A photon rocket is a rocket that uses thrust from the momentum of emitted photons (radiation pressure by emission) for its propulsion. Photon rockets have been discussed as a propulsion system that could
make interstellar flight possible during a human lifetime, which
requires the ability to propel spacecraft to speeds at least 10% of the speed of light, v ≈ 0.1c = 30,000 km/s. Photon
propulsion has been considered to be one of the best available
interstellar propulsion concepts, because it is founded on established
physics and technologies. Traditional photon rockets are proposed to be powered by onboard generators, as in the nuclear photonic rocket.
The standard textbook case of such a rocket is the ideal case where all
of the fuel is converted to photons which are radiated in the same
direction. In more realistic treatments, one takes into account that the
beam of photons is not perfectly collimated,
that not all of the fuel is converted to photons, and so on. A large
amount of fuel would be required and the rocket would be a huge vessel.
The limitations posed by the rocket equation can be overcome, as long as the reaction mass is not carried by the spacecraft. In beamed laser propulsion
(BLP), the photon generators and the spacecraft are physically
separated and the photons are beamed from the photon source to the
spacecraft using lasers. However, BLP is limited because of the
extremely low thrust generation efficiency of photon reflection. One of
the best ways to overcome the inherent inefficiency in producing thrust
of the photon thruster is by amplifying the momentum transfer of
photons by recycling photons between two high reflectance mirrors, one
being stationary, or on a thruster, the other being the "sail".
Speed
The
speed an ideal photon rocket will reach (in the reference frame in
which the rocket was at rest initially), in the absence of external
forces, depends on the ratio of its initial and final mass:
where is the initial mass and is the final mass.
For example, assuming a spaceship is equipped with a pure helium-3 fusion reactor and has an initial mass of 2300 kg, including 1000 kg of helium-3 – meaning, 2.3 kg will be converted to energy – and assuming all this energy is emitted as photons in the direction
opposing the direction of travel, and assuming the fusion products (helium-4 and hydrogen) are kept on board, the final mass will be (2300 − 2.3) kg =2297.7 kg
and the spaceship will reach a speed of 1/1000 of the speed of light.
If the fusion products are released into space, the speed will be
higher, but the above equation cannot be used to compute it, because it
assumes that all decrease in mass is converted into energy.
The gamma factor corresponding to a photon rocket speed has the simple expression:
At 10% the speed of light, the gamma factor is about 1.005, implying is very nearly 0.9.
Derivation
We denote the four-momentum of the rocket at rest as , the rocket after it has burned its fuel as , and the four-momentum of the emitted photons as . Conservation of four-momentum implies:
squaring both sides (i.e. taking the Lorentz inner product of both sides with themselves) gives:
According to the energy-momentum relation, the square of the four-momentum equals the square of the mass, and because photons have zero mass.
As we start in the rest frame (i.e. the zero-momentum frame) of the rocket, the initial four-momentum of the rocket is:
while the final four-momentum is:
Therefore, taking the Minkowski inner product (see four-vector), we get:
We can now solve for the gamma factor, obtaining:
Maximum speed limit
Standard
theory says that the theoretical speed limit of a photon rocket is
below the speed of light. Haug has recently suggested a maximum speed limit for an ideal photon rocket that is just below the
speed of light. However, his claims have been contested by Tommasini et al., because such velocity is formulated for the relativistic mass and is therefore frame-dependent.
Regardless of the photon generator characteristics, onboard
photon rockets powered with nuclear fission and fusion have speed limits
from the efficiency of these processes. Here it is assumed that the
propulsion system has a single stage. Suppose the total mass of the
photon rocket/spacecraft is M that includes fuels with a mass of αM with α < 1. Assuming the fuel mass to propulsion-system energy conversion efficiencyγ and the propulsion-system energy to photon energy conversion efficiency δ ≪ 1, the maximum total photon energy generated for propulsion, Ep, is given by
If the total photon flux can be directed at 100% efficiency to generate thrust, the total photon thrust, Tp, is given by
The maximum attainable spacecraft velocity, Vmax, of the photon propulsion system for Vmax ≪ c, is given by
For example, the approximate maximum velocities achievable by onboard
nuclear powered photon rockets with assumed parameters are given in
Table 1. The maximum velocity limits by such nuclear powered rockets are
less than 0.02% of the light velocity (60 km/s). Therefore, onboard
nuclear photon rockets are unsuitable for interstellar missions.
