logic, the law of excluded middle (or the principle of excluded middle) states that for any proposition, either that proposition is true or its negation is true. It is one of the so called three laws of thought, along with the law of noncontradiction, and the law of identity. The law of excluded middle is logically equivalent to the law of noncontradiction by De Morgan's laws. However, no system of logic is built on just these laws, and none of these laws provide inference rules, such as modus ponens or De Morgan's laws.
In
The law is also known as the law (or principle) of the excluded third, in Latin principium tertii exclusi. Another Latin designation for this law is tertium non datur: "no third [possibility] is given". It is a tautology.
The principle should not be confused with the semantical principle of bivalence, which states that every proposition is either true or false.
The principle should not be confused with the semantical principle of bivalence, which states that every proposition is either true or false.
Analogous laws
Some systems of logic have different but analogous laws. For some finite n-valued logics, there is an analogous law called the law of excluded n+1th. If negation is cyclic
and "∨" is a "max operator", then the law can be expressed in the
object language by (P ∨ ~P ∨ ~~P ∨ ... ∨ ~...~P), where "~...~"
represents n−1 negation signs and "∨ ... ∨" n−1 disjunction signs. It is easy to check that the sentence must receive at least one of the n truth values (and not a value that is not one of the n).
Other systems reject the law entirely.
Examples
For example, if P is the proposition:
- Socrates is mortal.
then the law of excluded middle holds that the logical disjunction:
- Either Socrates is mortal, or it is not the case that Socrates is mortal.
is true by virtue of its form alone. That is, the "middle" position,
that Socrates is neither mortal nor not-mortal, is excluded by logic,
and therefore either the first possibility (Socrates is mortal) or its negation (it is not the case that Socrates is mortal) must be true.
An example of an argument that depends on the law of excluded middle follows. We seek to prove that there exist two irrational numbers and such that
- is rational.
It is known that is irrational. Consider the number
- .
Clearly (excluded middle) this number is either rational or irrational. If it is rational, the proof is complete, and
- and .
But if is irrational, then let
- and .
Then
- ,
and 2 is certainly rational. This concludes the proof.
In the above argument, the assertion "this number is either rational or irrational" invokes the law of excluded middle. An intuitionist,
for example, would not accept this argument without further support for
that statement. This might come in the form of a proof that the number
in question is in fact irrational (or rational, as the case may be); or a
finite algorithm that could determine whether the number is rational.
Non-constructive proofs over the infinite
The above proof is an example of a non-constructive proof disallowed by intuitionists:
The proof is non-constructive because it doesn't give specific numbers and that satisfy the theorem but only two separate possibilities, one of which must work. (Actually is irrational but there is no known easy proof of that fact.) (Davis 2000:220)
(Constructive proofs of the specific example above are not hard to produce; for example and are both easily shown to be irrational, and ; a proof allowed by intuitionists).
By non-constructive Davis means that "a proof that there
actually are mathematic entities satisfying certain conditions would not
have to provide a method to exhibit explicitly the entities in
question." (p. 85). Such proofs presume the existence of a totality that
is complete, a notion disallowed by intuitionists when extended to the infinite—for them the infinite can never be completed:
In classical mathematics there occur non-constructive or indirect existence proofs, which intuitionists do not accept. For example, to prove there exists an n such that P(n), the classical mathematician may deduce a contradiction from the assumption for all n, not P(n). Under both the classical and the intuitionistic logic, by reductio ad absurdum this gives not for all n, not P(n). The classical logic allows this result to be transformed into there exists an n such that P(n), but not in general the intuitionistic... the classical meaning, that somewhere in the completed infinite totality of the natural numbers there occurs an n such that P(n), is not available to him, since he does not conceive the natural numbers as a completed totality. (Kleene 1952:49–50)
David Hilbert and Luitzen E. J. Brouwer
both give examples of the law of excluded middle extended to the
infinite. Hilbert's example: "the assertion that either there are only
finitely many prime numbers or there are infinitely many" (quoted in
Davis 2000:97); and Brouwer's: "Every mathematical species is either
finite or infinite." (Brouwer 1923 in van Heijenoort 1967:336).
