The Bohr–Einstein debates were a series of public disputes about quantum mechanics between Albert Einstein and Niels Bohr. Their debates are remembered because of their importance to the philosophy of science. An account of the debates was written by Bohr in an article titled "Discussions with Einstein
on Epistemological Problems in Atomic Physics".
Despite their differences of opinion regarding quantum mechanics, Bohr
and Einstein had a mutual admiration that was to last the rest of their
lives.
The debates represent one of the highest points of scientific
research in the first half of the twentieth century because it called
attention to an element of quantum theory, quantum non-locality,
which is central to our modern understanding of the physical world. The
consensus view of professional physicists has been that Bohr proved
victorious in his defense of quantum theory, and definitively
established the fundamental probabilistic character of quantum
measurement.
Pre-revolutionary debates
Einstein was the first physicist to say that Planck's discovery of the quantum (h) would require a rewriting of the laws of physics. To support his point, in 1905 he proposed that light sometimes acts as a particle which he called a light quantum. Bohr was one of the most vocal opponents of the photon idea and did not openly embrace it until 1925.
The photon appealed to Einstein because he saw it as a physical reality
(although a confusing one) behind the numbers. Bohr disliked it because
it made the choice of mathematical solution arbitrary. He did not like a
scientist having to choose between equations.
1913 brought the Bohr model of the hydrogen atom,
which made use of the quantum to explain the atomic spectrum. Einstein
was at first skeptical, but quickly changed his mind and admitted his
shift in mindset.
The quantum revolution
The
quantum revolution of the mid-1920s occurred under the direction of
both Einstein and Bohr, and their post-revolutionary debates were about
making sense of the change. The shocks for Einstein began in 1925 when Werner Heisenberg
introduced matrix equations that removed the Newtonian elements of
space and time from any underlying reality. The next shock came in 1926
when Max Born proposed that mechanics were to be understood as a probability without any causal explanation.
Einstein rejected this interpretation. In a 1926 letter to Max Born, Einstein wrote: "I, at any rate, am convinced that He [God] does not throw dice."
At the Fifth Solvay Conference held in October 1927
Heisenberg and Born concluded that the revolution was over and nothing
further was needed. It was at that last stage that Einstein's skepticism
turned to dismay. He believed that much had been accomplished, but the
reasons for the mechanics still needed to be understood.
Einstein's refusal to accept the revolution as complete reflected
his desire to see developed a model for the underlying causes from
which these apparent random statistical methods resulted. He did not
reject the idea that positions in space-time could never be completely
known but did not want to allow the uncertainty principle
to necessitate a seemingly random, non-deterministic mechanism by which
the laws of physics operated. Einstein himself was a statistical
thinker but disagreed that no more needed to be discovered and
clarified.
Bohr, meanwhile, was dismayed by none of the elements that troubled
Einstein. He made his own peace with the contradictions by proposing a principle of complementarity that emphasized the role of the observer over the observed.
Post-revolution: First stage
As
mentioned above, Einstein's position underwent significant
modifications over the course of the years. In the first stage, Einstein
refused to accept quantum indeterminism and sought to demonstrate that
the principle of indeterminacy could be violated, suggesting ingenious thought experiments
which should permit the accurate determination of incompatible
variables, such as position and velocity, or to explicitly reveal
simultaneously the wave and the particle aspects of the same process.
Einstein's argument
The first serious attack by Einstein on the "orthodox" conception took place during the Fifth Solvay International Conference on Electrons and Photons in 1927. Einstein pointed out how it was possible to take advantage of the (universally accepted) laws of conservation of energy and of impulse (momentum) in order to obtain information on the state of a particle in a process of interference which, according to the principle of indeterminacy or that of complementarity, should not be accessible.
In order to follow his argumentation and to evaluate Bohr's response,
it is convenient to refer to the experimental apparatus illustrated in
figure A. A beam of light perpendicular to the X axis propagates in the direction z and encounters a screen S1
with a narrow (relative to the wavelength of the ray) slit. After
having passed through the slit, the wave function diffracts with an
angular opening that causes it to encounter a second screen S2 with two slits. The successive propagation of the wave results in the formation of the interference figure on the final screen F.
