In evolutionary biology, inclusive fitness is one of two metrics of evolutionary success as defined by W. D. Hamilton in 1964:
- Personal fitness is the number of offspring that an individual begets (regardless of who rescues/rears/supports them)
- Inclusive fitness is the number of offspring equivalents that an individual rears, rescues or otherwise supports through its behaviour (regardless of who begets them)
From the gene's point of view, evolutionary success ultimately depends on leaving behind the maximum number of copies of itself in the population. Prior to Hamilton's work, it was generally assumed that genes only achieved this through the number of viable offspring produced by the individual organism they occupied. However, this overlooked a wider consideration of a gene's success, most clearly in the case of the social insects where the vast majority of individuals do not produce (their own) offspring.
Overview
Hamilton
showed mathematically that, because other members of a population may
share one's genes, a gene can also increase its evolutionary success by
indirectly promoting the reproduction and survival of other individuals
who also carry that gene. This is variously called "kin theory", "kin
selection theory" or "inclusive fitness theory". The most obvious
category of such individuals is close genetic relatives, and where these
are concerned, the application of inclusive fitness theory is often
more straightforwardly treated via the narrower kin selection theory.
Hamilton's theory, alongside reciprocal altruism,
is considered one of the two primary mechanisms for the evolution of
social behaviors in natural species and a major contribution to the
field of sociobiology,
which holds that some behaviors can be dictated by genes, and therefore
can be passed to future generations and may be selected for as the
organism evolves.
Although described in seemingly anthropomorphic terms, these
ideas apply to all living things, and can describe the evolution of
innate and learned behaviors over a wide range of species including
insects, small mammals or humans.
Belding's ground squirrel
provides an example. The ground squirrel gives an alarm call to warn
its local group of the presence of a predator. By emitting the alarm, it
gives its own location away, putting itself in more danger. In the
process, however, the squirrel may protect its relatives within the
local group (along with the rest of the group). Therefore, if the effect
of the trait influencing the alarm call typically protects the other
squirrels in the immediate area, it will lead to the passing on of more
copies of the alarm call trait in the next generation than the squirrel
could leave by reproducing on its own. In such a case natural selection
will increase the trait that influences giving the alarm call, provided
that a sufficient fraction of the shared genes include the gene(s)
predisposing to the alarm call.
Synalpheus regalis, a eusocial shrimp,
also is an example of an organism whose social traits meet the
inclusive fitness criterion. The larger defenders protect the young
juveniles in the colony from outsiders. By ensuring the young's
survival, the genes will continue to be passed on to future generations.
Inclusive fitness is more generalized than strict kin selection, which requires that the shared genes are identical by descent. Inclusive fitness is not limited to cases where "kin" ('close genetic relatives') are involved.
Hamilton's rule
In
the context of sociobiology, Hamilton proposed that inclusive fitness
offers a mechanism for the evolution of altruism. He claimed that this
leads natural selection to favor organisms that behave in ways that
correlate with maximizing their inclusive fitness. If a gene (or gene
complex) promoting altruistic behavior has copies of itself in others,
helping those others survive ensures that the genes will be passed on.
Hamilton's rule describes mathematically whether or not a gene for altruistic behavior will spread in a population:
where
- is the probability, above the population average, of the individuals sharing an altruistic gene – commonly viewed as "degree of relatedness".
- is the reproductive benefit to the recipient of the altruistic behavior, and
- is the reproductive cost to the altruist,
Gardner et al. (2007) suggest that Hamilton's rule can be
applied to multi-locus models, but that it should be done at the point
of interpreting theory, rather than the starting point of enquiry.
They suggest that one should "use standard population genetics, game
theory, or other methodologies to derive a condition for when the social
trait of interest is favored by selection and then use Hamilton's rule
as an aid for conceptualizing this result".
Altruism
The concept serves to explain how natural selection can perpetuate altruism.
If there is an "altruism gene" (or complex of genes) that influences an
organism's behavior to be helpful and protective of relatives and their
offspring, this behavior also increases the proportion of the altruism
gene in the population, because relatives are likely to share genes with
the altruist due to common descent.
In formal terms, if such a complex of genes arises, Hamilton's rule
(rbc) specifies the selective criteria (in terms of cost, benefit and
relatedness) for such a trait to increase in frequency in the
population. Hamilton noted that inclusive fitness theory does not by itself predict
that a species will necessarily evolve such altruistic behaviors, since
an opportunity or context for interaction between individuals is a more
primary and necessary requirement in order for any social interaction
to occur in the first place. As Hamilton put it, "Altruistic or
selfish acts are only possible when a suitable social object is
available. In this sense behaviours are conditional from the start." (Hamilton 1987, 420).