In general, intuitionists allow the use of the law of excluded
middle when it is confined to discourse over finite collections (sets),
but not when it is used in discourse over infinite sets (e.g. the
natural numbers). Thus intuitionists absolutely disallow the blanket
assertion: "For all propositions P concerning infinite sets D: P or ~P" (Kleene 1952:48).
Putative counterexamples to the law of excluded middle include the liar paradox or Quine's paradox. Certain resolutions of these paradoxes, particularly Graham Priest's dialetheism
as formalised in LP, have the law of excluded middle as a theorem, but
resolve out the Liar as both true and false. In this way, the law of
excluded middle is true, but because truth itself, and therefore
disjunction, is not exclusive, it says next to nothing if one of the
disjuncts is paradoxical, or both true and false.
History
Aristotle
The earliest known formulation is in Aristotle's discussion of the principle of non-contradiction, first proposed in On Interpretation, where he says that of two contradictory propositions (i.e. where one proposition is the negation of the other) one must be true, and the other false. He also states it as a principle in the Metaphysics book 3, saying that it is necessary in every case to affirm or deny, and that it is impossible that there should be anything between the two parts of a contradiction.
Aristotle wrote that ambiguity can arise from the use of ambiguous names, but cannot exist in the facts themselves:
It is impossible, then, that "being a man" should mean precisely "not being a man", if "man" not only signifies something about one subject but also has one significance. ... And it will not be possible to be and not to be the same thing, except in virtue of an ambiguity, just as if one whom we call "man", and others were to call "not-man"; but the point in question is not this, whether the same thing can at the same time be and not be a man in name, but whether it can be in fact. (Metaphysics 4.4, W.D. Ross (trans.), GBWW 8, 525–526).
Aristotle's assertion that "...it will not be possible to be and not
to be the same thing", which would be written in propositional logic as
¬(P ∧ ¬P), is a statement modern logicians could call the law of excluded middle (P ∨ ¬P),
as distribution of the negation of Aristotle's assertion makes them
equivalent, regardless that the former claims that no statement is both true and false, while the latter requires that any statement is either true or false.
However, Aristotle also writes, "since it is impossible that
contradictories should be at the same time true of the same thing,
obviously contraries also cannot belong at the same time to the same
thing" (Book IV, CH 6, p. 531). He then proposes that "there cannot be
an intermediate between contradictories, but of one subject we must
either affirm or deny any one predicate" (Book IV, CH 7, p. 531). In the
context of Aristotle's traditional logic, this is a remarkably precise statement of the law of excluded middle, P ∨ ¬P.
Also in On Interpretation, Aristotle seemed to deny the law of excluded middle in the case of future contingents, in his discussion on the sea battle.
Leibniz
Its usual form, "Every judgment is either true or false" [footnote 9]..."(from Kolmogorov in van Heijenoort, p. 421) footnote 9: "This is Leibniz's very simple formulation (see Nouveaux Essais, IV,2)...." (ibid p 421)
Bertrand Russell and Principia Mathematica
The principle was stated as a theorem of propositional logic by Russell and Whitehead in Principia Mathematica as:
.
So just what is "truth" and "falsehood"? At the opening PM quickly announces some definitions:
Truth-values. The "truth-value" of a proposition is truth if it is true and falsehood if it is false* [*This phrase is due to Frege]...the truth-value of "p ∨ q" is truth if the truth-value of either p or q is truth, and is falsehood otherwise ... that of "~ p" is the opposite of that of p..." (p. 7-8)
This is not much help. But later, in a much deeper discussion,
("Definition and systematic ambiguity of Truth and Falsehood" Chapter II
part III, p. 41 ff ) PM defines truth and falsehood in terms of a
relationship between the "a" and the "b" and the "percipient". For
example "This 'a' is 'b'" (e.g. "This 'object a' is 'red'") really means
"'object a' is a sense-datum" and "'red' is a sense-datum", and they
"stand in relation" to one another and in relation to "I". Thus what we
really mean is: "I perceive that 'This object a is red'" and this is an
undeniable-by-3rd-party "truth".
PM further defines a distinction between a "sense-datum" and a "sensation":
That is, when we judge (say) "this is red", what occurs is a relation of three terms, the mind, and "this", and "red". On the other hand, when we perceive "the redness of this", there is a relation of two terms, namely the mind and the complex object "the redness of this" (pp. 43–44).
