Criticism of Marxism has come from various political ideologies and academic disciplines. This include general criticism about a lack of internal consistency, criticism related to historical materialism, that it is a type of historical determinism, the necessity of suppression of individual rights, issues with the implementation of communism and economic issues such as the distortion or absence of price signals and reduced incentives. In addition, empirical and epistemological problems are frequently identified.
General criticism
Democratic socialists and social democrats reject the idea that societies can achieve socialism only through class conflict and a proletarian revolution. Many anarchists reject the need for a transitory state phase. Some thinkers have rejected the fundamentals of Marxist theory such as historical materialism and the labour theory of value and have gone on to criticise capitalism and advocate socialism using other arguments.
Some contemporary supporters of Marxism see many aspects of
Marxist thought as viable, but they contend that the corpus is
incomplete or somewhat outdated in regard to certain aspects of
economic, political or social theory. They may therefore combine some
Marxist concepts with the ideas of other theorists such as Max Weber—the Frankfurt School provides one example of this approach.
Historian Paul Johnson
wrote: "The truth is, even the most superficial inquiry into Marx's use
of evidence forces one to treat with skepticism everything he wrote
which relies on factual data". For example, Johnson stated: "The whole
of the key Chapter Eight of Capital is a deliberate and systematic
falsification to prove a thesis which an objective examination of the
facts showed was untenable".
Historical materialism
Historical materialism remains one of the intellectual bases of Marxism. It proposes that technological advances in modes of production inevitably lead to changes in the social relations of production. This economic "base" of society supports, is reflected by and influences the ideological "superstructure" which encompasses culture, religion, politics, and all other aspects of humanity's social consciousness.
It thus looks for the causes of developments and changes in human
history in economic, technological and, more broadly, material factors
as well as the clashes of material interests among tribes, social
classes, and nations. Law, politics, the arts, literature, morality and
religion are understood by Marx to make up the superstructure as
reflections of the economic base of society. Many critics have argued
that this is an oversimplification of the nature of society and claim
that the influence of ideas, culture and other aspects of what Marx
called the superstructure are just as important as the economic base to
the course of society, if not more so. However, Marxism does not claim
that the economic base of society is the only determining element in
society as demonstrated by the following letter written by Friedrich Engels, Marx's long-time contributor:
According to the materialist conception of history, the ultimately determining element in history is the production and reproduction of real life. More than this neither Marx nor I ever asserted. Hence if somebody twists this into saying that the economic element is the only determining one he transforms that proposition into a meaningless, abstract, senseless phrase.
However, this also creates another problem for Marxism. If the
superstructure also influences the base then there is no need for Marx's
constant assertions that the history of society is one of economic
class conflict. This then becomes a classic chicken or the egg argument as to whether the base or the superstructure comes first. Peter Singer
proposes that the way to solve this problem is to understand that Marx
saw the economic base as ultimately real. Marx believed that humanity's
defining characteristic was its means of production
and thus the only way for man to free himself from oppression was for
him to take control of the means of production. According to Marx, this
is the goal of history and the elements of the superstructure act as
tools of history.
Even if Singer's interpretation of Marx's intuitions on the "goal of
history" is faithful to Marx's original intent, that still would not
make this viewpoint necessarily true.
Murray Rothbard criticized historical materialism as well, arguing that Marx claimed the "base"
of society (its technology and social relations) determined its
"consciousness" in the superstructure, yet, building on the arguments of
Ludwig von Mises, Rothbard observes it is human consciousness which
drives the development of technology and social relations. Rothbard
argues that Marx ignores how the base arises, which obscures that the
true causal path is from the superstructure to the base, as human
beings determine the development of technology and the social relations
they wish to pursue. Rothbard quotes von Mises, who states "We may
summarize the Marxian doctrine in this way: In the beginning there are
the 'material productive forces', i.e., the technological equipment of
human productive efforts, the tools and machines. No question concerning
their origin is permitted; they are, that is all; we must assume that
they are dropped from heaven."
