Goethean science concerns the natural philosophy (German Naturphilosophie "philosophy of nature") of German writer Johann Wolfgang von Goethe. Although primarily known as a literary figure, Goethe did research in morphology, anatomy, and optics. He also developed a phenomenological approach to natural history, an alternative to Enlightenment natural science, which is still debated today among scholars.
His works in natural history include his 1790 Metamorphosis of Plants and his 1810 book Theory of Colors. His work in optics, and his polemics against the reigning Newtonian theory of optics, were poorly received by the natural history establishment of his time.
Background
By the middle of the 1700s, Western philosophy had reached an ethical and epistemological cul-de-sac. The Enlightenment or Age of Reason was based on a static view of human nature, an increasingly mechanical view of the universe (based on:
- Copernican astronomy,
- Galilean mechanics and
- Newtonian physics) and
- a linear view of the progress of scientific knowledge (the mechano-material, reductionist approach).
The exclusively rationalist approach, was termed by Ernst Lehrs as the 'one-eyed, color blind' perspective of the world.
An exclusively rationalist approach to life raises fundamental issues about "God, freedom and immortality" (Kant) of growing concern to a culture undergoing significant economic, political and cultural transformation.
The rationalist scientific method, which had worked well with inert nature (Bacon's natura naturata), was less successful in seeking to understand vital nature (natura naturans). At the same time, the rational-empirical model based on the predominance of mentative thinking (German: sinnen) via the intellect (German: Sinn), started by Descartes
and advanced most notably in France, was leading to confusion and doubt
rather than clarity. Especially in subjective topics, equally rational
arguments could be made for widely divergent propositions or
conceptions.
The more empirical approach favored in Britain (Hume)
had led to viewing reality as sense-based, including the mind; how,
what we perceive is only a mental representation of what is real, and
what is real we can never really know.
As one observer summarizes, there were two 'games' being played
in philosophy at the time – one rational and one empirical, both of
which led to total skepticism and an epistemological crisis.
The Kantian problem
Immanuel Kant
in Prussia undertook a major rescue operation to preserve the validity
of knowledge derived via reason (science), as well as of knowledge going
beyond the rational mind, that is of human liberty and of life beyond
simply an expression of 'the chance whirlings of unproductive particles'
(Coleridge). Kant's writings had an immediate and major impact on Western philosophy and triggered a philosophical movement known as German idealism (Fichte, Hegel, Schelling),
which sought to overcome and transcend the chasm Kant had formalized
between the sense-based and the super-sensible worlds, in his attempt to
'save the appearances' (Owen Barfield), that is, to preserve the validity of scientific or rational knowledge as well as that of faith.
Kant's solution was an epistemological dualism: we cannot know the thing-in-itself (Das Ding an Sich) beyond our mental representation of it. While there is a power (productive imagination – produktive Einbildungskraft)
that produces a unity ("transcendental unity of apperception"), we
cannot know or experience it in itself; we can only see its
manifestations and create representations about it in our mind. The
realm beyond the senses also could not be known via reason, but only via
faith. To seek to know the realm beyond the senses amounts to what Kant
termed an 'adventure of reason'.
Goethe's approach to vital nature
Goethe
undertook his 'adventure of reason', starting with the "crisis" in
botany, the merely and purely mechanical classification-taxonomy of
plant life. In so doing Goethe also "wagered a sweeping theory about
Nature itself."
Goethe was concerned with the narrowing specialization in science
and emphasis on accumulating data in a merely mechanical manner, devoid
of human values and human development. Linnaean botanic taxonomic
system represented this in his day, a Systema naturae. Goethe
intuited the practice of rational science promoted a narrowing and
contracting interplay between humanity and Nature. For Goethe any
science based only on physical-material characteristics and then only
selected external traits, led to epistemic impoverishment and a
reduction of human knowledge.
What was needed was increased ability to derive meaning from
voluminous external data by looking at it from both external-sensory
angles; and, from an internal angle where thinking, Feeling, Intuition,
Imagination and Inspiration could all contribute to conclusions reached
by the experimenter.
Linnaean taxonomy was already coming under criticism from Comte de Buffon,
who argued the mechanistic classification of the outer forms of nature
(natura naturata) needed to be replaced by a study of the interrelation
of natural forces and natural historical change.
For Goethe, the production of new knowledge is inseparable from a Geschichte des Denkens und Begreifens, a history of thinking and conceptualization. Knowledge is also about association, not only about separation, as Coleridge also was at pains to explain in his Essays on Method.
While arranging material phenomena in logical linear sequence is a
valid scientific method, it had to be carried out under a correct and
humanistic organizing idea (Bacon's lumen siccum), itself grounded in Nature, or natural law (often boundaried by multiple, lawful pairs of polarity).
Goethe proposed experimenters seek the natural, lawful organizing
ideas and/or archetype behind specific natural phenomena. Phase One
was to immerse one's self in a living interaction with the natural
phenomena to be studied, with all available senses. Goethe valued "the
labor of experimentation".
