For many people, abortion is essentially a moral issue, concerning the commencement of human personhood, the rights of the fetus,
and a woman's rights over her own body. The debate has become a
political and legal issue in some countries with anti-abortion
campaigners seeking to enact, maintain and expand anti-abortion laws,
while abortion rights campaigners seeking the repeal or easing of such
laws while expanding access to abortion. Abortion laws vary considerably
between jurisdictions, ranging from outright prohibition of the
procedure to public funding of abortion. Availability of safe abortion
also varies across the world.
Overview
In ancient times, abortion, along with infanticide, was considered in the context of family planning, gender selection, population control, and the property rights of the patriarch. Rarely were the rights of the prospective mother, much less the prospective child, taken into consideration.
Although generally legal, the morality of abortion, birth control and
child abandonment (as a form of infanticide) was sometimes discussed.
Then, as now, these discussions often concerned the nature of man, the
existence of a soul, when life begins, and the beginning of human personhood.
While the practice of infanticide (as a form of family planning) has largely been eradicated in developed countries, birth control
and abortion are still practiced; and their morality and legality
continues to be debated. While modern debates about abortion retain some
of the language of these older debates, the terminology has often
acquired new meanings.
Discussion of the putative personhood of the fetus may be complicated by the current legal status of children. Like children or minors in the U.S., and unlike corporations,
a fetus or an embryo is not legally a "person", not having reached the
age of majority and not deemed able to enter into contracts and sue or
be sued. Since the 1860s, they have been treated as persons for the limited purposes of offence against the person
law in the UK including N. Ireland, although this treatment was amended
by the Abortion Act of 1967 in England, Scotland and Wales. Furthermore, there are logistic difficulties in treating a fetus as "the object of direct action." As one New Jersey Superior Court judge noted,
If a fetus is a person, it is a person in very special circumstances – it exists entirely within the body of another much larger person and usually cannot be the object of direct action by another person.
Proposals in the current debate range from complete prohibition, even if done to save the woman's life, to complete legalization with public funding, as in Canada.
Terminology
Many of the terms used in the debate are seen as political framing: terms used to validate one's own stance while invalidating the opposition's. For example, the labels "pro-choice" and "pro-life" imply endorsement of widely held values such as liberty or the right to life, while suggesting that the opposition must be "anti-choice" or "anti-life" (alternatively "pro-coercion" or "pro-death"). Terms used by some in the debate to describe their opponents include "pro-abortion" or "pro-abort". However, these terms do not always reflect a political view or fall along a binary; in one Public Religion Research Institute poll, seven in ten Americans described themselves as "pro-choice" while almost two-thirds described themselves as "pro-life". Another identifier in the debate is "abolitionist", which harks back to the 19th-century struggle against human slavery.
Some Native women have critiqued these terms as not representing their
views, as they do not see reproductive decisions as a choice but rather a
responsibility, and while they feel that life is sacred, they also see
abortion as, sometimes, a necessity.
Appeals are often made in the abortion debate to the rights of the fetus, pregnant woman, or other parties. Such appeals can generate confusion if the type of rights is not specified (whether civil, natural, or otherwise) or if it is simply assumed that the right appealed to takes precedence over all other competing rights (an example of begging the question).
The appropriate terms with which to designate the human organism prior to birth are also debated. The medical terms "embryo" and "fetus" are seen by some pro-life advocates as dehumanizing, while everyday terms such as "baby" are viewed as sentimental by some pro-choice advocates.
The use of the term "baby" to describe the unborn human organism
is seen by some scholars as part of an effort to assign the organism
agency. This assignation of agency functions to further the construction
of fetal personhood.
Political debate
Politics
refers to the processes, defined and limited through legal documents,
by which decisions (laws) are made in governments. In politics, rights
are the protections and privileges legally granted to citizens by the
government. In a democracy, certain rights are considered to be inalienable, and thus not subject to grant or withdrawal by government. Regarding abortion law, the political debate usually surrounds a right to privacy, and when or how a government may regulate abortion.
There is abundant debate regarding the extent of abortion regulation.
Some pro-choice advocates argue that it should be illegal for
governments to regulate abortion any more than other medical practices. On both sides of the debate, some argue that governments should be permitted to prohibit elective abortions after the 20th week, viability, or the second trimester. Some want to prohibit all abortions, starting from conception.