Historical determinism
Marx's theory of history has been considered a variant of historical determinism linked to his reliance on dialectical materialism as an endogenous mechanism for social change. Marx wrote:
At a certain stage of development, the material productive forces of society come into conflict with the existing relations of production or – this merely expresses the same thing in legal terms – with the property relations within the framework of which they have operated hitherto. From forms of development of the productive forces these relations turn into their fetters. Then begins an era of social revolution. The changes in the economic foundation lead sooner or later to the transformation of the whole immense superstructure.
The concept of the dialectic emerged from the dialogues of the ancient Greek philosophers, but it was brought out by Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel
in the early 19th century as a conceptual framework for the often
opposing forces of historical evolution. Historical determinism has also
been associated with scholars like Arnold Toynbee and Oswald Spengler, but in recent times this conceptual approach has fallen into disuse.
Terry Eagleton
writes that Marx's writings "should not be taken to mean that
everything that has ever happened is a matter of class struggle. It
means, rather, that class struggle is most fundamental to human
history".
Academic Peter Stillman believes Marx's status as a determinist is a "myth". Fredrick Engels
himself warned about conceiving of Marx's ideas as deterministic saying
"According to the materialist conception of history, the ultimately
determining element in history is the production and reproduction of
real life. Other than this neither Marx nor I have ever asserted. Hence
if somebody twists this into saying that the economic element is the
only determining one, he transforms that proposition into a meaningless,
abstract, senseless phrase." On another occasion Engels remarks that "younger people sometimes lay more stress on the economic side than is due to it".
In an effort to reassert this approach to an understanding of the forces of history, Prabhat Ranjan Sarkar criticised what he considers narrow conceptual basis of Marx's ideas on historical evolution. In the 1978 book The Downfall of Capitalism and Communism, Ravi Batra pointed out crucial differences in the historical determinist approaches of Sarkar and Marx.
Sarkar's main concern with the human element is what imparts universality to his thesis. Thus while social evolution according to Marx is governed chiefly by economic conditions, to Sarkar this dynamic is propelled by forces varying with time and space: sometimes physical prowess and high-spiritedness, sometimes intellect applied to dogmas and sometimes intellect applied to the accumulation of capital (p. 38) ... The main line of defence of the Sarkarian hypothesis is that unlike the dogmas now in disrepute, it does not emphasise one particular point to the exclusion of all others: it is based on the sum total of human experience – the totality of human nature. Whenever a single factor, however important and fundamental, is called upon to illuminate the entire past and by implication the future, it simply invites disbelief, and after closer inspection, rejection. Marx committed that folly, and to some extent so did Toynbee. They both offered an easy prey to the critics, and the result is that today historical determinism is regarded by most scholars as an idea so bankrupt that it can never be solvent again.
Suppression of individual rights
Various thinkers have argued that a communist state would by its very nature erode the rights of its citizens due to the postulated violent revolution and dictatorship of proletariat, its collectivist nature, reliance on "the masses" rather than individuals, historical determinism and centrally planned economy.
The U.S. neoclassical economist Milton Friedman
argued that under socialism the absence of a free market economy would
inevitably lead to an authoritarian political regime. Friedman's view
was also shared by Friedrich Hayek, who also believed that capitalism is a precondition for freedom to flourish in a nation state. Some liberal theorists argue that any redistribution of property is a form of coercion. Daniel De Leon
counters this stating "Capitalism is a fraud within a fraud.
Proclaiming itself individualistic, it organizes collectively in order
to promote the aims of a few. Socialism, on the other hand...would
secure to labor the products of its toil, now confiscated by the few,
and, in this way, preserve to the workers, the majority of the
population, a greater individuality than that which they now attain".
Anarchists have also argued that centralized communism will inevitably lead to coercion and state domination. Mikhail Bakunin believed Marxist regimes would lead to the "despotic control of the populace by a new and not at all numerous aristocracy". Even if this new aristocracy were to have originated from among the ranks of the proletariat,
Bakunin argued that their new-found power would fundamentally change
their view of society and thus lead them to "look down at the plain
working masses".
Economic
Marxian economics
have been criticized for a number of reasons. Some critics point to the
Marxian analysis of capitalism while others argue that the economic
system proposed by Marxism is unworkable.
There are also doubts that the rate of profit in capitalism would tend to fall as Marx predicted. In 1961, Marxian economist Nobuo Okishio devised a theorem (Okishio's theorem) showing that if capitalists pursue cost-cutting techniques and if the real wage does not rise, the rate of profit must rise.