This contrasted greatly with a trend in rational Natural Science,
to 'abandon' Nature herself, formulate an abstract hypothesis; then,
experiment to test whether your hypothesis can be verified or not.
Goethe considered this an 'artificial experience' which 'tears'
individual manifestations out of the meaningful context of the whole
(for example, Newton's color hypothesis).
Instead, Goethe's experimenter must adopt a more living, more
humane, approach aspiring to entering into the living essence of Nature,
as perceived in the phenomenon studied.
For Goethe success meant penetrating to the crucial underlying, sensorily-invisible archetype-pattern (Ur-phänomen).
The Experimenter aspires to allow the phenomena to reveal its inherent
order and lawfulness. While often invisible, this lawfulness is
clearly objective not subjective, not invented by the experimenter (see
Goethe's description of a dandelion or Steiner's copied version).
Ernst Lehrs went further in emphasizing how all objective
manifestation comes from movement, physical-material objects as motion
come to rest (Man or Matter, 3rd ed preferred).
Goethean Science stands apart from Cartesian-Newtonian Science;
its alternative value system sets it apart. Regarding quantification,
Goethean Science is nonetheless rigorous as to experimental method and
the matter of qualities.
Goethe's student and editor of his works, Rudolf Steiner, applied Goethe's methodology of a living approach to Nature to the performing and fine arts. This gives Anthroposophic visual and performing arts their air of going beyond the mere outer form of things (natura naturata) to discern a more inner nature (natura naturans). Steiner hoped to relate the human sphere with all of Nature through the arts; including, the art of Goethean Science.
Goethe's Ur-phenomena
Five arts was Goethe's method of transmuting his observation of human nature into sharable form. Drawing from his novel, Elective Affinities (Wahlverwandschaften), Goethe discerned a geheime Verwandschaft (hidden relationship) of parts that explains how one form can transform into another form while being part of an underlying archetypal form (Ur-phänomen).
It is this organizing idea or form that guides the consideration of the parts; it is a Bild or virtual image that "emerges and re-emerges from the interaction of experience and ideas". This consideration is a special type of thinking (noetic ideation or denken) carried out with a different organ of cognizance to that of the brain (mentation or sinnen), one that involves an act of creative imagination, what Goethe terms "the living imaginal beholding of Nature" (das lebendige Anschauen der Natur). Goethe's nature (natura naturans, the activity of "nature naturing" – as distinguished from natura naturata, "nature natured", the domain of naturally formed objects)
is one in constant flux and flow, but nonetheless governed by law,
logic and intelligence above the mind. To approach vital nature requires
a different cognitive capacity (denken) and cognitive organ (Gemüt) from that used to perceive inert nature (sinnen based on the Intellect or Sinn).
Experiment as interactive experience
In his 1792 essay "The experiment as mediator between subject and object", Goethe developed an original philosophy of science,
which he used in his research. The essay underscores his experiential
standpoint. "The human being himself, to the extent he makes sound use
of his senses, is the most exact physical apparatus that can exist."
While the fixed Linnaean system, like classical physics, its
distinctions broke down increasingly at the border, reflected in the
increasing confusion as to how to classify the growing number of plant
forms being brought forward. This led to greater division rather than
greater unity. Goethe's discovery of an underlying order directly
challenged the fixed, static view of nature of the Linnaean taxonomy
(based on artificial types arrived at by choosing certain features and
ignoring others), but also the tendency of natural science to study
vital nature by means of the methodology used on inert nature (physics,
chemistry).
The Cartesian-Newtonian method presupposes separation between
observer and observed. Goethe considered this a barrier. As Wellmon
observes, Goethe's concept of science is one in which "not only the
object of observation changes and moves but also the subject of
observation." Thus, a true science of vital nature would be based on an
approach that was itself vital, dynamic, labile. The key for this is a
living, direct, interactive experience (Erlebnis) involving the mind, but also higher faculties more participatory and Imaginative (Gemüt), not dissociative and separative (Sinn).
Only since the 1970s have other mainstream scientists come to be
interested in Goethe's more holistic-humanistic approach to experiments.
In his study on color (Farbenlehre), Goethe challenged the
view observers can look devoid and naive of theoretical context;
likewise, challenging the assumption of shared common neutral language
in science research and innovation. Rather Goethe believed every act
of looking at a thing turns into observation, every act of observation
turns into mentation, every act of mentation turns into associations.
Thus it is evident we theorize every time we look attentively out into
the world." In support of Goethe, Feyerabend wrote: "Newton... did not
give the explanation [of light] but simply re-described what he
saw...[and] introduced the machinery of the very same theory he wanted
to prove."
For Goethe, the ultimate aim of science was two-fold, both
increase to the database of human knowledge; second, as a method for the
metamorphosis of the experimenter.
