associated with "wheeling and dealing" and
wasteful government activities intended to curb such behavior and deal
with unemployment.
From a non-Marxist, market socialist perspective, the clearest
benefit of social ownership is an equalization of the distribution of
property income, eliminating the vast disparities in wealth that arise
from private ownership under capitalism. Property income (profit,
interest and rent) is distinguished from labor income (wages and
salaries) which in a socialist system would continue to be unequal based
on one's marginal product of labor – social ownership would only equalize passive property income.
Notable non-Marxist and Marxist socialist theorists alike have
argued that the most significant argument for social ownership of the
means of production is to enable productivity gains to ease the work
burden for all individuals in society, resulting in progressively
shorter hours of work with increasing automation and thus a greater
amount of free time for individuals to engage in creative pursuits and
leisure.
Criticism of private ownership
Social ownership is contrasted with the concept of private ownership of the means of production, promoted as a solution to what its proponents see as being inherent issues to private ownership. Market socialists and non-market socialists
therefore have slightly different conceptions of social ownership. The
former believe that private ownership and private appropriation of property income
is the fundamental issue with capitalism, and thus believe that the
process of capital accumulation and profit-maximizing enterprise can be
retained, with their profits being used to benefit society in the form
of a social dividend.
By contrast, non-market socialists argue that the major problems with
capitalism arise from its contradictory economic laws that make it
unsustainable and historically limited. Therefore, social ownership is
seen as a component of the establishment of non-market coordination and
alternative "socialist laws of motion" that overcome the systemic issues
of capital accumulation.
The socialist critique of private ownership is heavily influenced
by the Marxian analysis of capitalist property forms as part of its
broader critique of alienation
and exploitation in capitalism. Although there is considerable
disagreement among socialists about the validity of certain aspects of
Marxian analysis, the majority of socialists are sympathetic to Marx's
views on exploitation and alienation.
Socialists critique the private appropriation of property income on the
grounds that because such income does not correspond to a return on any
productive activity and is generated by the working class, it
represents exploitation. The property-owning (capitalist) class lives
off passive property income produced by the working population by virtue
of their claim to ownership in the form of stock, bonds or private
equity. This exploitative arrangement is perpetuated due to the
structure of capitalist society. From this perspective, capitalism is
regarded as class system akin to historical class systems like slavery
and feudalism.
Private ownership has also been criticized on ethical grounds by
the economist James Yunker. Yunker argues that because passive property
income requires no mental or physical exertion on the part of the
recipient and because its appropriation by a small group of private
owners is the source of the vast inequalities in contemporary
capitalism, this establishes the ethical case for social ownership and
socialist transformation.
Socialization as a process
Socialization
is conceived as a process that transforms the economic processes and,
by extension, the social relations within an economy. As such, it is
distinct from the process of "nationalization" which does not
necessarily imply a transformation of the organizational structure of
organizations or the transformation of the economic framework under
which economic organizations operate.
Marxists envision socialization as a restructuring of social
relations to overcome alienation, replacing hierarchical social
relations within the workplace with an association of members.
Socialization debates
During the 1920s, socialists in Austria and Germany were engaged in a
comprehensive dialogue about the nature of socialization and how a
program of socialization could be effectively carried out. Austrian scientific thinkers whose ideas were based on Ernst Mach's
empiricist notion of energy and technological optimism, including Josef
Popper-Lynkeus and Carl Ballod, proposed plans for rational allocation
of exhaustible energy and materials through statistical empirical
methods. This conception of non-capitalist calculation involved the use
of energy and time units, the latter being viewed as the standard
cardinal unity of measurement for socialist calculation. These thinkers
belonged to a technical school of thought called "scientific
utopianism", which is an approach to social engineering that explores
possible forms of social organization.
The most notable thinker belonging to this school of thought was the Viennese philosopher and economist Otto Neurath,
whose conception of socialism as a natural, non-monetary economic
system became widespread within the socialist movement following the end
of World War I. Neurath's position was held in contrast to other
socialists in this period, including the revisionist perspective
stemming from Eduard Bernstein, the orthodox social democratic perspective of Karl Kautsky, the Austro-Marxism models of labor-time calculation
from Otto Bauer and the emerging school of neoclassical market
socialism. Neurath's position opposed all models of market socialism
because it rejected the use of money, but was also held in contrast with
the more orthodox Marxist conception of socialism held by Karl Kautsky,
where socialism only entails the elimination of money as capital along
with super-session of the process of capital accumulation.