Labor theory of value
The labor theory of value is one of the most commonly criticized core tenets of Marxism.
The Austrian School argues that this fundamental theory of classical economics is false and prefers the subsequent and modern subjective theory of value put forward by Carl Menger in his book Principles of Economics.
The Austrian School was not alone in criticizing the Marxian and
classical belief in the labor theory of value. British economist Alfred Marshall
attacked Marx, saying: "It is not true that the spinning of yarn in a
factory [...] is the product of the labour of the operatives. It is the
product of their labour, together with that of the employer and
subordinate managers, and of the capital employed".
Marshall points to the capitalist as sacrificing the money he could be
using now for investment in business, which ultimately produces work.
By this logic, the capitalist contributes to the work and productivity
of the factory because he delays his gratification through investment. Through the law of supply and demand,
Marshall attacked Marxian theory of value. According to Marshall, price
or value is determined not just by supply, but by the demand of the
consumer.
Labor does contribute to cost, but so do the wants and needs of
consumers. The shift from labor being the source of all value to
subjective individual evaluations creating all value undermines Marx's
economic conclusions and some of his social theories.
Shimshon Bichler and Jonathan Nitzan argue that most studies
purporting to show empirical evidence of the labor theory of value often
make methodological errors by comparing the total labor value to total
price of multiple economic sectors, which results in a strong overall
correlation but this is a statistical exaggeration; the authors argue
that the correlations between labor value and price in each sector are
often very small if not insignificant. Bichler and Nitzan also argue
that because it is difficult to quantify a way to measure abstract
labor, researchers are forced to make assumptions. However, Bichler and Nitzan argue these assumptions involve circular reasoning:
The most important of these assumptions are that the value of labour power is proportionate to the actual wage rate, that the ratio of variable capital to surplus value is given by the price ratio of wages to profit, and occasionally also that the value of the depreciated constant capital is equal to a fraction of the capital’s money price. In other words, the researcher assumes precisely what the labour theory of value is supposed to demonstrate.
Distorted or absent price signals
The economic calculation problem is a criticism of socialist economics or, more precisely, of centralized socialist planned economies. It was first proposed by Austrian School economist Ludwig von Mises in 1920 and later expounded by Friedrich Hayek. The problem referred to is that of how to distribute resources rationally in an economy. The free market solution is the price mechanism,
wherein people individually have the ability to decide how a good
should be distributed based on their willingness to give money for it.
The price conveys embedded information about the abundance of resources
as well as their desirability which in turn allows on the basis of
individual consensual decisions corrections that prevent shortages and surpluses.
Mises and Hayek argued that this is the only possible solution and,
without the information provided by market prices, socialism lacks a
method to rationally allocate resources. The debate raged in the 1920s
and 1930s and that specific period of the debate has come to be known by
economic historians as the socialist calculation debate. In practice, socialist states like the Soviet Union used mathematical techniques to determine and set prices with mixed results.
Reduced incentives
Some critics of socialism argue that income sharing reduces individual
incentives to work and therefore incomes should be individualised as
much as possible.
Critics of socialism have argued that in any society where everyone
holds equal wealth there can be no material incentive to work because
one does not receive rewards for work well done. They further argue that
incentives increase productivity for all people and that the loss of
those effects would lead to stagnation. In Principles of Political Economy (1848), John Stuart Mill said:
It is the common error of Socialists to overlook the natural indolence of mankind; their tendency to be passive, to be the slaves of habit, to persist indefinitely in a course once chosen. Let them once attain any state of existence which they consider tolerable, and the danger to be apprehended is that they will thenceforth stagnate; will not exert themselves to improve, and by letting their faculties rust, will lose even the energy required to preserve them from deterioration. Competition may not be the best conceivable stimulus, but it is at present a necessary one, and no one can foresee the time when it will not be indispensable to progress.
However, he later altered his views and became more sympathetic to socialism, particularly Fourierism, adding chapters to his Principles of Political Economy in defence of a socialist outlook and defending some socialist causes.
Within this revised work, he also made the radical proposal that the
whole wage system be abolished in favour of a co-operative wage system.