Privacy
Even though the right to privacy
is not explicitly stated in many constitutions of sovereign nations,
many people see it as foundational to a functioning democracy. In
general the right to privacy can be found to rest on the provisions of habeas corpus,
which first found official expression under Henry II in 11th century
England, but has precedent in Anglo-Saxon law. This provision guarantees
the right to freedom from arbitrary government interference, as well as
due process of law. This conception of the right to privacy is operant
in all countries which have adopted English common law through Acts of Reception. The Law of the United States rests on English common law by this means.
Time has stated that the issue of bodily privacy is "the core" of the abortion debate. Time defined privacy, in relation to abortion, as the ability of a woman to "decide what happens to her own body". In political terms, privacy can be understood as a condition in which one is not observed or disturbed by government.
Traditionally, American courts have located the right to privacy in the Fourth Amendment, Ninth Amendment, Fourteenth Amendment, as well as the penumbra of the Bill of Rights. The landmark decision Roe v Wade
relied on the 14th Amendment, which guarantees that federal rights
shall be applied equally to all persons born in the United States. The
14th Amendment has given rise to the doctrine of Substantive due process, which is said to guarantee various privacy rights, including the right to bodily integrity. In Canada, the courts have located privacy rights in the security of persons clause of the Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms. Section 7 of that charter echoes language used in the Universal Declaration of Human Rights, which also guarantees security of persons.
While governments are allowed to invade the privacy of their
citizens in some cases, they are expected to protect privacy in all
cases lacking a compelling state interest. In the US, the compelling state interest test has been developed in accordance with the standards of strict scrutiny. In Roe v Wade,
the Court decided that the state has an "important and legitimate
interest in protecting the potentiality of human life" from the point of
viability on, but that prior to viability, the woman's fundamental
rights are more compelling than that of the state.
U.S. judicial involvement
Roe v. Wade struck down state laws banning abortion in 1973. Over 20 cases have addressed abortion law in the United States, all of which upheld Roe v. Wade. Since Roe, abortion has been legal throughout the country, but states have placed varying regulations on it, from requiring parental involvement in a minor's abortion to restricting late-term abortions.
Legal criticisms of the Roe decision address many points, among them are several suggesting that it is an overreach of judicial powers, or that it was not properly based on the Constitution, or that it is an example of judicial activism and that it should be overturned so that abortion law can be decided by legislatures. Justice Potter Stewart, who joined with the majority, viewed the Roe opinion as "legislative" and asked that more consideration be paid to state legislatures.
Candidates competing for the Democratic nomination for the 2008 Presidential election cited Gonzales v. Carhart as judicial activism. In upholding the Partial-Birth Abortion Ban Act, Carhart is the first judicial opinion upholding a legal barrier to a specific abortion procedure.
"Where, in the performance of its judicial duties, the Court decides a case in such a way as to resolve the sort of intensely divisive controversy reflected in Roe and those rare, comparable cases, its [505 U.S. 833, 867] decision has a dimension that the resolution of the normal case does not carry. It is the dimension present whenever the Court's interpretation of the Constitution calls the contending sides of a national controversy to end their national division by accepting a common mandate rooted in the Constitution [...W]hatever the premises of opposition may be, only the most convincing justification under accepted standards of precedent could suffice to demonstrate that a later decision overruling the first was anything but a surrender to political pressure and an unjustified repudiation of the principle on which the Court staked its authority in the first instance." — Majority opinion of Planned Parenthood v. Casey.
"Quite to the contrary, by foreclosing all democratic outlet for the deep passions this issue arouses, by banishing the issue from the political forum that gives all participants, even the losers, the satisfaction of a fair hearing and an honest fight, by continuing the imposition of a rigid national rule instead of allowing for regional differences, the Court merely prolongs and intensifies the anguish [over abortion]." — Justice Antonin Scalia, "concurring in the judgment in part and dissenting in part".
Canadian judicial involvement
With R v. Morgentaler, the Supreme Court of Canada removed abortion from the Criminal Code. Relying on the security of person clause of the Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms,
the court stated that while the state has an interest in protecting the
fetus "at some point", this interest cannot override that of the
pregnant woman because: "the right to security of the person of a
pregnant woman was infringed more than was required to achieve the
objective of protecting the fetus, and the means were not reasonable."
The only laws currently governing abortion in Canada are those which
govern medical procedures in general, such as those regulating licensing
of facilities, the l training of medical personnel, and the like. Laws also exist
which are intended to prevent anti-abortion activists from interfering
with staff and patient access to hospitals and clinics, for instance by
creating buffer zones around them.