In other words, whilst inclusive fitness theory specifies a set of
necessary criteria for the evolution of altruistic traits, it does not
specify a sufficient condition for their evolution in any given species.
More primary necessary criteria include the existence of gene complexes
for altruistic traits in gene pool, as mentioned above, and especially
that "a suitable social object is available", as Hamilton noted. Paul
Sherman, who has contributed much research on the ground squirrels
mentioned above, gives a fuller discussion of Hamilton's latter point:
To understand any species' pattern of nepotism, two questions about individuals' behavior must be considered: (1) what is reproductively ideal?, and (2) what is socially possible? With his formulation of "inclusive fitness," Hamilton suggested a mathematical way of answering (1). Here I suggest that the answer to (2) depends on demography, particularly its spatial component, dispersal, and its temporal component, mortality. Only when ecological circumstances affecting demography consistently make it socially possible will nepotism be elaborated according to what is reproductively ideal. For example, if dispersing is advantageous and if it usually separates relatives permanently, as in many birds (Nice 1937: 180-187; Gross 1940; Robertson 1969), on the rare occasions when nestmates or other kin live in proximity, they will not preferentially cooperate. Similarly, nepotism will not be elaborated among relatives that have infrequently coexisted in a population's or a species' evolutionary history. If an animal's life history characteristics (Stearns 1976; Warner this volume) usually preclude the existence of certain relatives, that is if kin are usually unavailable, the rare coexistence of such kin will not occasion preferential treatment. For example, if reproductives generally die soon after zygotes are formed, as in many temperate zone insects, the unusual individual that survives to interact with its offspring is not expected to behave parentally. (Sherman 1980, 530, underlining in original)
The occurrence of sibling cannibalism in several species
underlines the point that inclusive fitness theory should not be
understood to simply predict that genetically related individuals will
inevitably recognize and engage in positive social behaviors towards
genetic relatives. Only in species that have the appropriate traits in
their gene pool, and in which individuals typically interacted with
genetic relatives in the natural conditions of their evolutionary
history, will social behavior potentially be elaborated, and
consideration of the evolutionarily typical demographic composition of
grouping contexts of that species is thus a first step in understanding
how selection pressures upon inclusive fitness have shaped the forms of
its social behavior. Dawkins gives a simplified illustration:
If families [genetic relatives] happen to go around in groups, this fact provides a useful rule of thumb for kin selection: 'care for any individual you often see'." (Dawkins 1979, 187)
Evidence from a variety of species including humans, primates, and other social mammals
suggests that contextual cues (such as familiarity) are often
significant proximate mechanisms mediating the expression of altruistic
behavior, regardless of whether the participants are always in fact
genetic relatives or not. This is nevertheless evolutionarily stable
since selection pressure acts on the typical conditions, not on the rare occasions where actual genetic relatedness differs from that normally encountered (see Sherman above). Inclusive fitness theory thus does not imply that organisms evolve to direct altruism towards genetic relatives. Many popular treatments do however promote this interpretation, as illustrated in a recent review:
[M]any misunderstandings persist. In many cases, they result from conflating "coefficient of relatedness" and "proportion of shared genes," which is a short step from the intuitively appealing—but incorrect—interpretation that "animals tend to be altruistic toward those with whom they share a lot of genes." These misunderstandings don't just crop up occasionally; they are repeated in many writings, including undergraduate psychology textbooks—most of them in the field of social psychology, within sections describing evolutionary approaches to altruism. (Park 2007, p860)
Such misunderstandings of inclusive fitness' implications for the
study of altruism, even amongst professional biologists utilizing the
theory, are widespread, prompting prominent theorists to regularly
attempt to highlight and clarify the mistakes. Here is one recent example of attempted clarification from West et al. (2010):
In his original papers on inclusive fitness theory, Hamilton pointed out a sufficiently high relatedness to favour altruistic behaviours could accrue in two ways—kin discrimination or limited dispersal (Hamilton, 1964, 1971,1972, 1975). There is a huge theoretical literature on the possible role of limited dispersal reviewed by Platt & Bever (2009) and West et al. (2002a), as well as experimental evolution tests of these models (Diggle et al., 2007; Griffin et al., 2004; Kümmerli et al., 2009 ). However, despite this, it is still sometimes claimed that kin selection requires kin discrimination (Oates & Wilson, 2001; Silk, 2002 ). Furthermore, a large number of authors appear to have implicitly or explicitly assumed that kin discrimination is the only mechanism by which altruistic behaviours can be directed towards relatives... [T]here is a huge industry of papers reinventing limited dispersal as an explanation for cooperation. The mistakes in these areas seem to stem from the incorrect assumption that kin selection or indirect fitness benefits require kin discrimination (misconception 5), despite the fact that Hamilton pointed out the potential role of limited dispersal in his earliest papers on inclusive fitness theory (Hamilton, 1964; Hamilton, 1971; Hamilton, 1972; Hamilton, 1975). (West et al. 2010, p.243 and supplement)
Green-beard effects
As well as interactions in reliable contexts of genetic relatedness,
altruists may also have some way to recognize altruistic behavior in
unrelated individuals and be inclined to support them. As Dawkins points
out in The Selfish Gene (Chapter 6) and The Extended Phenotype, this must be distinguished from the green-beard effect.