Maximum velocity obtainable by photon rockets with onboard nuclear photon generators with exemplary parameters
Energy source
α
γ
δ
vmax/c
vmax (m/s)
Fission
0.1
10−3
0.5
5 × 10−5
15 000
Fusion
0.1
4 × 10−3
0.5
2 × 10−4
60 000
The beamed laser propulsion,
such as photonic laser thruster, however, in principle can provide the
maximum spacecraft velocity approaching the speed of light, c.
Students and teachers in Ghana in a parade for inclusive education.Cienfuegos, a non-profit group teaching art to people with disabilities in Cuba.
Universal access to education is the ability of all people to have equal opportunity in education, regardless of their social class, race, gender, sexuality, ethnic background or physical and mental disabilities. The term is used both in college admission for the middle and lower classes, and in assistive technology for the disabled. Some critics feel that this practice in higher education, as opposed to a strict meritocracy, causes lower academic standards. In order to facilitate the access of education to all, countries have right to education.
Universal access to education encourages a variety of pedagogical
approaches to accomplish the dissemination of knowledge across the
diversity of social, cultural, economic, national and biological
backgrounds. Initially developed with the theme of equal opportunity
access and inclusion of students with learning or physical and mental disabilities,
the themes governing universal access to education have now expanded
across all forms of ability and diversity. However, as the definition of
diversity is within itself a broad amalgamation, teachers exercising
universal access will continually face challenges and incorporate
adjustments in their lesson plan to foster themes of equal opportunity
of education.
As universal access continues to be incorporated into the U.S. education system, professors and instructors at the college level are required (in some
instances by law) to rethink methods of facilitating universal access in
their classrooms. Universal access to college education may involve the
provision of a variety of different assessment methods of learning and
retention. For example, in order to determine how much of the material
was learned, a professor may enlist multiple methods of assessment.
Methods of assessment may include a comprehensive exam, unit exams,
portfolios, research papers, literature reviews, an oral exam or
homework assignments. Providing a variety of ways to assess the extent of learning and
retention will help identify the gaps in universal access and may also
elucidate the ways to improve universal access.
As part of the United Nations Convention on the Rights of the Child,
Universal Education for All (EFA) children were adopted according to
the United Nations in 1989. The limitation of education existed for
students living with disabilities despite international declarations.
Non-discrimination and equality in education
Examples of marginalized groups
Human rights are internationally recognized as universal rights, therefore meaning it applies to everyone equally and without discrimination. However, a significant number of individuals miss out on education due to discrimination preventing access to education.
Discrimination occurs most prominently in terms of accessing
education. For example, girls can face gender-based barriers such as child marriage, pregnancy, and gender-basedviolence which often prevent them from going to school or contribute to them dropping-out of school. People with disabilities
often face literal accessibility issues, such as a lack of ramps or
insufficient school transportation, making it more difficult to get to
school. Migrants often face administrative barriers that prevent them
from enrolling, effectively barring them from education systems.
Girls are dropped out of school to assist their families with
domestic labour. Due to limited resources, sons are sent to school
rather than girls.. Uniforms, tuition fees, textbooks, teacher salaries
and school maintenance are part of hindrances to education. Poverty is a
significant barrier accessing education. In sub-Saharan Africa,
children from the richest 20% of households reach ninth grade at eleven
times the rate of those from the poorest 40% of households.
However, discrimination also occurs within education systems when
certain groups receiving an inferior quality of education compared with
others, for instance, the quality of education in urban schools tends
to be higher than that found in rural areas.