At the passage through the two slits of the second screen S2, the wave aspects of the process become essential. In fact, it is precisely the interference between the two terms of the quantum superposition
corresponding to states in which the particle is localized in one of
the two slits which implies that the particle is "guided" preferably
into the zones of constructive interference and cannot end up in a point
in the zones of destructive interference (in which the wave function is
nullified). It is also important to note that any experiment designed
to evidence the "corpuscular" aspects of the process at the passage of the screen S2
(which, in this case, reduces to the determination of which slit the
particle has passed through) inevitably destroys the wave aspects,
implies the disappearance of the interference figure and the emergence
of two concentrated spots of diffraction which confirm our knowledge of
the trajectory followed by the particle.
At this point Einstein brings into play the first screen as well
and argues as follows: since the incident particles have velocities
(practically) perpendicular to the screen S1, and
since it is only the interaction with this screen that can cause a
deflection from the original direction of propagation, by the law of conservation of impulse
which implies that the sum of the impulses of two systems which
interact is conserved, if the incident particle is deviated toward the
top, the screen will recoil toward the bottom and vice versa. In
realistic conditions the mass of the screen is so large that it will
remain stationary, but, in principle, it is possible to measure even an
infinitesimal recoil. If we imagine taking the measurement of the
impulse of the screen in the direction X after every single
particle has passed, we can know, from the fact that the screen will be
found recoiled toward the top (bottom), whether the particle in question
has been deviated toward the bottom or top, and therefore through which
slit in S2 the particle has passed. But since the
determination of the direction of the recoil of the screen after the
particle has passed cannot influence the successive development of the
process, we will still have an interference figure on the screen F. The interference takes place precisely because the state of the system is the superposition
of two states whose wave functions are non-zero only near one of the
two slits. On the other hand, if every particle passes through only the
slit b or the slit c, then the set of systems is the
statistical mixture of the two states, which means that interference is
not possible. If Einstein is correct, then there is a violation of the
principle of indeterminacy.
Bohr's response
Bohr's response was to illustrate Einstein's idea more clearly using the diagram in Figure C. (Figure C shows a fixed screen S1
that is bolted down. Then try to imagine one that can slide up or down
along a rod instead of a fixed bolt.) Bohr observes that extremely
precise knowledge of any (potential) vertical motion of the screen is an
essential presupposition in Einstein's argument. In fact, if its
velocity in the direction X before the passage of the
particle is not known with a precision substantially greater than that
induced by the recoil (that is, if it were already moving vertically
with an unknown and greater velocity than that which it derives as a
consequence of the contact with the particle), then the determination of
its motion after the passage of the particle would not give the
information we seek. However, Bohr continues, an extremely precise
determination of the velocity of the screen, when one applies the
principle of indeterminacy, implies an inevitable imprecision of its
position in the direction X. Before the process even begins, the
screen would therefore occupy an indeterminate position at least to a
certain extent (defined by the formalism). Now consider, for example,
the point d in figure A, where the interference is destructive.
Any displacement of the first screen would make the lengths of the two
paths, a–b–d and a–c–d, different from those indicated in the figure. If the difference between the two paths varies by half a wavelength, at point d
there will be constructive rather than destructive interference. The
ideal experiment must average over all the possible positions of the
screen S1, and, for every position, there corresponds, for a certain fixed point F,
a different type of interference, from the perfectly destructive to the
perfectly constructive. The effect of this averaging is that the
pattern of interference on the screen F will be uniformly grey. Once more, our attempt to evidence the corpuscular aspects in S2 has destroyed the possibility of interference in F, which depends crucially on the wave aspects.
It should be noted that, as Bohr recognized, for the understanding of
this phenomenon "it is decisive that, contrary to genuine instruments
of measurement, these bodies along with the particles would constitute,
in the case under examination, the system to which the
quantum-mechanical formalism must apply. With respect to the precision
of the conditions under which one can correctly apply the formalism, it
is essential to include the entire experimental apparatus. In fact, the
introduction of any new apparatus, such as a mirror, in the path of a
particle could introduce new effects of interference which influence
essentially the predictions about the results which will be registered
at the end."