Because the courts did not specifically establish abortion as a
right, Parliament has leave to legislate on this aspect of the matter;
and in 1989, the Progressive Conservative government attempted to do
just that. A bill was introduced that would allow abortion only if two
doctors certified that the woman's health was in danger. This bill
passed the House of Commons but was defeated by a tie vote in the
Senate.
Several additional cases have considered further issues.
Although the courts have not ruled on the question of fetal personhood, the question has been raised in two cases, Tremblay v. Daigle and R. v. Sullivan. Both cases relied on the born alive rule, inherited from English common law, to determine that the fetus was not a person at law.
Two further cases are notable: Dobson (Litigation Guardian of) v. Dobson, and Winnipeg Child & Family Services (Northwest Area) v. G . (D.F.), [I9971 3 S.C.R. 925 M], which dismissed so-called fetal abuse charges.
Worldwide stances
Countries that refuse abortions
As
of June 2018, there are 5 countries that completely outlaw abortion: El
Salvador, the Vatican, Malta, the Dominican Republic, and Nicaragua.
This bans women from an abortion for any reason (underage, fetal
impairment, rape/incest), even if it might mean saving her life. All of these countries have a punishment if it is done illegally of jail time.
Countries with strict laws
Ireland
used to only allow abortions if the pregnancy is a risk to the woman's
life. It was also a very expensive procedure. The recent referendum
allowed abortions. There are also penalties of jail time if an abortion
is induced for any other reason.
China has a free abortion policy but for the reason of complying with
the one child policy - so many times it is forced upon them.
The Philippines also only have abortions in place to save the woman's
life but it is not stated in the law. This means that it is also
punishable by jail time.
Argentina allows abortion "only" in case of rape or mother's health at
risk. Argentina Senate has rejected bill to legalize abortion.
Effects of legalization/illegalization
Pro-choice advocates argue that illegalization of abortion increases the incidence of unsafe abortions, as the availability of professional abortion services decreases, and leads to increased maternal mortality. According to a global study collaboratively conducted by the World Health Organization and the Guttmacher Institute, most unsafe abortions occur where abortion is illegal.
The effect on crime of legalized abortion
is a subject of controversy, with proponents of the theory generally
arguing that "unwanted children" are more likely to become criminals and
that an inverse correlation is observed between the availability of
abortion and subsequent crime.
Economist George Akerlof
has argued that the legalization of abortion in the United States
contributed to a declining sense of paternal duty among biological
fathers and to a decline in shotgun weddings,
even when women chose childbirth over abortion, and thus to an increase
rather than a decrease in the rate of children born to unwed mothers.
Personhood
There are differences of opinion as to whether a zygote/embryo/fetus acquires "personhood" or was always a "person". If "personhood" is acquired, opinions differ about when this happens.
Traditionally, the concept of personhood entailed the soul, a metaphysical concept referring to a non-corporeal or extra-corporeal dimension of human being. Today, the concepts of subjectivity and intersubjectivity, personhood, mind, and self have come to encompass a number of aspects of human being previously considered the domain of the "soul". Thus, while the historical question has been: when does the soul enter the body,
in modern terms, the question could be put instead: at what point does
the developing individual develop personhood or selfhood.
Since the zygote is genetically identical to the embryo, the
fully formed fetus, and the baby, the notion of acquired personhood
could lead to an instance of the Sorites paradox, also known as the paradox of the heap.
Related issues attached to the question of the beginning of human
personhood include the legal status, bodily integrity, and subjectivity
of the pregnant woman
and the philosophical concept of "natality" (i.e. "the distinctively
human capacity to initiate a new beginning", which a new human life
embodies).
In the 1973 US judgment Roe v Wade, the opinion of the justices included the following statement:
"We need not resolve the difficult question of when life begins. When those trained in the respective disciplines of medicine, philosophy, and theology are unable to arrive at any consensus, the judiciary, at this point in the development of man's knowledge, is not in a position to speculate as to the answer."
Fetal pain
The existence and implications of fetal pain are part of a larger
debate about abortion. A 2005 multidisciplinary systematic review in JAMA in the area of fetal development found that a fetus is unlikely to feel pain until after the sixth month of pregnancy. Developmental neurobiologists suspect that the establishment of thalamocortical connections (at about 26 weeks) may be critical to fetal perception of pain.