Discrimination also happens after education where different
groups of people are less likely to draw the same benefits from their
schooling. For example, educated boys tend to leave school with higher
wage potential than equally educated girls.
Colored Memorial School of Brunswick, Georgia was built in 1922
Non-discrimination and equality provisions found in international human rights law
(IHRL) exist to ensure that the principle that international human
rights are universal is applied in practice. Non-discrimination and
equality are not abstract concepts under international human rights law
(IHRL). They are elaborated human rights
that have been developed over decades to address the discrimination
that people face daily. Particularly education where the rights to
non-discrimination and equality have been applied to the right to education across numerous human rights treaties, including one dedicated to the issue, known as UNESCOConvention against Discrimination in Education.
Despite the strength of non-discrimination and equality law,
eliminating discrimination and inequalities is a challenge that
individual states and the international community face. This was
acknowledged in 2015 when the international community vowed to ‘leave no
one behind’.
International and regional human rights treaties apply the rights to non-discrimination and equality to the right to education of specific marginalised
groups. Marginalized groups are those who have suffered prolonged and
historical discrimination, usually, but not exclusively, on the basis of
identity (gender, for example), characteristics (ethnicity, race), or
circumstance (refugees, migrants, internally displaced persons). Marginalized groups are very likely to be subject to multiple, compound, or intersectional forms of discrimination.
people living in countries or areas affected by armed conflict
Access to education in racial minorities
In
the context of post-secondary education, there exists a lack of access
to education that disproportionately affects minority students. The
number of students who pursue higher education heavily relies on the
number of students that graduate from high school. Since the late 1970s,
the rate in which young adults between the ages of 25 and 29 years old
have graduated from high school and received a diploma or the equivalent
has stagnated between 85 and 88 percent. In terms of race, there is a statistical gap between minority groups’
rates of graduation and white students’ rates of graduation. In 2006,
the rate of high school graduation was 93 percent, for Black students
was 86 percent, and for Hispanic students was 63 percent.
Although minority college attendance has increased throughout the
years, the disparity has remained. In terms of completing high school,
in 2010, white (47 percent) and Asian (66 percent) students were more
likely to have graduated from high school. In comparison, only 39
percent of Pacific Islanders, 37 percent of Black students, 31 percent
of Hispanics, and 28 percent of Native Americans completed high school. This transfers over to the numbers of students in minority groups who
have enrolled in college, even though these students have great
aspirations to attend college. When examining enrollment numbers, Black (23 percent) and Hispanic (19
percent) students enrolled into and attended 2-year and 4-year
universities at lower rates, compared to white (45 percent), Asian (53
percent), and multiracial (37 percent) students. However, Black and Hispanic students are more likely to enroll into 2-year universities.
Causes of disparities
The
disparity in access to higher education is primarily due to a
difference in college readiness these students experience. College
readiness refers to how prepared for higher education students are.
Although there are several ways to define it, college readiness involves
measuring four aspects of student performance: basic skills, knowledge
of certain content areas, grade point averages (GPA), and college
knowledge, also referred to as social capital. Basic skills include being able to read, write and think analytically
about situations; content areas that students should have knowledge of
include English and mathematics. Both aspects are crucial to college
readiness because of their real-world application, and if a student is
not proficient in these two areas, they are less likely to even pursue
university. However, for many minority students they do not meet the
basic requirements for colleges and universities.
In terms of GPA and college knowledge, racial disparities exist.
Regarding GPA, the gap in school performance between minority and white
students is significant. This gap can influence minority students’ aspirations towards attending
college, which affects minority enrollment rates. In terms of college
knowledge, many minority students do not have access to social capital
because of the lack of resources catered to them to ensure their
success. There also is a lack of knowledge among minority students about
what resources are available, especially because many of them are
first-generation students.