Further along, Bohr attempts to resolve this ambiguity concerning which
parts of the system should be considered macroscopic and which not:
- In particular, it must be very clear that...the unambiguous use of spatiotemporal concepts in the description of atomic phenomena must be limited to the registration of observations which refer to images on a photographic lens or to analogous practically irreversible effects of amplification such as the formation of a drop of water around an ion in a dark room.
Bohr's argument about the impossibility of using the apparatus
proposed by Einstein to violate the principle of indeterminacy depends
crucially on the fact that a macroscopic system (the screen S1)
obeys quantum laws. On the other hand, Bohr consistently held that, in
order to illustrate the microscopic aspects of reality, it is necessary
to set off a process of amplification, which involves macroscopic
apparatuses, whose fundamental characteristic is that of obeying
classical laws and which can be described in classical terms. This
ambiguity would later come back in the form of what is still called
today the measurement problem.
The principle of indeterminacy applied to time and energy
In many textbook examples and popular discussions of quantum
mechanics, the principle of indeterminacy is explained by reference to
the pair of variables position and velocity (or momentum). It is
important to note that the wave nature of physical processes implies
that there must exist another relation of indeterminacy: that between
time and energy. In order to comprehend this relation, it is convenient
to refer to the experiment illustrated in
Figure D, which results in the propagation of a wave which is limited in
spatial extension. Assume that, as illustrated in the figure, a ray
which is extremely extended longitudinally is propagated toward a screen
with a slit furnished with a shutter which remains open only for a very
brief interval of time . Beyond the slit, there will be a wave of limited spatial extension which continues to propagate toward the right.
A perfectly monochromatic wave (such as a musical note which
cannot be divided into harmonics) has infinite spatial extent. In order
to have a wave which is limited in spatial extension (which is
technically called a wave packet),
several waves of different frequencies must be superimposed and
distributed continuously within a certain interval of frequencies around
an average value, such as .
It then happens that at a certain instant, there exists a spatial region
(which moves over time) in which the contributions of the various
fields of the superposition add up constructively. Nonetheless,
according to a precise mathematical theorem, as we move far away from
this region, the phases
of the various fields, at any specified point, are distributed causally
and destructive interference is produced. The region in which the wave
has non-zero amplitude is therefore spatially limited. It is easy to
demonstrate that, if the wave has a spatial extension equal to (which means, in our example, that the shutter has remained open for a time
where v is the velocity of the wave), then the wave contains (or is a
superposition of) various monochromatic waves whose frequencies cover an
interval which satisfies the relation:
Remembering that in the universal relation of Planck, frequency and energy are proportional:
it follows immediately from the preceding inequality that the
particle associated with the wave should possess an energy which is not
perfectly defined (since different frequencies are involved in the
superposition) and consequently there is indeterminacy in energy:
From this it follows immediately that:
which is the relation of indeterminacy between time and energy.
Einstein's second criticism
At the sixth Congress of Solvay in 1930, the indeterminacy relation
just discussed was Einstein's target of criticism. His idea contemplates
the existence of an experimental apparatus which was subsequently
designed by Bohr in such a way as to emphasize the essential elements
and the key points which he would use in his response.
Einstein considers a box (called Einstein's box; see
figure) containing electromagnetic radiation and a clock which controls
the opening of a shutter which covers a hole made in one of the walls of
the box. The shutter uncovers the hole for a time
which can be chosen arbitrarily. During the opening, we are to suppose
that a photon, from among those inside the box, escapes through the
hole. In this way a wave of limited spatial extension has been created,
following the explanation given above. In order to challenge the
indeterminacy relation between time and energy, it is necessary to find a
way to determine with adequate precision the energy that the photon has
brought with it. At this point, Einstein turns to his celebrated
relation between mass and energy of special relativity: .