However, legislation was proposed by anti-abortion advocates that would
require abortion providers to tell a woman that the fetus may feel pain
during an abortion procedure.
The 2005 JAMA review concluded that data from dozens of
medical reports and studies indicate that fetuses are unlikely to feel
pain until the third trimester of pregnancy. However a number of medical critics have since disputed these conclusions.
Other researchers such as Anand and Fisk have challenged the idea that
pain cannot be felt before 26 weeks, positing instead that pain can be
felt at around 20 weeks.
Anand's suggestion is disputed in a March 2010 report on fetal
awareness published by a working party of the Royal College of
Obstetricians and Gynaecologists, citing a lack of evidence or
rationale.
Page 20 of the report definitively states that the fetus cannot feel
pain prior to week 24. Because pain can involve sensory, emotional and
cognitive factors, leaving it "impossible to know" when painful
experiences are perceived, even if it is known when thalamocortical
connections are established.
Wendy Savage—press officer, Doctors for a Woman's Choice on
Abortion—considers the question to be irrelevant. In a 1997 letter to
the British Medical Journal,
she noted that the majority of surgical abortions in Britain were
performed under general anesthesia which affects the fetus, and
considers the discussion "to be unhelpful to women and to the scientific
debate." Others caution against unnecessary use of fetal anesthetic
during abortion, as it poses potential health risks to the pregnant
woman.
David Mellor and colleagues have noted that the fetal brain is already
awash in naturally occurring chemicals that keep it sedated and
anesthetized until birth.
At least one anesthesia researcher has suggested the fetal pain
legislation may make abortions harder to obtain because abortion clinics
lack the equipment and expertise to supply fetal anesthesia. Anesthesia
is administered directly to fetuses only while they are undergoing
surgery.
Fetal personhood
Although the two main sides of the abortion debate tend to agree that
a human fetus is biologically and genetically human (that is, of the
human species), they often differ in their view on whether or not a
human fetus is, in any of various ways, a person. Pro-life supporters argue that abortion is morally wrong on the basis that a fetus is an innocent human person or because a fetus is a potential life that will, in most cases, develop into a fully functional human being. They believe that a fetus is a person upon conception. Others reject this position by drawing a distinction between human being and human person, arguing that while the fetus is innocent and biologically human, it is not a person with a right to life. In support of this distinction, some propose a list of criteria as markers of personhood. For example, Mary Ann Warren suggests consciousness (at least the capacity to feel pain), reasoning, self-motivation, the ability to communicate, and self-awareness.
According to Warren, a being need not exhibit all of these criteria to
qualify as a person with a right to life, but if a being exhibits none
of them (or perhaps only one), then it is certainly not a person.
Warren concludes that as the fetus satisfies only one criterion,
consciousness (and this only after it becomes susceptible to pain),
the fetus is not a person and abortion is therefore morally
permissible. Other philosophers apply similar criteria, concluding that
a fetus lacks a right to life because it lacks brain waves or higher brain function, self-consciousness, rationality, and autonomy. These lists diverge over precisely which features confer a right to life, but tend to propose various developed psychological or physiological features not found in fetuses.
Critics of this typically argue that some of the proposed criteria for personhood would disqualify two classes of born human beings – reversibly comatose
patients, and human infants – from having a right to life, since they,
like fetuses, are not self-conscious, do not communicate, and so on. Defenders of the proposed criteria may respond that the reversibly comatose do satisfy the relevant criteria because they "retain all their unconscious mental states" or at least some higher brain function (brain waves). Warren concedes that infants are not "persons" by her proposed criteria, and on that basis she and others, including the moral philosopher Peter Singer, conclude that infanticide could be morally acceptable under some circumstances (for example if the infant is severely disabled or in order to save the lives of several other infants.)
Critics may see such concessions as an indication that the right to
life cannot be adequately defined by reference to developed
psychological featured.
An alternative approach is to base personhood or the right to life on a being's natural or inherent capacities. On this approach, a being essentially has a right to life if it has a natural capacity
to develop the relevant psychological features; and, since human beings
do have this natural capacity, they essentially have a right to life
beginning at conception (or whenever they come into existence).
Critics of this position argue that mere genetic potential is not a
plausible basis for respect (or for the right to life), and that basing a
right to life on natural capacities would lead to the counterintuitive
position that anencephalic infants, irreversibly comatose patients, and brain-dead patients kept alive on a medical ventilator, are all persons with a right to life.