Nonetheless, some of his views on the idea of flat taxation remained,
albeit in a slightly toned-down form.
The economist John Kenneth Galbraith
has criticised communal forms of socialism that promote egalitarianism
in terms of wages/compensation as unrealistic in its assumptions about
human motivation:
This hope [that egalitarian reward would lead to a higher level of motivation], one that spread far beyond Marx, has been shown by both history and human experience to be irrelevant. For better or worse, human beings do not rise to such heights. Generations of socialists and socially oriented leaders have learned this to their disappointment and more often to their sorrow. The basic fact is clear: the good society must accept men and women as they are.
Edgar Hardcastle
responds to this by saying "They want to work and need no more
inducement than is given by the knowledge that work must be done to keep
society going, and that they are playing their part in it along with
their fellow men and women". He continues by criticising what he sees
are the double standards
of anti-socialists, "Notice how they object to the unemployed receiving
a miserly dole without having to work, but never object to the
millionaires (most of them in that position through inheritance) being
able to live in luxurious idleness." Authors like Arnold Petersen argue that arguments such as these are inaccurate as hunter-gatherers practiced primitive communism without problems such as these.
Inconsistency
Vladimir Karpovich Dmitriev writing in 1898, Ladislaus von Bortkiewicz writing in 1906–1907[55] and subsequent critics have alleged that Karl Marx's value theory and law of the tendency of the rate of profit to fall
are internally inconsistent. In other words, the critics allege that
Marx drew conclusions that actually do not follow from his theoretical
premises. Once those errors are corrected, Marx's conclusion that
aggregate price and profit are determined by—and equal to—aggregate
value and surplus value no longer holds true. This result calls into
question his theory that the exploitation of workers is the sole source
of profit.
The inconsistency allegations have been a prominent feature of Marxian economics and the debate surrounding it since the 1970s. Andrew Kliman
argues that since internally inconsistent theories cannot possibly be
right, this undermines Marx's critique of political economy and
current-day research based upon it as well as the correction of Marx's
alleged inconsistencies.
Critics who have alleged that Marx has been proved internally inconsistent include former and current Marxian and/or Sraffian economists, such as Paul Sweezy, Nobuo Okishio, Ian Steedman, John Roemer, Gary Mongiovi and David Laibman,
who propose that the field be grounded in their correct versions of
Marxian economics instead of in Marx's critique of political economy in
the original form in which he presented and developed it in Capital.
Proponents of the temporal single system interpretation
(TSSI) of Marx's value theory, like Kliman, claim that the supposed
inconsistencies are actually the result of misinterpretation and argue
that when Marx's theory is understood as "temporal" and "single-system",
the alleged internal inconsistencies disappear. In a recent survey of
the debate, Kliman concludes that "the proofs of inconsistency are no
longer defended; the entire case against Marx has been reduced to the
interpretive issue".
Relevance
Marxism has been criticized as irrelevant, with many economists rejecting its core tenets and assumptions. John Maynard Keynes referred to Capital
as "an obsolete textbook which I know to be not only scientifically
erroneous but without interest or application for the modern world". According to George Stigler,
"Economists working in the Marxian-Sraffian tradition represent a small
minority of modern economists, and that their writings have virtually
no impact upon the professional work of most economists in major
English-language universities". Robert Solow, in a review of the first edition of The New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics criticized it for overemphasizing the importance of Marxism in modern economics.
Marx was an important and influential thinker, and Marxism has been a doctrine with intellectual and practical influence. The fact is, however, that most serious English-speaking economists regard Marxist economics as an irrelevant dead end.
A 2006 nationally representative survey of American professors found
3% of them identify as Marxists. The share rises to 5% in the humanities
and is about 18% amongst social scientists.
Social
Social criticism is based on the assertion that the Marxian conception of society is fundamentally flawed. The Marxist stages of history, class analysis and theory of social evolution have been criticised. Jean-Paul Sartre
concluded that "class" was not a homogenous entity and could never
mount a revolution, but continued to advocate Marxist beliefs. Marx himself admitted that his theory could not explain the internal development of the Asiatic social system, where much of the world's population lived for thousands of years.
Epistemological
Arguments against Marxism are often based on epistemological reasoning. Specifically, various critics have contended that Marx or his adherents have a flawed approach to epistemology.