Work towards better access
Although
racial disparities in college readiness exist, there are several ways
to counteract them. One way involves the way that students’ communities
support them. Their counselors, teachers, and parents must work with
them to ensure that their school records, academic records, and such are
accurately conveyed to colleges and universities. Other crucial factors that would contribute to higher rates of minority
enrollment include encouraging students through policies and rewards
for focusing on information pertaining to college, providing schools
with the necessary resources, and cultivating the classroom environment
to be encouraging of students’ skills so that they are better prepared
for college. Organizations like the National Association for College Admission
Counseling should also be more aware of this issue as well as do more to
bring more attention to these disparities. Changes also must occur on an institution level for minority students to better succeed.
Programs like the ones developed at the University of Maryland,
Baltimore County work towards eliminating disparities in higher
education access in minority students. Their programs mostly focus on
minorities having better access and getting more involved in science,
technology, engineering, and mathematics (STEM) fields. One program, the
Meyerhoff Scholars Program, aids students by addressing the social
capital aspect college readiness. This program connects students to
financial resources as well as academic and social support, and they
also receive research opportunities and connect with on-campus staff
members. Other programs like the ACTiVATE program and the Partnerships for
Innovation Program have stemmed from the Meyerhoff Scholars Program.
These have pushed minority students towards success in accessing and
completing post-secondary education, especially in STEM fields. Other programs across the country have also aided minority students in succeeding in higher education.
In 2009, both the houses of the Indian Parliament and the President
of India both signed and approved a bill that would grant free,
legally-mandated education for children ages six to fourteen. It was considered a major step towards universal education for all.
Muchkund Dubey author of the article “The Right of Children to Free and
Compulsory Education Act, 2009 : The Story of Missed Opportunity"
discusses and highlights the issues of access, quality of education,
financial implication, and discrimination.
In the United States, Brown vs. Board of Education was a landmark
decision because it found and declared that, “separate educational
facilities are inherently unequal”. This began the process of desegregation in many schools that had not desegregated yet. The significance of Brown vs. Board was the universal right of all
students to attend educational institutions equally rather than using
racial segregation to separate students. Jonathan Kozol, author of The
Shame of the Nation, talks about how “physical conditions in these newly integrated schools
were generally more cheerful…state of mind among the teachers and the
children [was] more high-spirited” in the aftermath of desegregation.
Universal Access to education is defined as having equal
opportunities to take part in any educational system. However, some
individuals, groups, or ethnic groups face barriers to equal access. The
United States is credited with the current idea of universal access as a
concern for handicapped persons. Two international agencies (World Health Organization and World Bank)
estimated that around one billion people all over the world have various
types of disabilities. Between 93 and 150 million of them are children. Plan International revealed that these kids are less likely to attend
school, and if enrolled, they are often separated from their peers. The Global Partnership for Education said approximately 90 percent of
children with disabilities from low and middle income nations are out of
school. Historically, these students have been excluded from the ordinary education system and referred to special learning schools.
Despite all improvements made, education up to this day is
inaccessible to millions of schoolchildren globally. Over 72 million
children of primary education age are out of school, and around 759
million adults are uneducated. They do not have the resources for
developing the situation of themselves, their families, and their
countries. Poverty leads to lack of education. In almost all countries (developing and developed), children face
barriers to education as a result of inequalities that emanate from
health, gender, and cultural identity like religion, language, and
ethnic origin. Factors associated with poverty include unemployment,
illiteracy among parents, and ailments increase the possibility of
non-schooling and dropout rates. Universal primary education is widely known as a major issue for many
nations. The majority of these developing states do not possess the
financial resources needed to build schools, provide books and other
materials, and recruit, train, and pay teachers. The Sub-Saharan African region is the most affected region in the world
as roughly 32 million African children are still uneducated. This is followed by Central and East Asia as well as the Pacific with over 27 million children uneducated. However, observers noted that universal access to education remains an attainable goal by 2030.
Paranoia is an instinct or thought process that is believed to be heavily influenced by anxiety, suspicion, or fear, often to the point of delusion and irrationality. Paranoid thinking typically includes persecutory beliefs, or beliefs of conspiracy concerning a perceived threat towards oneself (e.g., "Everyone is out to get me"). Paranoia is distinct from phobias, which also involve irrational fear, but usually no blame.
