Eliminative materialism (also called eliminativism) is the claim that people's common-sense understanding of the mind (or folk psychology) is false and that certain classes of mental states that most people believe in do not exist. It is a materialist position in the philosophy of mind. Some supporters of eliminativism argue that no coherent neural basis will be found for many everyday psychological concepts such as belief or desire, since they are poorly defined. Rather, they argue that psychological concepts of behavior and experience should be judged by how well they reduce to the biological level. Other versions entail the non-existence of conscious mental states such as pain and visual perceptions.
Eliminativism about a class of entities is the view that that class of entities does not exist. For example, materialism tends to be eliminativist about the soul; modern chemists are eliminativist about phlogiston; and modern physicists are eliminativist about the existence of luminiferous aether. Eliminative materialism
is the relatively new (1960s–1970s) idea that certain classes of mental
entities that common sense takes for granted, such as beliefs, desires,
and the subjective sensation of pain, do not exist. The most common versions are eliminativism about propositional attitudes, as expressed by Paul and Patricia Churchland, and eliminativism about qualia (subjective interpretations about particular instances of subjective experience), as expressed by Daniel Dennett and Georges Rey. These philosophers often appeal to an introspection illusion.
In the context of materialist understandings of psychology, eliminativism stands in opposition to reductive materialism which argues that mental states as conventionally understood do exist, and that they directly correspond to the physical state of the nervous system. An intermediate position is revisionary materialism, which will often argue that the mental state in question will prove to be somewhat reducible to physical phenomena—with some changes needed to the common sense concept.
Since eliminative materialism claims that future research will
fail to find a neuronal basis for various mental phenomena, it must
necessarily wait for science to progress further. One might question the
position on these grounds, but other philosophers like Churchland argue
that eliminativism is often necessary in order to open the minds of
thinkers to new evidence and better explanations.
Overview
Various
arguments have been put forth both for and against eliminative
materialism over the last forty years. Most of the arguments in favor of
the view are based on the assumption that people's commonsense view of
the mind is actually an implicit theory. It is to be compared and
contrasted with other scientific theories in its explanatory success,
accuracy, and ability to allow people to make correct predictions about
the future. Eliminativists argue that, based on these and other
criteria, commonsense "folk" psychology has failed and will eventually
need to be replaced with explanations derived from the neurosciences.
These philosophers therefore tend to emphasize the importance of
neuroscientific research as well as developments in artificial intelligence to sustain their thesis.
Philosophers who argue against eliminativism may take several approaches. Simulation theorists, like Robert Gordon and Alvin Goldman
argue that folk psychology is not a theory, but rather depends on
internal simulation of others, and therefore is not subject to
falsification in the same way that theories are. Jerry Fodor, among others,
argues that folk psychology is, in fact, a successful (even
indispensable) theory. Another view is that eliminativism assumes the
existence of the beliefs and other entities it seeks to "eliminate" and
is thus self-refuting.
Eliminativism maintains that the common-sense understanding of the mind is mistaken, and that the neurosciences
will one day reveal that the mental states that are talked about in
everyday discourse, using words such as "intend", "believe", "desire",
and "love", do not refer to anything real. Because of the inadequacy of
natural languages, people mistakenly think that they have such beliefs
and desires. Some eliminativists, such as Frank Jackson, claim that consciousness does not exist except as an epiphenomenon of brain function; others, such as Georges Rey, claim that the concept will eventually be eliminated as neuroscience progresses.
Consciousness and folk psychology are separate issues and it is
possible to take an eliminative stance on one but not the other. The roots of eliminativism go back to the writings of Wilfred Sellars, W.V. Quine, Paul Feyerabend, and Richard Rorty. The term "eliminative materialism" was first introduced by James Cornman in 1968 while describing a version of physicalism endorsed by Rorty. The later Ludwig Wittgenstein
was also an important inspiration for eliminativism, particularly with
his attack on "private objects" as "grammatical fictions".
Early eliminativists such as Rorty and Feyerabend often confused
two different notions of the sort of elimination that the term
"eliminative materialism" entailed. On the one hand, they claimed, the cognitive sciences
that will ultimately give people a correct account of the workings of
the mind will not employ terms that refer to common-sense mental states
like beliefs and desires; these states will not be part of the ontology of a mature cognitive science. But critics immediately countered that this view was indistinguishable from the identity theory of mind. Quine himself wondered what exactly was so eliminative about eliminative materialism after all:
“ | Is physicalism a repudiation of mental objects after all, or a theory of them? Does it repudiate the mental state of pain or anger in favor of its physical concomitant, or does it identify the mental state with a state of the physical organism (and so a state of the physical organism with the mental state)? | ” |
On the other hand, the same philosophers also claimed that
common-sense mental states simply do not exist. But critics pointed out
that eliminativists could not have it both ways: either mental states
exist and will ultimately be explained in terms of lower-level
neurophysiological processes or they do not.