Russell reiterated his distinction between "sense-datum" and "sensation" in his book The Problems of Philosophy (1912) published at the same time as PM (1910–1913):
Let us give the name of "sense-data" to the things that are immediately known in sensation: such things as colours, sounds, smells, hardnesses, roughnesses, and so on. We shall give the name "sensation" to the experience of being immediately aware of these things... The colour itself is a sense-datum, not a sensation. (p. 12)
Russell further described his reasoning behind his definitions of "truth" and "falsehood" in the same book (Chapter XII Truth and Falsehood).
Consequences of the law of excluded middle in Principia Mathematica
From the law of excluded middle, formula ✸2.1 in Principia Mathematica, Whitehead and Russell derive some of the most powerful tools in the logician's argumentation toolkit. (In Principia Mathematica, formulas and propositions are identified by a leading asterisk and two numbers, such as "✸2.1".)
✸2.1 ~p ∨ p "This is the Law of excluded middle" (PM, p. 101).
The proof of ✸2.1 is roughly as follows: "primitive idea" 1.08 defines p → q = ~p ∨ q. Substituting p for q in this rule yields p → p = ~p ∨ p. Since p → p is true (this is Theorem 2.08, which is proved separately), then ~p ∨ p must be true.
✸2.11 p ∨ ~p (Permutation of the assertions is allowed by axiom 1.4)
✸2.12 p → ~(~p) (Principle of double negation, part 1: if
"this rose is red" is true then it's not true that "'this rose is
not-red' is true".)
✸2.13 p ∨ ~{~(~p)} (Lemma together with 2.12 used to derive 2.14)
✸2.14 ~(~p) → p (Principle of double negation, part 2)
✸2.15 (~p → q) → (~q → p) (One of the four "Principles of transposition". Similar to 1.03, 1.16 and 1.17. A very long demonstration was required here.)
✸2.15 (~p → q) → (~q → p) (One of the four "Principles of transposition". Similar to 1.03, 1.16 and 1.17. A very long demonstration was required here.)
✸2.16 (p → q) → (~q → ~p) (If it's true that
"If this rose is red then this pig flies" then it's true that "If this
pig doesn't fly then this rose isn't red.")
✸2.17 ( ~p → ~q ) → (q → p) (Another of the "Principles of transposition".)
✸2.18 (~p → p) → p (Called "The complement of reductio ad absurdum. It states that a proposition which follows from the hypothesis of its own falsehood is true" (PM, pp. 103–104).)
Most of these theorems—in particular ✸2.1, ✸2.11, and ✸2.14—are
rejected by intuitionism. These tools are recast into another form that
Kolmogorov cites as "Hilbert's four axioms of implication" and
"Hilbert's two axioms of negation" (Kolmogorov in van Heijenoort,
p. 335).
Propositions ✸2.12 and ✸2.14, "double negation":
The intuitionist writings of L. E. J. Brouwer refer to what he calls "the principle of the reciprocity of the multiple species,
that is, the principle that for every system the correctness of a
property follows from the impossibility of the impossibility of this
property" (Brouwer, ibid, p. 335).
This principle is commonly called "the principle of double negation" (PM, pp. 101–102). From the law of excluded middle (✸2.1 and ✸2.11), PM derives principle ✸2.12 immediately. We substitute ~p for p in 2.11 to yield ~p ∨ ~(~p),
and by the definition of implication (i.e. 1.01 p → q = ~p ∨ q) then ~p
∨ ~(~p)= p → ~(~p). QED (The derivation of 2.14 is a bit more
involved.)
Reichenbach
It is correct, at least for bivalent logic—i.e. it can be seen with a Karnaugh map—that this law removes "the middle" of the inclusive-or used in his law (3). And this is the point of Reichenbach's demonstration that some believe the exclusive-or should take the place of the inclusive-or.