Making false accusations and the general distrust of other people also frequently accompany paranoia. For example, a paranoid person might believe an incident was
intentional when most people would view it as an accident or
coincidence. Paranoia is a central symptom of psychosis.
Signs and symptoms
A common symptom of paranoia is attribution bias. These individuals typically have a biased perception of reality, often exhibiting more hostile beliefs than average. A paranoid person may view someone else's accidental behavior as though it is intentional or signifies a threat.
An investigation of a non-clinical paranoid population found that
characteristics such as feeling powerless and depressed, isolating
oneself, and relinquishing activities, were associated with more
frequent paranoia. Some scientists have created different subtypes for the various symptoms
of paranoia, including erotic, persecutory, litigious, and exalted.
Most commonly paranoid individuals tend to be of a single status,
perhaps because paranoia results in difficulty with interpersonal
relationships.
Some researchers have arranged types of paranoia by commonality.
The least common types of paranoia at the very top of the hierarchy
would be those involving more serious threats. Social anxiety is at the bottom of this hierarchy as the most frequently exhibited level of paranoia.
Causes
Social and environmental
Social
circumstances appear to be highly influential on paranoid beliefs.
According to a mental health survey distributed to residents of Ciudad Juárez, Chihuahua (in Mexico) and El Paso, Texas (in the United States), paranoid beliefs seem to be associated with feelings of powerlessness and victimization,
enhanced by social situations. Paranoid symptoms were associated with
an attitude of mistrust and an external locus of control. Citing
research showing that women and those with lower socioeconomic status
are more prone to locating locus of control externally, the researchers
suggested that women may be especially affected by the effects of
socioeconomic status on paranoia.
Surveys have revealed that paranoia can develop from difficult
parental relationships and untrustworthy environments, for instance
those that were highly disciplinary, strict, and unstable, could
contribute to paranoia. Some sources have also noted that indulging and
pampering the child could contribute to greater paranoia, via disrupting
the child's understanding of their relationship with the world. Experiences found to enhance or create paranoia included frequent disappointment, stress, and a sense of hopelessness.
Discrimination has also been reported as a potential predictor of
paranoid delusions. Such reports that paranoia seemed to appear more in
older patients who had experienced greater discrimination throughout
their lives. Immigrants are more subject to some forms of psychosis than
the general population, which may be related to more frequent
experiences of discrimination and humiliation.
Psychological
Many more mood-based symptoms, for example grandiosity and guilt, may underlie functional paranoia.
Colby (1981) defined paranoid cognition as "persecutory delusions
and false beliefs whose propositional content clusters around ideas of
being harassed, threatened, harmed, subjugated, persecuted, accused,
mistreated, killed, wronged, tormented, disparaged, vilified, and so on,
by malevolent others, either specific individuals or groups" (p. 518).
Three components of paranoid cognition have been identified by Robins
& Post: "a) suspicions without enough basis that others are
exploiting, harming, or deceiving them; b) preoccupation with
unjustified doubts about the loyalty, or trustworthiness, of friends or
associates; c) reluctance to confide in others because of unwarranted
fear that the information will be used maliciously against them" (1997,
p. 3).
Paranoid cognition has been conceptualized by clinical psychology
almost exclusively in terms of psychodynamic constructs and
dispositional variables. From this point of view, paranoid cognition is a
manifestation of an intra-psychic conflict or disturbance. For
instance, Colby (1981) suggested that the biases of blaming others for
one's problems serve to alleviate the distress produced by the feeling
of being humiliated, and helps to repudiate the belief that the self is
to blame for such incompetence. This intra-psychic perspective
emphasizes that the cause of paranoid cognitions is inside the head of
the people (social perceiver), and dismisses the possibility that
paranoid cognition may be related to the social context in which such
cognitions are embedded. This point is extremely relevant because when
origins of distrust and suspicion (two components of paranoid cognition)
are studied many researchers have accentuated the importance of social
interaction, particularly when social interaction has gone awry. Even
more, a model of trust development pointed out that trust increases or
decreases as a function of the cumulative history of interaction between
two or more persons.