From this it follows that knowledge of the mass of an object provides a
precise indication about its energy. The argument is therefore very
simple: if one weighs the box before and after the opening of the
shutter and if a certain amount of energy has escaped from the box, the
box will be lighter. The variation in mass multiplied by
will provide precise knowledge of the energy emitted.
Moreover, the clock will indicate the precise time at which the event of
the particle's emission took place. Since, in principle, the mass of
the box can be determined to an arbitrary degree of accuracy, the energy
emitted can be determined with a precision as accurate as one desires. Therefore, the product can be rendered less than what is implied by the principle of indeterminacy.
The idea is particularly acute and the argument seemed unassailable.
It's important to consider the impact of all of these exchanges on the
people involved at the time. Leon Rosenfeld, a scientist who had participated in the Congress, described the event several years later:
- It was a real shock for Bohr...who, at first, could not think of a solution. For the entire evening he was extremely agitated, and he continued passing from one scientist to another, seeking to persuade them that it could not be the case, that it would have been the end of physics if Einstein were right; but he couldn't come up with any way to resolve the paradox. I will never forget the image of the two antagonists as they left the club: Einstein, with his tall and commanding figure, who walked tranquilly, with a mildly ironic smile, and Bohr who trotted along beside him, full of excitement...The morning after saw the triumph of Bohr.
Bohr's Triumph
The
"Triumph of Bohr" consisted in his demonstrating, once again, that
Einstein's subtle argument was not conclusive, but even more so in the
way that he arrived at this conclusion by appealing precisely to one of
the great ideas of Einstein: the principle of equivalence between
gravitational mass and inertial mass, together with the time dilation of
special relativity, and a consequence of these—the Gravitational redshift.
Bohr showed that, in order for Einstein's experiment to function, the
box would have to be suspended on a spring in the middle of a
gravitational field. In order to obtain a measurement of the weight of
the box, a pointer would have to be attached to the box which
corresponded with the index on a scale. After the release of a photon, a
mass could be added to the box to restore it to its original position and this would allow us to determine the energy that was lost when the photon left. The box is immersed in a gravitational field of strength , and the gravitational redshift affects the speed of the clock, yielding uncertainty in the time
required for the pointer to return to its original position. Bohr gave
the following calculation establishing the uncertainty relation .
Let the uncertainty in the mass be denoted by . Let the error in the position of the pointer be . Adding the load to the box imparts a momentum that we can measure with an accuracy , where ≈ . Clearly , and therefore . By the redshift formula (which follows from the principle of equivalence and the time dilation), the uncertainty in the time is , and , and so . We have therefore proven the claimed .
Post-revolution: Second stage
The second phase of Einstein's "debate" with Bohr and the orthodox
interpretation is characterized by an acceptance of the fact that it is,
as a practical matter, impossible to simultaneously determine the
values of certain incompatible quantities, but the rejection that this
implies that these quantities do not actually have precise values.
Einstein rejects the probabilistic interpretation of Born and insists that quantum probabilities are epistemic and not ontological
in nature. As a consequence, the theory must be incomplete in some way.
He recognizes the great value of the theory, but suggests that it
"does not tell the whole story", and, while providing an appropriate
description at a certain level, it gives no information on the more
fundamental underlying level:
- I have the greatest consideration for the goals which are pursued by the physicists of the latest generation which go under the name of quantum mechanics, and I believe that this theory represents a profound level of truth, but I also believe that the restriction to laws of a statistical nature will turn out to be transitory....Without doubt quantum mechanics has grasped an important fragment of the truth and will be a paragon for all future fundamental theories, for the fact that it must be deducible as a limiting case from such foundations, just as electrostatics is deducible from Maxwell's equations of the electromagnetic field or as thermodynamics is deducible from statistical mechanics.
These thoughts of Einstein would set off a line of research into hidden variable theories, such as the Bohm interpretation, in an attempt to complete the edifice of quantum theory. If quantum mechanics can be made complete in Einstein's sense, it cannot be done locally; this fact was demonstrated by John Stewart Bell with the formulation of Bell's inequality in 1964.