About this issue (in admittedly very technical terms) Reichenbach observes:
-
- The tertium non datur
- 29. (x)[f(x) ∨ ~f(x)]
- is not exhaustive in its major terms and is therefore an inflated formula. This fact may perhaps explain why some people consider it unreasonable to write (29) with the inclusive-'or', and want to have it written with the sign of the exclusive-'or'
-
- 30. (x)[f(x) ⊕ ~f(x)], where the symbol "⊕" signifies exclusive-or
- in which form it would be fully exhaustive and therefore nomological in the narrower sense. (Reichenbach, p. 376)
In line (30) the "(x)" means "for all" or "for every", a form used by Russell and Reichenbach; today the symbolism is usually x. Thus an example of the expression would look like this:
- (pig): (Flies(pig) ⊕ ~Flies(pig))
- (For all instances of "pig" seen and unseen): ("Pig does fly" or "Pig does not fly" but not both simultaneously)
Logicists versus the intuitionists
In late 1800s through the 1930s a bitter, persistent debate raged between Hilbert and his followers versus Hermann Weyl and L. E. J. Brouwer. Brouwer's philosophy, called intuitionism, started in earnest with Leopold Kronecker in the late 1800s.
Hilbert intensely disliked Kronecker's ideas:
...Kronecker insisted that there could be no existence without construction. For him, as for Paul Gordan [another elderly mathematician], Hilbert's proof of the finiteness of the basis of the invariant system was simply not mathematics. Hilbert, on the other hand, throughout his life was to insist that if one can prove that the attributes assigned to a concept will never lead to a contradiction, the mathematical existence of the concept is thereby established (Reid p. 34)
It was his [Kronecker's] contention that nothing could be said to have mathematical existence unless it could actually be constructed with a finite number of positive integers (Reid p. 26)
The debate had a profound effect on Hilbert. Reid indicates that Hilbert's second problem (one of Hilbert's problems from the Second International Conference in Paris in 1900) evolved from this debate (italics in the original):
-
- In his second problem [Hilbert] had asked for a mathematical proof of the consistency of the axioms of the arithmetic of real numbers.
- To show the significance of this problem, he added the following observation:
- "If contradictory attributes be assigned to a concept, I say that mathematically the concept does not exist"... (Reid p. 71)
Thus Hilbert was saying: "If p and ~p are both shown to be true, then p does not exist" and he was thereby invoking the law of excluded middle cast into the form of the law of contradiction.
And finally constructivists ... restricted mathematics to the study of concrete operations on finite or potentially (but not actually) infinite structures; completed infinite totalities ... were rejected, as were indirect proof based on the Law of Excluded Middle. Most radical among the constructivists were the intuitionists, led by the erstwhile topologist L. E. J. Brouwer ... (Dawson p. 49)
The rancorous debate continued through the early 1900s into the
1920s; in 1927 Brouwer complained about "polemicizing against it
[intuitionism] in sneering tones" (Brouwer in van Heijenoort, p. 492).
However, the debate had been fertile: it had resulted in Principia Mathematica
(1910–1913), and that work gave a precise definition to the law of
excluded middle, and all this provided an intellectual setting and the
tools necessary for the mathematicians of the early twentieth century:
Out of the rancor, and spawned in part by it, there arose several important logical developments...Zermelo's axiomatization of set theory (1908a) ... that was followed two years later by the first volume of Principia Mathematica ... in which Russell and Whitehead showed how, via the theory of types, much of arithmetic could be developed by logicist means (Dawson p. 49)
Brouwer reduced the debate to the use of proofs designed from "negative" or "non-existence" versus "constructive" proof:
-
- According to Brouwer, a statement that an object exists having a given property means that, and is only proved, when a method is known which in principle at least will enable such an object to be found or constructed...
- Hilbert naturally disagreed.
- "...pure existence proofs have been the most important landmarks in the historical development of our science," he maintained. (Reid p. 155)
-
- Brouwer ... refused to accept the logical principle of the excluded middle... His argument was the following:
-
- "Suppose that A is the statement "There exists a member of the set S having the property P." If the set is finite, it is possible—in principle—to examine each member of S and determine whether there is a member of S with the property P or that every member of S lacks the property P. For finite sets, therefore, Brouwer accepted the principle of the excluded middle as valid. He refused to accept it for infinite sets because if the set S is infinite, we cannot—even in principle—examine each member of the set. If, during the course of our examination, we find a member of the set with the property P, the first alternative is substantiated; but if we never find such a member, the second alternative is still not substantiated.
- Since mathematical theorems are often proved by establishing that the negation would involve us in a contradiction, this third possibility which Brouwer suggested would throw into question many of the mathematical statements currently accepted.