Respondents to this criticism argue that the noted human cases in fact
would not be classified as persons as they do not have a natural
capacity to develop any psychological features. Also, in a view that favors benefiting even unconceived but potential future persons, it has been argued as justified to abort an unintended pregnancy in favor for conceiving a new child later in better conditions.
Philosophers such as Aquinas use the concept of individuation. They argue that abortion is not permissible from the point at which individual human identity is realized. Anthony Kenny
argues that this can be derived from everyday beliefs and language and
one can legitimately say "if my mother had had an abortion six months
into her pregnancy, she would have killed me" then one can reasonably
infer that at six months the "me" in question would have been an
existing person with a valid claim to life. Since division of the zygote
into twins through the process of monozygotic twinning
can occur until the fourteenth day of pregnancy, Kenny argues that
individual identity is obtained at this point and thus abortion is not
permissible after two weeks.
Arguments for abortion rights which do not depend on fetal non-personhood
Bodily rights
An argument first presented by Judith Jarvis Thomson states that even if
the fetus is a person and has a right to life, abortion is morally
permissible because a woman has a right to control her own body and its
life-support functions. Thomson's variant of this argument draws an
analogy between forcing a woman to continue an unwanted pregnancy and
forcing a person to allow his body to be used to maintain blood homeostasis (as a dialysis machine is used) for another person suffering from kidney failure.
It is argued that just as it would be permissible to "unplug" and
thereby cause the death of the person who is using one's kidneys, so it
is permissible to abort the fetus (who similarly, it is said, has no
right to use one's body's life-support functions against one's will).
Critics of this argument generally argue that there are morally
relevant disanalogies between abortion and the kidney failure scenario.
For example, it is argued that the fetus is the woman's child as
opposed to a mere stranger; that abortion kills the fetus rather than merely letting it die;
and that in the case of pregnancy arising from voluntary intercourse,
the woman has either tacitly consented to the fetus using her body, or has a duty to allow it to use her body since she herself is responsible for its need to use her body.
Some writers defend the analogy against these objections, arguing that
the disanalogies are morally irrelevant or do not apply to abortion in
the way critics have claimed.
Alternative scenarios have been put forth as more accurate and
realistic representations of the moral issues present in abortion. John Noonan
proposes the scenario of a family who was found to be liable for
frostbite finger loss suffered by a dinner guest whom they refused to
allow to stay overnight, although it was very cold outside and the guest
showed signs of being sick. It is argued that just as it would not be
permissible to refuse temporary accommodation for the guest to protect
him from physical harm, it would not be permissible to refuse temporary
accommodation of a fetus.
Other critics claim that there is a difference between artificial
and extraordinary means of preservation, such as medical treatment,
kidney dialysis, and blood transfusions, and normal and natural means of
preservation, such as gestation, childbirth, and breastfeeding. They
argue that if a baby was born into an environment in which there was no
replacement available for her mother's breast milk, and the baby would
either breastfeed or starve, the mother would have to allow the baby to
breastfeed. But the mother would never have to give the baby a blood
transfusion, no matter what the circumstances were. The difference
between breastfeeding in that scenario and blood transfusions is the
difference between using your body as a kidney dialysis machine, and
gestation and childbirth.
Freedom and equality
Margaret
Sanger wrote: "No woman can call herself free until she can choose
consciously whether she will or will not be a mother." From this
perspective the right to abortion can be construed to be necessary in
order for women to achieve equality with men whose freedom is not nearly
so restricted by having children.
Impacts of criminalization
Some activists and academics, such as Andrea Smith,
argue that the criminalization of abortion furthers the marginalization
of oppressed groups such as poor women and women of color. Sending
these women into the prison system would do nothing to address the
social/political/economic problems that marginalize these women or,
sometimes, cause them to require abortions.
Abortion safety
Even
where abortions are illegal, some do take place. However, they are
generally done unsafely, both because the need for secrecy tends to be
more important than the woman's safety, and due to the lack of training
and experience the doctor performing the abortion. When done correctly
by properly trained doctors, abortion is generally safe.
Arguments against the right to abortion
Discrimination
The book Abortion and the Conscience of the Nation presents the argument that abortion involves unjust discrimination against the unborn. According to this argument, those who deny that fetuses have a right to life do not value all
human life, but instead select arbitrary characteristics (such as
particular levels of physical or psychological development) as giving
some human beings more value or rights than others.