Modern eliminativists have much more clearly expressed the view that
mental phenomena simply do not exist and will eventually be eliminated
from people's thinking about the brain in the same way that demons have
been eliminated from people's thinking about mental illness and
psychopathology.
While it was a minority view in the 1960s, eliminative materialism gained prominence and acceptance during the 1980s. Proponents of this view, such as B.F. Skinner, often made parallels to previous superseded scientific theories (such as that of the four humours, the phlogiston theory of combustion, and the vital force
theory of life) that have all been successfully eliminated in
attempting to establish their thesis about the nature of the mental. In
these cases, science has not produced more detailed versions or
reductions of these theories, but rejected them altogether as obsolete. Radical behaviorists, such as Skinner, argued that folk psychology is already obsolete and should be replaced by descriptions of histories of reinforcement and punishment. Such views were eventually abandoned. Patricia and Paul Churchland argued that folk psychology will be gradually replaced as neuroscience matures.
Eliminativism is not only motivated by philosophical
considerations, but is also a prediction about what form future
scientific theories will take. Eliminativist philosophers therefore tend
to be concerned with the data coming from the relevant brain and cognitive sciences.
In addition, because eliminativism is essentially predictive in
nature, different theorists can, and often do, make different
predictions about which aspects of folk psychology will be eliminated
from folk psychological vocabulary. None of these philosophers are
eliminativists "tout court".
Today, the eliminativist view is most closely associated with the philosophers Paul and Patricia Churchland, who deny the existence of propositional attitudes (a subclass of intentional states), and with Daniel Dennett, who is generally considered to be an eliminativist about qualia
and phenomenal aspects of consciousness. One way to summarize the
difference between the Churchlands's views and Dennett's view is that
the Churchlands are eliminativists when it comes to propositional
attitudes, but reductionists
concerning qualia, while Dennett is an anti-reductionist with respect
to propositional attitudes, and an eliminativist concerning qualia.
Arguments for eliminativism
Problems with folk theories
Eliminativists such as Paul and Patricia Churchland argue that folk psychology
is a fully developed but non-formalized theory of human behavior. It is
used to explain and make predictions about human mental states and
behavior. This view is often referred to as the theory of mind or just simply theory-theory, for it is a theory which theorizes the existence of an unacknowledged theory. As a theory
in the scientific sense, eliminativists maintain, folk psychology needs
to be evaluated on the basis of its predictive power and explanatory
success as a research program for the investigation of the mind/brain.
Such eliminativists have developed different arguments to show
that folk psychology is a seriously mistaken theory and needs to be
abolished. They argue that folk psychology excludes from its purview or
has traditionally been mistaken about many important mental phenomena
that can, and are, being examined and explained by modern neurosciences. Some examples are dreaming, consciousness, mental disorders, learning processes, and memory
abilities. Furthermore, they argue, folk psychology's development in
the last 2,500 years has not been significant and it is therefore a
stagnating theory. The ancient Greeks
already had a folk psychology comparable to modern views. But in
contrast to this lack of development, the neurosciences are a rapidly
progressing science complex that, in their view, can explain many cognitive processes that folk psychology cannot.
Folk psychology retains characteristics of now obsolete theories
or legends from the past. Ancient societies tried to explain the
physical mysteries of nature
by ascribing mental conditions to them in such statements as "the sea
is angry". Gradually, these everyday folk psychological explanations
were replaced by more efficient scientific
descriptions. Today, eliminativists argue, there is no reason not to
accept an effective scientific account of people's cognitive abilities.
If such an explanation existed, then there would be no need for
folk-psychological explanations of behavior, and the latter would be
eliminated the same way as the mythological explanations the ancients used.
Another line of argument is the meta-induction based on what
eliminativists view as the disastrous historical record of folk theories
in general. Ancient pre-scientific "theories" of folk biology, folk
physics, and folk cosmology have all proven to be radically wrong.
Eliminativists argue the same in the case of folk psychology. There
seems no logical basis, to the eliminativist, for making an exception
just because folk psychology has lasted longer and is more intuitive or
instinctively plausible than the other folk theories.
Indeed, the eliminativists warn, considerations of intuitive
plausibility may be precisely the result of the deeply entrenched nature
in society of folk psychology itself. It may be that people's beliefs
and other such states are as theory-laden as external perceptions and
hence intuitions will tend to be biased in favor of them.
Specific problems with folk psychology
Much of folk psychology involves the attribution of intentional states (or more specifically as a subclass, propositional attitudes).
Eliminativists point out that these states are generally ascribed
syntactic and semantic properties. An example of this is the language of thought
hypothesis, which attributes a discrete, combinatorial syntax and other
linguistic properties to these mental phenomena. Eliminativists argue
that such discrete and combinatorial characteristics have no place in
the neurosciences, which speak of action potentials, spiking frequencies,
and other effects which are continuous and distributed in nature.