The green-beard effect is the act of a gene (or several closely linked gene), that:
- Produces a phenotype.
- Allows recognition of that phenotype in others.
- Causes the individual to preferentially treat other individuals with the same gene.
The green-beard effect was originally a thought experiment by Hamilton in his publications on inclusive fitness in 1964,
although it hadn't yet been observed. As of today, it has been observed
in few species. Its rarity is probably due to its susceptibility to
'cheating' whereby individuals can gain the trait that confers the
advantage, without the altruistic behavior. This normally would occur
via the crossing over of chromosomes which happens frequently, often
rendering the green-beard effect a transient state. However, Wang et al.
has shown in one of the species where the effect is common (fire ants),
recombination cannot occur due to a large genetic transversion,
essentially forming a supergene. This, along with homozygote inviability
at the green-beard loci allows for the extended maintenance of the
green-beard effect.
Equally, cheaters may not be able to invade the green-beard
population if the mechanism for preferential treatment and the phenotype
are intrinsically linked. In budding yeast (Saccharomyces cerevisiae),
the dominant allele FLO1 is responsible for flocculation
(self-adherence between cells) which helps protect them against harmful
substances such as ethanol. While 'cheater' yeast cells occasionally
find their way into the biofilm-like substance that is formed from FLO1
expressing yeast, they cannot invade as the FLO1 expressing yeast will
not bind to them in return, and thus the phenotype is intrinsically
linked to the preference.
Parental care
In The Selfish Gene, Dawkins reported that some question the
idea that parental investment (parental care) contributes to inclusive
fitness. The distinctions between the kind of beneficiaries nurtured
(collateral versus descendant relatives) and the kind of fitnesses used
(inclusive versus personal) in the parsing of nature are independent
concepts. This orthogonality can best be understood in a thought
experiment: Consider a model of a population of animals such as crocodiles or tangle web spiders.
Some species or populations of these spiders and reptiles exhibit
parental care, while closely related species or populations lack it.
Assume that in these animals a gene, called a, codes for parental care,
and its other allele, called A, codes for an absence thereof. The aa
homozygotes care for their young, and AA homozygotes don't, and the
heterozygotes behave like aa homozygotes if a is dominant, and like AA
homozygotes if A is dominant, or exhibit some kind of intermediate
behavior if there is partial dominance. Other kinds of animals could be
considered in which all individuals exhibit parental care, but variation
among them would be in the quantity and quality thereof.
If one considers a life cycle as extending from conception to
conception, and an animal is an offspring of parents with poor parental
care, then the higher mortality with poor care could be considered a
diminution of the offspring's expected fitness.
Alternatively, if one considers the life cycle as extending from
weaning to weaning, the same mortality would be considered a diminution
in the parents' fecundity, and therefore a diminution of the parent's
fitness.
In Hamilton's paradigm, fitnesses calculated according to in the
weaning-to-weaning perspective are inclusive fitnesses, and fitnesses
calculated in the conception-to-conception perspective are personal
fitnesses. This distinction is independent of whether the altruism
involved in child rearing is toward descendants or toward collateral
relatives, as when aunts and uncle rear their nieces and nephews.
Inclusive fitness theory was developed in order to better
understand collateral altruism, but this does not mean that it is
limited to collateral altruism. It applies just as well to parental
care. Which perspective one chooses does not affect the animals but just
one's understanding.
Parent offspring conflict and optimization
Early
writings on inclusive fitness theory (including Hamilton 1964) used K
in place of B/C. Thus Hamilton's rule was expressed as
is the necessary and sufficient condition for selection for altruism.