- "Taking the Principle of the Excluded Middle from the mathematician," Hilbert said, "is the same as ... prohibiting the boxer the use of his fists."
- "The possible loss did not seem to bother Weyl... Brouwer's program was the coming thing, he insisted to his friends in Zürich." (Reid, p. 149)}}
In his lecture in 1941 at Yale and the subsequent paper Gödel
proposed a solution: "...that the negation of a universal proposition
was to be understood as asserting the existence ... of a counterexample"
(Dawson, p. 157))
Gödel's approach to the law of excluded middle was to assert that
objections against "the use of 'impredicative definitions'" "carried
more weight" than "the law of excluded middle and related theorems of
the propositional calculus" (Dawson p. 156). He proposed his "system Σ
... and he concluded by mentioning several applications of his
interpretation. Among them were a proof of the consistency with intuitionistic logic of the principle ~ (∀A: (A ∨ ~A)) (despite the inconsistency of the assumption ∃ A: ~ (A ∨ ~A)..." (Dawson, p. 157)
The debate seemed to weaken: mathematicians, logicians and
engineers continue to use the law of excluded middle (and double
negation) in their daily work.
Intuitionist definitions of the law (principle) of excluded middle
The
following highlights the deep mathematical and philosophic problem
behind what it means to "know", and also helps elucidate what the "law"
implies (i.e. what the law really means). Their difficulties with the
law emerges: that they do not want to accept as true, implications drawn
from that which is unverifiable (untestable, unknowable) or from the
impossible or the false. (All quotes are from van Heijenoort, italics
added).
Brouwer offers his definition of "principle of excluded middle"; we see here also the issue of "testability":
-
- On the basis of the testability just mentioned, there hold, for properties conceived within a specific finite main system, the "principle of excluded middle", that is, the principle that for every system every property is either correct [richtig] or impossible, and in particular the principle of the reciprocity of the complementary species, that is, the principle that for every system the correctness of a property follows from the impossibility of the impossibility of this property. (335)
Kolmogorov's definition cites Hilbert's two axioms of negation
- A → (~A → B)
- (A → B) → { (~A → B) → B}
-
- Hilbert's first axiom of negation, "anything follows from the false", made its appearance only with the rise of symbolic logic, as did the first axiom of implication.... while... the axiom under consideration [axiom 5] asserts something about the consequences of something impossible: we have to accept B if the true judgment A is regarded as false...
- Hilbert's second axiom of negation expresses the principle of excluded middle. The principle is expressed here in the form in which is it used for derivations: if B follows from A as well as from ~A, then B is true. Its usual form, "every judgment is either true or false" is equivalent to that given above".
- From the first interpretation of negation, that is, the interdiction from regarding the judgment as true, it is impossible to obtain the certitude that the principle of excluded middle is true... Brouwer showed that in the case of such transfinite judgments the principle of excluded middle cannot be considered obvious
- footnote 9: "This is Leibniz's very simple formulation (see Nouveaux Essais, IV,2). The formulation "A is either B or not-B" has nothing to do with the logic of judgments.
- footnote 10: "Symbolically the second form is expessed thus
- A ∨ ~A
where ∨ means "or". The equivalence of the two forms is easily proved... (p. 421)
Criticisms
Many modern logic systems replace the law of excluded middle with the concept of negation as failure. Instead of a proposition's being either true or false, a proposition is either true or not able to be proved true. These two dichotomies only differ in logical systems that are not complete. The principle of negation as failure is used as a foundation for autoepistemic logic, and is widely used in logic programming. In these systems, the programmer is free to assert the law of excluded middle as a true fact, but it is not built-in a priori into these systems.
Mathematicians such as L. E. J. Brouwer and Arend Heyting have also contested the usefulness of the law of excluded middle in the context of modern mathematics.
In mathematical logic
In modern mathematical logic, the excluded middle has been shown to result in possible self-contradiction.
It is possible in logic to make well-constructed propositions that can
be neither true nor false; a common example of this is the "Liar's paradox", the statement "this statement is false", which can itself be neither true nor false. In set theory,
such a self-referential paradox can be constructed by examining the set
"the set of all sets that do not contain themselves". This set is
unambiguously defined, but leads to a Russell's paradox: does the set contain, as one of its elements, itself? However, in the modern Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory, this type of contradiction is no longer admitted.