Post-revolution: Third stage
The argument of EPR
In 1935 Einstein, Boris Podolsky and Nathan Rosen developed an argument, published in the magazine Physical Review with the title Can Quantum-Mechanical Description of Physical Reality Be Considered Complete?,
based on an entangled state of two systems. Before coming to this
argument, it is necessary to formulate another hypothesis that comes out
of Einstein's work in relativity: the principle of locality. The elements of physical reality which are objectively possessed cannot be influenced instantaneously at a distance.
The argument of EPR was in 1957 picked up by David Bohm and Yakir Aharonov in a paper published in Physical Review with the title Discussion of Experimental Proof for the Paradox of Einstein, Rosen, and Podolsky. The authors reformulated the argument in terms of an entangled state of two particles, which can be summarized as follows:
1) Consider a system of two photons which at time t are located, respectively, in the spatially distant regions A and B and which are also in the entangled state of polarization described below:
2) At time t the photon in region A is tested for vertical
polarization. Suppose that the result of the measurement is that the
photon passes through the filter. According to the reduction of the wave
packet, the result is that, at time t + dt, the system becomes
3) At this point, the observer in A who carried out the first measurement on photon 1,
without doing anything else that could disturb the system or the other
photon ("assumption (R)", below), can predict with certainty that photon
2 will pass a test of vertical polarization. It follows that photon 2 possesses an element of physical reality: that of having a vertical polarization.
4) According to the assumption of locality, it cannot have been
the action carried out in A which created this element of reality for
photon 2. Therefore, we must conclude that the photon possessed the property of being able to pass the vertical polarization test before and independently of the measurement of photon 1.
5) At time t, the observer in A could have decided
to carry out a test of polarization at 45°, obtaining a certain result,
for example, that the photon passes the test. In that case, he could
have concluded that photon 2 turned out to be polarized at 45°. Alternatively, if the photon did not pass the test, he could have concluded that photon 2 turned out to be polarized at 135°. Combining one of these alternatives with the conclusion reached in 4, it seems that photon 2,
before the measurement took place, possessed both the property of being
able to pass with certainty a test of vertical polarization and the
property of being able to pass with certainty a test of polarization at
either 45° or 135°. These properties are incompatible according to the
formalism.
6) Since natural and obvious requirements have forced the conclusion that photon 2
simultaneously possesses incompatible properties, this means that, even
if it is not possible to determine these properties simultaneously and
with arbitrary precision, they are nevertheless possessed objectively by
the system. But quantum mechanics denies this possibility and it is
therefore an incomplete theory.
Bohr's response
Bohr's response to this argument was published, five months later than the original publication of EPR, in the same magazine Physical Review and with exactly the same title as the original. The crucial point of Bohr's answer is distilled in a passage which he later had republished in Paul Arthur Schilpp's book Albert Einstein, scientist-philosopher in honor of the seventieth birthday of Einstein. Bohr attacks assumption (R) of EPR by stating:
- The statement of the criterion in question is ambiguous with regard to the expression "without disturbing the system in any way". Naturally, in this case no mechanical disturbance of the system under examination can take place in the crucial stage of the process of measurement. But even in this stage there arises the essential problem of an influence on the precise conditions which define the possible types of prediction which regard the subsequent behaviour of the system...their arguments do not justify their conclusion that the quantum description turns out to be essentially incomplete...This description can be characterized as a rational use of the possibilities of an unambiguous interpretation of the process of measurement compatible with the finite and uncontrollable interaction between the object and the instrument of measurement in the context of quantum theory.
Post-revolution: Fourth stage
In his last writing on the topic,
Einstein further refined his position, making it completely clear that
what really disturbed him about the quantum theory was the problem of
the total renunciation of all minimal standards of realism, even at the
microscopic level, that the acceptance of the completeness of the theory
implied. Although the majority of experts in the field agree that Einstein was wrong, the current understanding is still not complete. There is no scientific consensus that determinism would have been refuted.