In contrast, philosophers who define the right to life by
reference to particular levels of physical or psychological development
typically maintain that such characteristics are morally relevant, and reject the assumption that all human life necessarily has value (or that membership in the species Homo sapiens is in itself morally relevant).
Deprivation
The argument of deprivation states that abortion is morally wrong because it deprives the fetus of a valuable future. On this account, killing an adult human being is wrong because it deprives the victim of a future like ours—a future containing highly valuable or desirable experiences, activities, projects, and enjoyments.
If a being has such a future, then (according to the argument) killing
that being would seriously harm it and hence would be seriously wrong.
But since a fetus does have such a future, the "overwhelming majority"
of deliberate abortions are placed in the "same moral category" as
killing an innocent adult human being. Not all
abortions are unjustified according to this argument: abortion would be
justified if the same justification could be applied to killing an
adult human.
Criticism of this line of reasoning follows several threads. Some reject the argument on grounds relating to personal identity, holding that the fetus is not the same entity as the adult into which it will develop, and thus that the fetus does not have a "future like ours" in the required sense.
Others grant that the fetus has a future like ours, but argue that
being deprived of this future is not a significant harm or a significant
wrong to the fetus, because there are relatively few psychological connections (continuations of memory, belief, desire and the like) between the fetus as it is now and the adult into which it will develop. Another criticism is that the argument creates inequalities in the wrongness of killing:
as the futures of some people appear to be far more valuable or
desirable than the futures of other people, the argument appears to
entail that some killings are far more wrong than others, or that some people have a far stronger right to life than others—a conclusion that is taken to be counterintuitive or unacceptable.
Argument from uncertainty
Some
pro-life supporters argue that if there is uncertainty as to whether
the fetus has a right to life, then having an abortion is equivalent to
consciously taking the risk of killing another. According to this
argument, if it is not known for certain whether something (such as the
fetus) has a right to life, then it is reckless, and morally wrong, to
treat that thing as if it lacks a right to life (for example by killing it). This would place abortion in the same moral category as manslaughter (if it turns out that the fetus has a right to life) or certain forms of criminal negligence (if it turns out that the fetus does not have a right to life).
David Boonin replies that if this kind of argument were correct,
then the killing of nonhuman animals and plants would also be morally
wrong, because (Boonin contends) it is not known for certain that such
beings lack a right to life.
Boonin also argues that arguments from uncertainty fail because the
mere fact that one might be mistaken in finding certain arguments
persuasive (for example, arguments for the claim that the fetus lacks a
right to life) does not mean that one should act contrary to those
arguments or assume them to be mistaken.
Religious beliefs
Each religion has many varying views on the moral implications of
abortion. These views can often be in direct opposition to each other. Muslims regard abortion as haram
meaning forbidden. Muslims typically cite the Quranic verse 17:31 which
states that a fetus shouldn't be aborted out of fear of poverty. Christians who oppose abortion may support their views with Scripture references such as that of Luke 1:15; Jeremiah 1:4–5; Genesis 25:21–23; Matthew 1:18; and Psalm 139:13–16. The Catholic Church believes that human life begins at conception as does the right to life; thus, abortion is considered immoral. The Church of England
also considers abortion to be morally wrong, though their position
admits abortion when "the continuance of a pregnancy threatens the life
of the mother".
Other factors
Mexico City policy
The Mexico City policy—also known as the "global gag rule"—required
any non-governmental organization receiving U.S. government funding to
refrain from performing or promoting abortion services in other
countries. This had a significant effect on the health policies of many
nations across the globe. The Mexico City policy was instituted under President Reagan, suspended under President Clinton, reinstated by President George W. Bush, and suspended again by President Barack Obama on 24 January 2009 and re-instated once again by President Donald J. Trump on 23 January 2017.
Public opinion
A number of opinion polls around the world have explored public
opinion regarding the issue of abortion. Results have varied from poll
to poll, country to country, and region to region, while varying with
regard to different aspects of the issue.
A May 2005 survey examined attitudes toward abortion in 10
European countries, asking respondents whether they agreed with the
statement, "If a woman doesn't want children, she should be allowed to
have an abortion". The highest level of approval was 81% (in the Czech
Republic); the lowest was 47% (in Poland).