In Goethean Science, experiment is the 'mediator between object
[natural phenomena] and subject ]the experimenter].' All experiments
then become two-fold, potentially revealing as much about a natural
phenomena as they reveal the experimenter to him or herself.
Goethe's methodology is mutual and intimate interaction of
observer and observed; and, what transpires over time. Ideally as the
experimenter's observed knowledge grows from his study of natural
phenomena, so does his capacity for inner awareness, insight,
Imagination, Intuition and Inspiration.
Where Cartesian-Newtonian science accepts only a single,
practical syllogism about experimenters and research topics, Goethean
Science demonstrates practicing science as an art, practice directed
towards refining the experimenter's perceptions over time, heightening
them towards Imagination, Inspiration and Intuition.
Goethe's epistemology
Goethe's
method of science as art, of experiment as mediator between
experimenter and Nature, can be applied to studies of every kind. Where
Cartesian-Newtonian science defines and values "expansion of knowledge"
as a logical and linear march towards accumulating facts, Goethean
Science defines and values "expansion of knowledge" as:
1) Observing organic transformation in natural phenomena over time
(historical progression); and
2) Organic transformation of the inner life of the experimenter.
Goethe developed two dynamic concepts – one of polarity (developed in his Chromatology) and one of logical-linear sequence (Morphology). These are applicable across all domains.
For Goethe understanding vital nature (natura naturans) is
very much a function of taking impressions and activating thereby
responses via the Gemüt (empathy, perhaps also compassion) so that one
'becomes what one perceives'. This approach offers a way out of the current nihilism and downward spiral of Cartesian-Newtonian science.
The Kantian view is the realm of quantity and thing is separate
from quality and phenomenon. Therefore, we can never be certain what we
perceive is objectively real.
Goethe's new way of thinking (denken) is a parallel order
of science [more a distinct, separate, more holistic paradigm], useful
for getting past the heavy cognitive curtain erected by Kant, where only
utilitarian ideas and science are valued.
As Amrine states, Goethe accepted the mathematical approach (mathesis)
was appropriate for inert nature. However to become truly human, we
cannot hold mathesis at the center of our life—apart from and dominating
over—rational Feeling. Anything less than truly human values at the
center of our life are inappropriate and counter-productive.
Goethe and the idea of evolution
Goethe writes in Story of My Botanical Studies (1831):
The ever-changing display of plant forms, which I have followed for so many years, awakens increasingly within me the notion: The plant forms which surround us were not all created at some given point in time and then locked into the given form, they have been given… a felicitous mobility and plasticity allowing them to grow and adapt themselves to many different conditions in many different places.
Andrew Dickson White also writes with respect to evolutionary thought, in A History of the Warfare of Science with Theology in Christendom (1896):
About the end of the eighteenth century fruitful suggestions and even clear presentations of this or that part of a large evolutionary doctrine came thick and fast, and from the most divergent quarters. Especially remarkable were those from Erasmus Darwin in England, Maupertuis in France, Oken in Switzerland, and Herder, and, most brilliantly of all, from Goethe in Germany.
Recent research
Arthur Schopenhauer expanded on Goethe's research in optics using a different methodology in his On Vision and Colors.
Rudolf Steiner presents Goethe's approach to science as phenomenological in the Kürschner edition of Goethe's writings. Steiner elaborated on this in the books Goethean Science (1883) and
Theory of Knowledge Implicit in Goethe's World-Conception (1886). in which he emphasizes the need of the perceiving organ of intuition in order to grasp Goethe's biological archetype (i.e. The Typus).
Steiner's branch of Goethean Science was extended by Oskar Schmiedel and Wilhelm Pelikan, who did research using Steiner's interpretations.
Ludwig Wittgenstein's discussions of Goethe's Theory of Colors were published as Bemerkungen über die Farben (Remarks on Color).
He went to an Anglican boarding school and then took biology at Cambridge, studying "life" by killing animals and then grinding them up to extract their DNA. This was troubling. Rescue came when a friend turned him on to Goethe. This old German's 18th century vision of "holistic science" appealed to the young Brit very much. Sheldrake used Goethe to investigate how the lilies of the field actually become lilies of the field.
Sheldrake is famous for the term "morphogenetic field" actually a quote from one of Steiner's students, Poppelbaum.
American philosopher Walter Kaufmann argued that Freud's psychoanalysis was a "poetic science" in Goethe's sense.
In 1998, David Seamon and Arthur Zajonc wrote Goethe's way of science: a phenomenology of nature.
Also in 1998, Henri Bortoft wrote The Wholeness of Nature: Goethe's Science of Conscious Participation in Nature in which he discusses the relevance and importance of Goethe's approach to modern scientific thought.
Biologist Brian Goodwin (1931-2009) in his book How the Leopard Changed Its Spots : The Evolution of Complexity
claimed that organisms as dynamic systems are the primary agents of
creative evolutionary adaptation, in the book Goodwin stated: "The ideas
I am developing in this book are very much in the Goethean spirit."