Hence, the syntactic structures which are assumed by folk psychology can
have no place in such a structure as the brain.
Against this there have been two responses. On the one hand, there are
philosophers who deny that mental states are linguistic in nature and
see this as a straw man argument. The other view is represented by those who subscribe to "a language of thought". They assert that the mental states can be multiply realized and that functional characterizations are just higher-level characterizations of what's happening at the physical level.
It has also been argued against folk psychology that the
intentionality of mental states like belief imply that they have
semantic qualities. Specifically, their meaning is determined by the
things that they are about in the external world. This makes it
difficult to explain how they can play the causal roles that they are
supposed to in cognitive processes.
In recent years, this latter argument has been fortified by the theory of connectionism.
Many connectionist models of the brain have been developed in which the
processes of language learning and other forms of representation are
highly distributed and parallel. This would tend to indicate that there
is no need for such discrete and semantically endowed entities as
beliefs and desires.
Arguments against eliminativism
Intuitive reservations
The
thesis of eliminativism seems to be so obviously wrong to many critics,
under the claim that people know immediately and indubitably that they
have minds, that argumentation seems unnecessary. This sort of intuition
pumping is illustrated by asking what happens when one asks oneself
honestly if one has mental states. Eliminativists object to such a rebuttal of their position by claiming that intuitions often are mistaken. Analogies from the history of science are frequently invoked to buttress this observation: it may appear obvious that the sun travels around the earth,
for example, but for all its apparent obviousness this conception was
proved wrong nevertheless. Similarly, it may appear obvious that apart
from neural events there are also mental conditions. Nevertheless, this
could equally turn out to be false.
But even if one accepts the susceptibility to error of people's
intuitions, the objection can be reformulated: if the existence of
mental conditions seems perfectly obvious and is central in people's
conception of the world, then enormously strong arguments are needed in
order to successfully deny the existence of mental conditions.
Furthermore, these arguments, to be consistent, need to be formulated in
a way which does not pre-suppose the existence of entities like "mental
states", "logical arguments", and "ideas", otherwise they are self-contradictory.
Those who accept this objection say that the arguments in favor of
eliminativism are far too weak to establish such a radical claim;
therefore there is no reason to believe in eliminativism.
Self-refutation
Some philosophers, such as Paul Boghossian, have attempted to show that eliminativism is in some sense self-refuting,
since the theory itself presupposes the existence of mental phenomena.
If eliminativism is true, then the eliminativist must permit an intentional property like truth,
supposing that in order to assert something one must believe it. Hence,
for eliminativism to be asserted as a thesis, the eliminativist must
believe that it is true; if that is the case, then there are beliefs and
the eliminativist claim is false.
Georges Rey and Michael Devitt reply to this objection by invoking deflationary semantic theories that avoid analyzing predicates
like "x is true" as expressing a real property. They are construed,
instead, as logical devices so that asserting that a sentence is true is
just a quoted way of asserting the sentence itself. To say, "'God
exists' is true" is just to say, "God exists". This way, Rey and Devitt
argue, insofar as dispositional replacements of "claims" and
deflationary accounts of "true" are coherent, eliminativism is not
self-refuting.
Qualia
Another problem for the eliminativist is the consideration that human beings undergo subjective experiences and, hence, their conscious mental states have qualia.
Since qualia are generally regarded as characteristics of mental
states, their existence does not seem to be compatible with
eliminativism. Eliminativists, such as Daniel Dennett and Georges Rey, respond by rejecting qualia.
This is seen to be problematic to opponents of eliminativists, since
many claim that the existence of qualia seems perfectly obvious. Many
philosophers consider the "elimination" of qualia implausible, if not
incomprehensible. They assert that, for instance, the existence of pain
is simply beyond denial.
Admitting that the existence of qualia seems obvious, Dennett
nevertheless states that "qualia" is a theoretical term from an outdated
metaphysics stemming from Cartesian
intuitions. He argues that a precise analysis shows that the term is in
the long run empty and full of contradictions. The eliminativist's
claim with respect to qualia is that there is no unbiased evidence for
such experiences when regarded as something more than propositional attitudes. In other words, they do not deny that pain exists, but that it exists independently of its effect on behavior. Influenced by Ludwig Wittgenstein's Philosophical Investigations, Dennett and Rey have defended eliminativism about qualia, even when other portions of the mental are accepted.
Efficacy of folk psychology
Some philosophers argue that folk psychology is a quite successful theory.
Simulation theorists doubt that people's understanding of the mental
can be explained in terms of a theory at all. Rather they argue that
people's understanding of others is based on internal simulations of how
they would act and respond in similar situations. Jerry Fodor
is one of the objectors that believes in folk psychology's success as a
theory, because it makes for an effective way of communication in
everyday life that can be implemented with few words. Such an
effectiveness could never be achieved with a complex neuroscientific
terminology.