Another relevant difference can be discerned among "pathological
and non-pathological forms of trust and distrust". According to Deutsch,
the main difference is that non-pathological forms are flexible and
responsive to changing circumstances. Pathological forms reflect
exaggerated perceptual biases and judgmental predispositions that can
arise and perpetuate them, are reflexively caused errors similar to a self-fulfilling prophecy.
It has been suggested that a "hierarchy" of paranoia exists,
extending from mild social evaluative concerns, through ideas of social
reference, to persecutory beliefs concerning mild, moderate, and severe
threats.
Physical
A
paranoid reaction may be caused from a decline in brain circulation as a
result of high blood pressure or hardening of the arterial walls.
Drug-induced paranoia, associated with cannabis and stimulants like amphetamines or methamphetamine,
has much in common with schizophrenic paranoia; the relationship has
been under investigation since 2012. Drug-induced paranoia has a better
prognosis than schizophrenic paranoia once the drug has been removed. For further information, see stimulant psychosis and substance-induced psychosis.
Based on data obtained by the Dutch NEMESIS project in 2005,
there was an association between impaired hearing and the onset of
symptoms of psychosis, which was based on a five-year follow up. Some
older studies have actually declared that a state of paranoia can be
produced in patients that were under a hypnotic state of deafness. This
idea however generated much skepticism during its time.
Diagnosis
In the DSM-IV-TR, paranoia is diagnosed in the form of:
According to clinical psychologist
P. J. McKenna, "As a noun, paranoia denotes a disorder which has been
argued in and out of existence, and whose clinical features, course,
boundaries, and virtually every other aspect of which is controversial.
Employed as an adjective, paranoid has become attached to a diverse set
of presentations, from paranoid schizophrenia, through paranoid
depression, to paranoid personality—not to mention a motley collection
of paranoid 'psychoses', 'reactions', and 'states'—and this is to
restrict discussion to functional disorders.
Even when abbreviated down to the prefix para-, the term crops up
causing trouble as the contentious but stubbornly persistent concept of paraphrenia".[21]
The word paranoia comes from the Greek παράνοια (paránoia), "madness", and that from παρά (pará), "beside, by" and νόος (nóos), "mind". The term was used to describe a mental illness in which a delusional
belief is the sole or most prominent feature. In this definition, the
belief does not have to be persecutory to be classified as paranoid, so
any number of delusional beliefs can be classified as paranoia. For example, a person who has the sole delusional belief that they are
an important religious figure would be classified by Kraepelin as having
"pure paranoia". The word "paranoia" is associated from the Greek word
"para-noeo". Its meaning was "derangement", or "departure from the normal". However,
the word was used strictly and other words were used such as "insanity"
or "crazy", as these words were introduced by Aulus Cornelius Celsus.
The term "paranoia" first made an appearance during plays of Greek
tragedians, and was also used by philosophers such as Plato and
Hippocrates. Nevertheless, the word "paranoia" was the equivalent of
"delirium" or "high". Eventually, the term fell out of use for two
millennia. "Paranoia" was revived in the 18th century, appearing in the
works of nosologists such as François Boissier de Sauvage (1759) and Rudolph August Vogel (1772).
According to Michael Phelan, Padraig Wright, and Julian Stern (2000), paranoia and paraphrenia are debated entities that were detached from dementia praecox
by Kraepelin, who explained paranoia as a continuous systematized
delusion arising much later in life with no presence of either
hallucinations or a deteriorating course, and paraphrenia as an
identical syndrome to paranoia but with hallucinations. Even at the
present time, a delusion need not be suspicious or fearful to be
classified as paranoid. A person might be diagnosed with paranoid
schizophrenia without delusions of persecution, simply because the
delusions refer mainly to the self.
