In philosophy, ideas are usually taken as mental representational images of some object. Ideas can also be abstract concepts that do not present as mental images. Many philosophers have considered ideas to be a fundamental ontological category of being. The capacity to create and understand the meaning of ideas is considered to be an essential and defining feature of human beings. In a popular sense, an idea arises in a reflexive, spontaneous manner, even without thinking or serious reflection, for example, when we talk about the idea of a person or a place. A new or original idea can often lead to innovation.
Etymology
Innate and adventitious ideas
One view on the nature of ideas is that there exist some ideas (called innate ideas) which are so general and abstract that they could not have arisen as a representation of an object of our perception but rather were in some sense always present. These are distinguished from adventitious ideas which are images or concepts which are accompanied by the judgment that they are caused or occasioned by an external object.
Another view holds that we only discover ideas in the same way
that we discover the real world, from personal experiences. The view
that humans acquire all or almost all their behavioral traits from nurture (life experiences) is known as tabula rasa
("blank slate"). Most of the confusions in the way ideas arise is at
least in part due to the use of the term "idea" to cover both the
representation perceptics and the object of conceptual thought. This can
be always illustrated in terms of the scientific doctrines of innate ideas, "concrete ideas versus abstract ideas", as well as "simple ideas versus complex ideas".
Philosophy
Plato
Plato in Ancient Greece
was one of the earliest philosophers to provide a detailed discussion
of ideas and of the thinking process (it must be noted that in Plato's
Greek the word idea carries a rather different sense from our modern English term). Plato argued in dialogues such as the Phaedo, Symposium, Republic, and Timaeus that there is a realm of ideas or forms (eidei),
which exist independently of anyone who may have thoughts on these
ideas, and it is the ideas which distinguish mere opinion from
knowledge, for unlike material things which are transient and liable to
contrary properties, ideas are unchanging and nothing but just what they
are. Consequently, Plato seems to assert forcefully that material
things can only be the objects of opinion; real knowledge can only be
had of unchanging ideas. Furthermore, ideas for Plato appear to serve as
universals; consider the following passage from the Republic:
We both assert that there are," I said, "and distinguish in speech, many fair things, many good things, and so on for each kind of thing."
"Yes, so we do."
"And we also assert that there is a fair itself, a good itself, and so on for all things that we set down as many. Now, again, we refer to them as one idea of each as though the idea were one; and we address it as that which really is."
"That's so."
"And, moreover, we say that the former are seen, but not intellected, while the ideas are intellected but not seen.
— Plato, Bk. VI 507b-c
René Descartes
Descartes often wrote of the meaning of idea as an image or representation, often but not necessarily "in the mind", which was well known in the vernacular.
Despite that Descartes is usually credited with the invention of the
non-Platonic use of the term, he at first followed this vernacular use.b In his Meditations on First Philosophy
he says, "Some of my thoughts are like images of things, and it is to
these alone that the name 'idea' properly belongs." He sometimes
maintained that ideas were innate and uses of the term idea
diverge from the original primary scholastic use. He provides multiple
non-equivalent definitions of the term, uses it to refer to as many as
six distinct kinds of entities, and divides ideas inconsistently into various genetic categories. For him knowledge took the form of ideas and philosophical investigation is the deep consideration of these entities.
John Locke
In striking contrast to Plato's use of idea is that of John Locke. In his Introduction to An Essay Concerning Human Understanding, Locke defines idea
as "that term which, I think, serves best to stand for whatsoever is
the object of the understanding when a man thinks, I have used it to
express whatever is meant by phantasm, notion, species, or whatever it
is which the mind can be employed about in thinking; and I could not
avoid frequently using it." He said he regarded the book necessary to examine our own abilities and
see what objects our understandings were, or were not, fitted to deal
with. In his philosophy other outstanding figures followed in his
footsteps — Hume and Kant in the 18th century, Arthur Schopenhauer in the 19th century, and Bertrand Russell, Ludwig Wittgenstein, and Karl Popper in the 20th century. Locke always believed in good sense
— not pushing things to extremes and on taking fully into account the
plain facts of the matter. He considered his common-sense ideas
"good-tempered, moderate, and down-to-earth."