In North America, a December 2001 poll surveyed Canadian opinion on abortion,
asking in what circumstances they believe abortion should be permitted;
32% responded that they believe abortion should be legal in all
circumstances, 52% that it should be legal in certain circumstances, and
14% that it should be legal in no circumstances. A similar poll in
April 2009 surveyed people in the United States about U.S. opinion on abortion;
18% said that abortion should be "legal in all cases", 28% said that
abortion should be "legal in most cases", 28% said abortion should be
"illegal in most cases" and 16% said abortion should be "illegal in all
cases". A November 2005 poll in Mexico found that 73.4% think abortion should not be legalized while 11.2% think it should.
Of attitudes in South America, a December 2003 survey found that 30% of Argentines thought that abortion in Argentina
should be allowed "regardless of situation", 47% that it should be
allowed "under some circumstances", and 23% that it should not be
allowed "regardless of situation".
A more recent poll now suggest that 45% of Argentineans are in favor of
abortion for any reason in the first twelve weeks. This same poll
conducted in September 2011 also suggests that most Argentineans favor
abortion being legal when a woman's health or life is at risk (81%),
when the pregnancy is a result of rape (80%) or the fetus has severe
abnormalities (68%). A March 2007 poll regarding the abortion law in Brazil
found that 65% of Brazilians believe that it "should not be modified",
16% that it should be expanded "to allow abortion in other cases", 10%
that abortion should be "decriminalized", and 5% were "not sure". A July 2005 poll in Colombia
found that 65.6% said they thought that abortion should remain illegal,
26.9% that it should be made legal, and 7.5% that they were unsure.
Effect upon crime rate
A theory attempts to draw a correlation between the United States'
unprecedented nationwide decline of the overall crime rate during the
1990s and the decriminalization of abortion 20 years prior.
The suggestion was brought to widespread attention by a 1999 academic paper, The Impact of Legalized Abortion on Crime, authored by the economists Steven D. Levitt
and John Donohue. They attributed the drop in crime to a reduction in
individuals said to have a higher statistical probability of committing
crimes: unwanted children, especially those born to mothers who are
African American, impoverished, adolescent, uneducated, and single.
The change coincided with what would have been the adolescence, or peak
years of potential criminality, of those who had not been born as a
result of Roe v. Wade
and similar cases. Donohue and Levitt's study also noted that states
which legalized abortion before the rest of the nation experienced the
lowering crime rate pattern earlier, and those with higher abortion
rates had more pronounced reductions.
Fellow economists Christopher Foote and Christopher Goetz
criticized the methodology in the Donohue-Levitt study, noting a lack of
accommodation for statewide yearly variations such as cocaine use, and
recalculating based on incidence of crime per capita; they found no statistically significant results. Levitt and Donohue responded to this by presenting an adjusted data set
which took into account these concerns and reported that the data
maintained the statistical significance of their initial paper.
Such research has been criticized by some as being utilitarian, discriminatory as to race and socioeconomic class, and as promoting eugenics as a solution to crime. Levitt states in his book Freakonomics that they are neither promoting nor negating any course of action—merely reporting data as economists.
Breast cancer hypothesis
The abortion–breast cancer hypothesis posits that induced abortion increases the risk of developing breast cancer. This position contrasts with the scientific consensus that abortion does not cause breast cancer.
In early pregnancy, levels of estrogen increase, leading to breast growth in preparation for lactation.
The hypothesis proposes that if this process is interrupted by an
abortion – before full maturity in the third trimester – then more
relatively vulnerable immature cells could be left than there were prior
to the pregnancy, resulting in a greater potential risk of breast
cancer. The hypothesis mechanism was first proposed and explored in rat
studies conducted in the 1980s.
Minors
Many states require some form of parental consent before the abortion
is set to happen. In the United States, 37 states require the parent to
have knowledge while only 21 of those states need one parent to
consent.
Certain states have an alternative answer to the involvement of the
parent by getting the judicial system involved with a judicial bypass.
In those states, minors can get permission from the judge if parents are
not willing to do so or if they are absent from their lives.
These laws are known as parental involvement laws.
There are different guidelines to minors and abortions in every
country. In most of Europe, all persons that are capable of judgment
enjoy medical privacy
and can decide medical matters on their own. Capability of judgment
does not come at a defined age, however, and is dependent on how well
the person is able to understand the decision and its consequences. For
most medical procedures, capability of judgment usually sets in at ages
12 to 14.