Otto Neurath conceptualized a comprehensive view of socialization
during the socialization debates. "Total socialization" involved not
only a form of ownership but also the establishment of economic planning
based on calculation in kind,
and was contrasted with "partial socialization". "Partial
socialization" involved the use of in-kind calculation and planning
within a single organization, which externally operated within the
framework of a monetary market economy. Neurath's conception of
socialism was the initial point of criticism of Ludwig Von Mises in the socialist calculation debate.
In the subsequent socialist calculation debates, a dichotomy
between socialists emerged between those who argued that socialization
entailed the end of monetary valuation and capital markets, and those
who argued that monetary prices could be used within a socialized
economy. A further distinction arose between market socialists who
argued that social ownership can be achieved within the context of a
market economy, where worker-owned or publicly owned enterprises
maximized profit and those who argued that socially owned enterprises
operate according to other criteria, like marginal cost pricing.
Typology
Social ownership and socialization is categorically distinct from the process of nationalization. In most cases, "socialization" is understood to be a deeper process of transforming the social relations of production
within economic organizations as opposed to simply changing titles of
ownership. In this sense, "socialization" often involves both a change
in ownership and a change in organizational management, including self-management
or some form of workplace democracy in place of a strict hierarchical
form of control. More fundamentally, social ownership implies that the
surplus product (or economic profits) generated by publicly owned
enterprise accrues to all of society – state ownership does not
necessarily imply this.
Fundamentally, there are two major forms of "social ownership".
The first is society-wide public ownership by an entity or network of
entities representing society.
The second major form of social ownership is employee-owned cooperative
enterprise, with the members of each individual enterprise being
co-owners of their organization. These possibilities give rise to a socialization dilemma,
faced by advocates of public ownership: if social ownership is
entrusted exclusively to state agents, then it is liable to
bureaucratization; if it is entrusted exclusively to workers, then it is
liable to monopoly power and abuse of market position.
Additionally, there are two major forms of management or "social
control" for socially owned organizations, both of which can exist
alongside the two major modes of social ownership. The first variant of
control is public management, where enterprises are run by management
held accountable to an agency representing the public either at the
level of national, regional or local government. The second form of
social control is worker self-management,
where managers are elected by the member-workers of each individual
enterprise or enterprises are run according to self-directed work
processes.
The exact forms of social ownership vary depending on whether or
not they are conceptualized as part of a market economy or as part of a
non-market planned economy.
Public ownership
Public
ownership can exist both within the framework of a market economy and
within the framework of a non-market planned economy. In market
socialist proposals, public ownership takes the form of state-owned
enterprises that acquire capital goods in capital markets and operate to
maximize profits, which are then distributed among the entire
population in the form of a social dividend.
In non-market models of socialism, public ownership takes the form of a
single entity or a network of public entities coordinated by economic
planning. A contemporary approach to socialism involves linking together
production and distribution units by modern computers to achieve rapid
feedback in the allocation of capital inputs to achieve efficient
economic planning.
The economist Alec Nove defines social ownership as a form of autonomous public ownership,
drawing a distinction between state-owned and directed enterprises.
Nove advocates for the existence of both forms of enterprise in his
model of feasible socialism.
Public ownership was advocated by neoclassical socialist
economists during the interwar socialist calculation debate, most
notable Oskar Lange, Fred M. Taylor, Abba P. Lerner and Maurice Dobb.
Neoclassical market socialist economists in the latter half of
the 20th century who advocated public ownership highlighted the
distinction between "control" and "ownership". John Roemer and Pranab
Bardhan argued that public ownership, meaning a relatively egalitarian
distribution of enterprise profits, does not require state control –
Publicly owned enterprises can be controlled by agents who don't
represent the state.
David McMullen's concept of decentralized non-market socialism
advocates social ownership of the means of production, believing it to
be far more efficient than private ownership. In his proposal, property
titles would be replaced by "usership" rights and the exchange of
capital goods would no longer be possible. Market exchange in capital
goods would be replaced by internal transfers of resources, but an
internal and decentralized price system would be fundamental to this
systems' operation.
However, by itself public ownership is not socialist as it can exist under a wide variety of different political and economic systems.
State ownership by itself does not imply social ownership where income
rights belong to society as a whole. As such, state ownership is only
one possible expression of public ownership, which itself is one
variation of the broader concept of social ownership.
Social ownership of equity
The
social ownership of capital and corporate stock have been proposed in
the context of a market socialist system, where social ownership is
achieved either by having a public body or employee-owned pension funds
own corporate stock.
The American economist John Roemer
developed a model of market socialism that features a form of public
ownership where individuals receive a non-transferable coupon entitling
them to a share of the profits generated by autonomous non-governmental
publicly owned enterprises. In this model, "social ownership" refers to
citizen ownership of equity in a market economy.