As John Locke studied humans in his work “An Essay Concerning
Human Understanding” he continually referenced Descartes for ideas as he
asked this fundamental question: “When we are concerned with something
about which we have no certain knowledge, what rules or standards should
guide how confident we allow ourselves to be that our opinions are
right?” A simpler way of putting it is how do humans know ideas, and what are
the different types of ideas. An idea to Locke “can simply mean some
sort of brute experience.” He shows that there are “No innate principles in the mind.”. Thus, he concludes that “our ideas are all experiential in nature.” An experience can either be a sensation or a reflection: “consider
whether there are any innate ideas in the mind before any are brought in
by the impression from sensation or reflection.” Therefore, an idea was an experience in which the human mind apprehended something.
In a Lockean view, there are really two types of ideas: complex
and simple. Simple ideas are the building blocks for much more complex
ideas, and “While the mind is wholly passive in the reception of simple
ideas, it is very active in the building of complex ideas…”
Complex ideas, therefore, can either be modes, substances, or
relations. Modes are when ideas are combined in order to convey new
information. For instance, David Banach gives the example of beauty as a mode. He says that it is the
combination of color and form. Substances, however, is different.
Substances are certain objects, that can either be dogs, cats, or
tables. And relations represent the relationship between two or more
ideas. In this way, Locke did, in fact, answer his own questions about
ideas and humans.
David Hume
Hume differs from Locke by limiting idea to the more or less vague mental reconstructions of perceptions, the perceptual process being described as an "impression."
Hume shared with Locke the basic empiricist premise that it is only
from life experiences (whether their own or others') that humans'
knowledge of the existence of anything outside of themselves can be
ultimately derived, that they shall carry on doing what they are
prompted to do by their emotional drives of varying kinds. In choosing
the means to those ends, they shall follow their accustomed associations
of ideas.d Hume has contended and defended the notion that "reason alone is merely the 'slave of the passions'."
Immanuel Kant
Immanuel Kant defines an idea as opposed to a concept. "Regulative ideas" are ideals that one must tend towards, but by definition may not be completely realized. Liberty, according to Kant, is an idea. The autonomy of the rational and universal subject is opposed to the determinism of the empirical subject.
Kant felt that it is precisely in knowing its limits that philosophy
exists. The business of philosophy he thought was not to give rules, but
to analyze the private judgements of good common sense.e
Rudolf Steiner
Whereas Kant declares limits to knowledge ("we can never know the thing in itself"), in his epistemological work, Rudolf Steiner sees ideas as "objects of experience" which the mind apprehends, much as the eye apprehends light. In Goethean Science
(1883), he declares, "Thinking ... is no more and no less an organ of
perception than the eye or ear. Just as the eye perceives colors and the
ear sounds, so thinking perceives ideas." He holds this to be the
premise upon which Goethe made his natural-scientific observations.
Wilhelm Wundt
Wundt widens the term from Kant's usage to include conscious representation of some object or process of the external world. In so doing, he includes not only ideas of memory and imagination, but also perceptual processes, whereas other psychologists confine the term to the first two groups. One of Wundt's main concerns was to investigate conscious processes in their own context by experiment and introspection. He regarded both of these as exact methods,
interrelated in that experimentation created optimal conditions for
introspection. Where the experimental method failed, he turned to other objectively valuable aids, specifically to those
products of cultural communal life which lead one to infer particular
mental motives. Outstanding among these are speech, myth, and social
custom. Wundt designed the basic mental activity apperception
— a unifying function which should be understood as an activity of the
will. Many aspects of his empirical physiological psychology are used
today. One is his principles of mutually enhanced contrasts and of assimilation and dissimilation (i.e. in color and form perception and his advocacy of objective
methods of expression and of recording results, especially in language.