Where B is the gain to the beneficiary, C is the cost to the
actor and r is the number of its own offspring equivalents the actor
expects in one of the offspring of the beneficiary. r is either called
the coefficient of relatedness or coefficient of relationship, depending
on how it is computed. The method of computing has changed over time,
as has the terminology. It is not clear whether or not changes in the
terminology followed changes in computation.
Robert L. Trivers (1974) defined "parent-offspring conflict" as any case where
i.e., K is between 1 and 2. The benefit is greater than the cost, but is less than twice the cost.
In this case, the parent would wish the offspring to behave as if
r is 1 between siblings, although it is actually presumed to be 1/2 or
closely approximated by 1/2.
In other words, a parent would wish its offspring to give up ten
offspring in order to raise 11 nieces and nephews. The offspring, when
not manipulated by the parent, would require at least 21 nieces and
nephews to justify the sacrifice of 10 of its own offspring.
The parent is trying to maximize its number of grandchildren,
while the offspring is trying to maximize the number of its own
offspring equivalents (via offspring and nieces and nephews) it
produces. If the parent cannot manipulate the offspring and therefore
loses in the conflict, the grandparents with the fewest grandchildren
seem to be selected for. In other words, if the parent has no influence
on the offspring's behavior, grandparents with fewer grandchildren
increase in frequency in the population.
By extension, parents with the fewest offspring will also increase in frequency.
This seems to go against Ronald A. Fisher's "Fundamental Theorem
of Natural Selection" which states that the change in fitness over the
course of a generation equals the variance in fitness at the beginning
of the generation. Variance is defined as the square of a quantity—
standard deviation — and as a square must always be positive (or zero).
That would imply that e fitness could never decrease as time passes.
This goes along with the intuitive idea that you can't select for lower
fitness.
During parent-offspring conflict the number of stranger equivalents reared per offspring equivalents reared is going down.
It is considerations of this phenomenon that have caused Orlove (1979) and Grafen (2006) to say that nothing is being maximized.
According to Trivers (1974), if Freud had tried to explain
intra-family conflict after Hamilton instead of before him, he would
have attributed the motivation for the conflict and for the
to resource allocation issues rather than
sexual jealousy.
Incidentally, when k=1 or k=2, the average number of offspring
per parent stays constant as time goes by. When k<1 k="" or="">2 then
the average number of offspring per parent increases as time goes by.
1>
The term "gene" can refer to a locus (location) on an organism's
DNA—a section that codes for a particular trait. Alternative versions of
the code at that location are called "alleles." If there are two
alleles at a locus, one of which codes for altruism and the other for
selfishness, an individual who has one of each is said to be a
heterozygote at that locus. If the heterozygote uses half of its
resources raising its own offspring and the other half helping its
siblings raise theirs, that condition is called codominance. If there is
codominance the "2" in the above argument is exactly 2.
If by contrast the altruism allele is more dominant, then the 2
in the above would be replaced by a number smaller than 2. If the
selfishness allele is the more dominant, something greater than 2 would
replace the 2. (Orlove 1975)
Criticism
A 2010 paper by Martin Nowak, Corina Tarnita, and E. O. Wilson
suggested that standard natural selection theory is superior to
inclusive fitness theory, stating that the interactions between cost and
benefit cannot be explained only in terms of relatedness. This, Nowak
said, makes Hamilton's rule at worst superfluous and at best ad hoc.
Gardner in turn was critical of the paper, describing it as "a really
terrible article", and along with other co-authors has written a reply,
submitted to Nature.
In work prior to Nowak et al. (2010), various authors derived different versions of a formula for , all designed to preserve Hamilton's rule. Orlove noted that if a formula for
is defined so as to ensure that Hamilton's rule is preserved, then the
approach is by definition ad hoc. However, he published an unrelated
derivation of the same formula for
– a derivation designed to preserve two statements about the rate of
selection – which on its own was similarly ad hoc. Orlove argued that
the existence of two unrelated derivations of the formula for reduces or eliminates the ad hoc nature of the formula, and of inclusive fitness theory as well. The derivations were demonstrated to be unrelated by corresponding parts of the two identical formulae for
being derived from the genotypes of different individuals. The parts
that were derived from the genotypes of different individuals were terms
to the right of the minus sign in the covariances in the two versions
of the formula for .
By contrast, the terms left of the minus sign in both derivations come
from the same source.
One study suggest the c/b ratio be considered as a continuum of this
behavioral trait rather than discontinuous in nature. From this approach
fitness transactions can be better observed because there is more to
what is happening to affect an individual's fitness than just losing and
gaining (Engles, W.R. 1982).