James Yunker argues that public ownership of the means of
production can be achieved in the same way private ownership is achieved
in modern capitalism, using the shareholder system that effectively
separates management from ownership. Yunker posits that social ownership
can be achieved by having a public body, designated the Bureau of
Public Ownership (BPO), own the shares of publicly listed firms without
affecting market-based allocation of capital inputs. Yunker termed this
model Pragmatic market socialism and argued that it would be at
least as efficient as modern-day capitalism while providing superior
social outcomes as public ownership would enable profits to be
distributed among the entire population rather than going largely to a
class of inheriting rentiers.
An alternative form of social ownership of equity is ownership of
corporate stock through wage earner funds and pension funds. The
underlying concept was first expounded upon in 1976 by the management
theorist Peter Drucker,
who argued that pension funds could reconcile employees' need for
financial security with capital's need to be mobile and diversified,
referring to this development as "pension fund socialism". In Sweden
during the late 1970s, the Meidner program was advanced by the Swedish Social Democratic Party as a way to socialize enterprises through employee wage earners' funds, which would be used to purchase corporate stock. Rudolf Meidner's
original plan was to require Swedish companies over a certain size to
issue shares equal to 20 percent of profits, which would be owned by
wage-earner funds controlled by employees through their trade unions.
This plan was rejected and a watered-down proposal was adopted in 1984,
which left corporate decision making just as it was and limited the
scope of employee ownership to less than 3.5% of listed company shares
in 1990.
Cooperative ownership
Cooperative ownership is the organization of economic units into enterprises owned by their workforce (workers cooperative) or by customers who use the products of the enterprise (this latter concept is called a consumer cooperative).
Cooperatives are often organized around some form of self-management,
either in the form of elected managers held accountable to the
workforce, or in the form of direct management of work processes by the
workers themselves. Cooperatives are often proposed by proponents of
market socialism, most notably by the economists Branko Horvat, Jaroslav
Vanek and Richard Wolff.
Cooperative ownership comes in various forms, ranging from direct workers' ownership, employee stock ownership plans
through pension funds, to the weakest version involving profit sharing.
Profit-sharing and varying degrees of self-management or "Holacracy" is practiced in many of the high-technology companies of Silicon Valley.
The earliest model of cooperative socialism is mutualism, proposed by the French anarchist philosopher Pierre-Joseph Proudhon.
In this system, the state would be abolished and economic enterprises
would be owned and operated as producer cooperatives, with
worker-members compensated in labor vouchers.
The model of market socialism promoted in the former Socialist Federal Republic of Yugoslavia
was based on what was officially called "social ownership", involving
an arrangement where workers of each firm each became members and
joint-owners and managed their own affairs in a system of workers'
self-management.
Contemporary proponents of cooperative ownership cite higher
motivation and performance in existing cooperatives. Critics argue that
cooperative ownership by itself does not resolve the structural issues
of capitalism like economic crises and the business cycle, and that
cooperatives have an incentive to limit employment in order to boost the
income of existing members.
Commons and peer-to-peer
In the context of non-market proposals, social ownership can include holding the means of producing wealth in common (common ownership), with the concept of "usership" replacing the concept of ownership. Commons-based peer production
involves the distribution of a critical mass of inputs and all outputs
through information networks as free goods rather than commodities to be
sold for profit by capitalist firms.
The economist Pat Devine defines social ownership as "ownership
by those who are affected by – who have an interest in – the use of the
assets involved", distinguishing it from other forms of ownership.
Devine argues that this variant of social ownership will be more
efficient than the other types of ownership because "it enables the
tacit knowledge of all those affected to be drawn upon in the process of
negotiating what should be done to further the social interest in any
particular context".
The phrases "social production" and "social peer-to-peer"
production have been used to classify the type of workplace
relationships and ownership structures found in the open-source software movement and Commons-based peer production processes, which operate, value and allocate value without private property and market exchange.
Ownership in Soviet-type economies
In Soviet-type economies,
the means of production and natural resources were almost entirely
owned by the state and collective enterprises. State enterprises were
integrated into a national planning system, where factor inputs were
allocated to them by the Ministry for Technical Supply (Gossnab).
According to The Great Soviet Encyclopedia, "socialist
ownership" is a form of social ownership that forms the basis for the
socialist system, involving the collective appropriation of material
wealth by working people. Social ownership arises out of the course of
capitalist development, creating the objective conditions for further
socialist transformation and for the emergence of a planned economy with
the aim of raising the living standards for everyone in society.
Misuse of the term
Particularly
in the United States, the term "socialization" has been mistakenly used
to refer to any state or government-operated industry or service (the
proper term for such being either nationalization or municipalization). It has also been incorrectly used to mean any tax-funded programs, whether privately run or government run.