Another is the principle of heterogony of ends — that multiply
motivated acts lead to unintended side effects which in turn become
motives for new actions.
Charles Sanders Peirce
C. S. Peirce published the first full statement of pragmatism in his important works "How to Make Our Ideas Clear" (1878) and "The Fixation of Belief" (1877). In "How to Make Our Ideas Clear" he proposed that a clear idea (in his study he uses concept and idea
as synonymic) is defined as one, when it is apprehended such as it will
be recognized wherever it is met, and no other will be mistaken for it.
If it fails of this clearness, it is said to be obscure. He argued that
to understand an idea clearly we should ask ourselves what difference
its application would make to our evaluation of a proposed solution to
the problem at hand. Pragmatism
(a term he appropriated for use in this context), he defended, was a
method for ascertaining the meaning of terms (as a theory of meaning).
The originality of his ideas is in their rejection of what was accepted
as a view and understanding of knowledge by scientists for some 250
years, i.e. that, he pointed, knowledge was an impersonal fact. Peirce
contended that we acquire knowledge as participants, not as spectators.
He felt "the real", sooner or later, is information acquired through
ideas and knowledge with the application of logical reasoning would
finally result in. He also published many papers on logic in relation to
ideas.
G. F. Stout and J. M. Baldwin
G. F. Stout and J. M. Baldwin, in the Dictionary of Philosophy and Psychology, define idea as "the reproduction with a more or less adequate image, of an object not actually present to the senses."
They point out that an idea and a perception are by various authorities
contrasted in various ways. "Difference in degree of intensity",
"comparative absence of bodily movement on the part of the subject",
"comparative dependence on mental activity", are suggested by
psychologists as characteristic of an idea as compared with a perception.
It should be observed that an idea, in the narrower and generally
accepted sense of a mental reproduction, is frequently composite. That
is, as in the example given above of the idea of a chair, a great many
objects, differing materially in detail, all call a single idea. When a
man, for example, has obtained an idea of chairs in general by
comparison with which he can say "This is a chair, that is a stool", he
has what is known as an "abstract idea" distinct from the reproduction
in his mind of any particular chair.
Furthermore, a complex idea may not have any corresponding physical
object, though its particular constituent elements may severally be the
reproductions of actual perceptions. Thus the idea of a centaur is a complex mental picture composed of the ideas of man and horse, that of a mermaid of a woman and a fish.
In anthropology and the social sciences
Diffusion
studies explore the spread of ideas from culture to culture. Some
anthropological theories hold that all cultures imitate ideas from one
or a few original cultures, the Adam of the Bible, or several cultural
circles that overlap. Evolutionary diffusion theory holds that cultures
are influenced by one another but that similar ideas can be developed in
isolation.
In the mid-20th century, social scientists began to study how and why ideas spread from one person or culture to another. Everett Rogers pioneered diffusion of innovations studies, using research to prove factors in adoption and profiles of adopters of ideas. In 1976, in his book The Selfish Gene, Richard Dawkins suggested applying biological evolutionary theories to the spread of ideas. He coined the term meme to describe an abstract unit of selection, equivalent to the gene in evolutionary biology.
Semantics
Samuel Johnson
James Boswell recorded Samuel Johnson's opinion about ideas. Johnson claimed that they are mental images or internal visual pictures. As such, they have no relation to words or the concepts which are designated by verbal names.
He was particularly indignant against the almost universal use of the word idea in the sense of notion or opinion when it is clear that idea can only signify something of which an image can be formed in the mind. We may have an idea or image of a mountain, a tree, a building; but we cannot surely have an idea or image of an argument or proposition. Yet we hear the sages of the law 'delivering their ideas upon the question under consideration;' and the first speakers in parliament 'entirely coinciding with the idea which has been ably stated by an honourable member;' — or 'reprobating an idea unconstitutional, and fraught with the most dangerous consequences to a great and free country.' Johnson called this 'modern cant.'