According to Leszek Kołakowski, the laws of dialectics at the very base of Marxism
are fundamentally flawed: some are "truisms with no specific Marxist
content", others "philosophical dogmas that cannot be proved by
scientific means", yet others just "nonsense". Some Marxist "laws" are
vague and can be interpreted differently, but these interpretations
generally fall into one of the aforementioned categories of flaws as
well. However, Ralph Miliband countered that Kolakowski had a flawed understanding of Marxism and its relation to Leninism and Stalinism.
Economist Thomas Sowell wrote in 1985:
What Marx accomplished was to produce such a comprehensive, dramatic, and fascinating vision that it could withstand innumerable empirical contradictions, logical refutations, and moral revulsions at its effects. The Marxian vision took the overwhelming complexity of the real world and made the parts fall into place, in a way that was intellectually exhilarating and conferred such a sense of moral superiority that opponents could be simply labelled and dismissed as moral lepers or blind reactionaries. Marxism was – and remains – a mighty instrument for the acquisition and maintenance of political power.
Many notable academics such as Karl Popper, David Prychitko, Robert C. Allen, and Francis Fukuyama argue that many of Marx's predictions have failed.
Marx predicted that wages would tend to depreciate and that capitalist
economies would suffer worsening economic crises leading to the ultimate
overthrow of the capitalist system. The socialist revolution would
occur first in the most advanced capitalist nations and once collective
ownership had been established then all sources of class conflict would
disappear. Instead of Marx's predictions, communist revolutions took
place in undeveloped regions in Latin America and Asia instead of
industrialized countries like the United States or the United Kingdom.
Popper has argued that both the concept of Marx's historical method as well as its application are unfalsifiable and thus it is a pseudoscience that cannot be proven true or false:
The Marxist theory of history, in spite of the serious efforts of some of its founders and followers, ultimately adopted this soothsaying practice. In some of its earlier formulations (for example in Marx's analysis of the character of the 'coming social revolution') their predictions were testable, and in fact falsified. Yet instead of accepting the refutations the followers of Marx re-interpreted both the theory and the evidence in order to make them agree. In this way they rescued the theory from refutation; but they did so at the price of adopting a device which made it irrefutable. They thus gave a 'conventionalist twist' to the theory; and by this stratagem they destroyed its much advertised claim to scientific status.
Popper believed that Marxism had been initially scientific, in that Marx
had postulated a theory which was genuinely predictive. When Marx's
predictions were not in fact borne out, Popper argues that the theory
was saved from falsification by the addition of ad hoc
hypotheses which attempted to make it compatible with the facts. By
this means, a theory which was initially genuinely scientific
degenerated into pseudoscientific dogma. Popper agreed on the general non-falsifiability of the social sciences, but instead used it as an argument against central planning and all-encompassing historiographical ideologies.
Popper devoted much attention to dissecting the practice of using the
dialectic in defence of Marxist thought, which was the very strategy
employed by V.A. Lektorsky in his defence of Marxism against Popper's
criticisms. Among Popper's conclusions was that Marxists used dialectic
as a method of side-stepping and evading criticisms, rather than
actually answering or addressing them:
Hegel thought that philosophy develops; yet his own system was to remain the last and highest stage of this development and could not be superseded. The Marxists adopted the same attitude towards the Marxian system. Hence, Marx's anti-dogmatic attitude exists only in the theory and not in the practice of orthodox Marxism, and dialectic is used by Marxists, following the example of Engels' Anti-Dühring, mainly for the purposes of apologetics – to defend the Marxist system against criticism. As a rule critics are denounced for their failure to understand the dialectic, or proletarian science, or for being traitors. Thanks to dialectic the anti-dogmatic attitude has disappeared, and Marxism has established itself as a dogmatism which is elastic enough, by using its dialectic method, to evade any further attack. It has thus become what I have called reinforced dogmatism.
Bertrand Russell
has criticized as unscientific Marx's belief in progress as a universal
law. Russell stated: "Marx professed himself an atheist, but retained a
cosmic optimism which only theism could justify". Marxists like Thomas Riggins have claimed that Russell misrepresented Marx's ideas.