— Boswell's Life of Johnson, Tuesday, 23 September 1777
Relationship of ideas to modern legal time- and scope-limited monopolies
Relationship between ideas and patents
On susceptibility to exclusive property
It has been pretended by some, (and in England especially,) that inventors have a natural and exclusive right to their inventions, and not merely for their own lives, but inheritable to their heirs. But while it is a moot question whether the origin of any kind of property is derived from nature at all, it would be singular to admit a natural and even a hereditary right to inventors. It is agreed by those who have seriously considered the subject, that no individual has, of natural right, a separate property in an acre of land, for instance.
By a universal law, indeed, whatever, whether fixed or movable, belongs to all men equally and in common, is the property for the moment of him who occupies it, but when he relinquishes the occupation, the property goes with it. Stable ownership is the gift of social law and is given late in the progress of society. It would be curious then, if an idea, the fugitive fermentation of an individual brain, could, of natural right, be claimed an exclusive and stable property.
If nature has made any one thing less susceptible than all others of exclusive property, it is the action of the thinking power called an idea, which an individual may exclusively possess as long as he keeps it to himself; but the moment it is divulged, it forces itself into the possession of every one, and the receiver cannot dispossess himself of it. Its peculiar character, too, is that no one possesses the less, because every other possesses the whole of it. He, who receives an idea from me, receives instruction himself without lessening mine; as he who lights his taper at my mine, receives light without darkening me.
Those ideas should freely spread from one to another over the globe, for the moral and mutual instruction of man, and improvement of his condition, seems to have been peculiarly and benevolently designed by nature, when she made them, like fire, expansible over all space, without lessening their density in any point, and like the air in which we breathe, move, and have our physical being, incapable of confinement or exclusive appropriation. Inventions then cannot, in nature, be a subject of property.
Society may give an exclusive right to the profits arising from them, as an encouragement to men to pursue ideas which may produce utility, but this may or may not be done, according to the will and convenience of the society, without claim or complaint from anybody. Accordingly, it is a fact, as far as I am informed, that England was, until we copied her, the only country on earth which ever, by a general law, gave a legal right to the exclusive use of an idea. In some other countries it is sometimes done, in a great case, and by a special and personal act but, generally speaking, other nations have thought that these monopolies produce more embarrassment than advantage to society.
— Thomas Jefferson, letter to Isaac McPherson, 13 August 1813
To protect the cause of invention and innovation, the legal constructions of Copyrights and Patents were established. Patent
law regulates various aspects related to the functional manifestation
of inventions based on new ideas or incremental improvements to existing
ones. Thus, patents have a direct relationship to ideas.
Relationship between ideas and copyrights
In some cases, authors can be granted limited legal monopolies on the manner in which certain works are expressed. This is known colloquially as copyright, although the term intellectual property is used mistakenly in place of copyright.
Copyright law regulating the aforementioned monopolies generally does
not cover the actual ideas. The law does not bestow the legal status of property
upon ideas per se. Instead, laws purport to regulate events related to
the usage, copying, production, sale and other forms of exploitation of
the fundamental expression of a work, that may or may not carry ideas.
Copyright law is fundamentally different from patent law in this respect: patents do grant monopolies on ideas (more on this below).
A copyright is meant to regulate some aspects of the usage of expressions of a work, not an idea. Thus, copyrights have a negative relationship to ideas.
Work means a tangible medium of expression. It may be an original
or derivative work of art, be it literary, dramatic, musical
recitation, artistic, related to sound recording, etc. In (at least)
countries adhering to the Berne Convention, copyright automatically
starts covering the work upon the original creation and fixation
thereof, without any extra steps. While creation usually involves an
idea, the idea in itself does not suffice for the purposes of claiming
copyright.
Relationship of ideas to confidentiality agreements
Confidentiality and nondisclosure agreements
are legal instruments that assist corporations and individuals in
keeping ideas from escaping to the general public. Generally, these
instruments are covered by contract law.