Relations to violence
It
has generally been agreed upon that individuals with paranoid delusions
will have the tendency to take action based on their beliefs. More research is needed on the particular types of actions that are
pursued based on paranoid delusions. Some researchers have made attempts
to distinguish the different variations of actions brought on as a
result of delusions. Wessely et al. (1993) did just this by studying
individuals with delusions of which more than half had reportedly taken
action or behaved as a result of these delusions. However, the overall
actions were not of a violent nature in most of the informants. The
authors note that other studies such as one by Taylor (1985), have shown
that violent behaviors were more common in certain types of paranoid
individuals, mainly those considered to be offensive such as prisoners.
Other researchers have found associations between childhood
abusive behaviors and the appearance of violent behaviors in psychotic
individuals. This could be a result of their inability to cope with
aggression as well as other people, especially when constantly attending
to potential threats in their environment. The attention to threat itself has been proposed as one of the major
contributors of violent actions in paranoid people, although there has
been much deliberation about this as well. Other studies have shown that there may only be certain types of
delusions that promote any violent behaviors, persecutory delusions seem
to be one of these.
Having resentful emotions towards others and the inability to
understand what other people are feeling seem to have an association
with violence in paranoid individuals. This was based on a study of
people with paranoid schizophrenia (one of the common mental disorders
that exhibit paranoid symptoms) theories of mind capabilities in
relation to empathy. The results of this study revealed specifically
that although the violent patients were more successful at the higher
level theory of mind tasks, they were not as able to interpret others'
emotions or claims.
Paranoid social cognition
Social psychological research has proposed a mild form of paranoid cognition, paranoid social cognition, that has its origins in social determinants more than intra-psychic conflict. This perspective states that in milder forms, paranoid cognitions may
be very common among normal individuals. For instance, it is not
considered strange to have self-centered thoughts of being talked about,
or to be suspicious of others' intentions, or to assume ill-will or
hostility (e.g., a feeling of everything going against them). According
to Kramer (1998), these milder forms of paranoid cognition may be
considered an adaptive response to cope with or make sense of a
disturbing and threatening social environment.
Paranoid cognition captures the idea that dysphoric
self-consciousness may be related to the position a person occupies in a
social system. This self-consciousness
conduces to a hypervigilant and ruminative mode to process social
information that finally will stimulate a variety of paranoid-like forms
of social misperception and misjudgment. This model identifies four components that are essential to
understanding paranoid social cognition: situational antecedents,
dysphoric self-consciousness, hypervigilance and rumination, and
judgmental biases.
Situational antecedents
Perceived social distinctiveness, perceived evaluative scrutiny and uncertainty about the social standing.
Perceived social distinctiveness: According to the social identity theory, people categorize themselves in terms of characteristics that made them
unique or different from others under certain circumstances. Gender, ethnicity, age, or experience may become extremely relevant to
explain people's behavior when these attributes make them unique in a
social group. This distinctive attribute may have influence not only in
how people are perceived, but may also affect the way they perceive
themselves.
Perceived evaluative scrutiny: According to this model, dysphoric
self-consciousness may increase when people feel under moderate or
intensive evaluative social scrutiny such as when an asymmetric
relationship is analyzed. For example, when asked about relationships,
doctoral students remembered events that they interpreted as significant
to their degree of trust in their advisors when compared with their
advisors. This suggests that students are willing to pay more attention
to their advisor than their advisor is to them. Also, students spent
more time ruminating about behaviors, events, and their relationship in
general.
Uncertainty about social standing: Knowledge about social standing
is another factor that may induce paranoid social cognition. Many
researchers have argued that experiencing uncertainty about a social
position in a social system constitutes an adverse psychological state,
one which people are highly motivated to reduce.
Dysphoric self-consciousness
An
aversive form of heightened 'public self-consciousness' is
characterized by the feelings that one is under intensive evaluation or scrutiny. Becoming self-tormenting will increase the odds of interpreting others' behaviors in a self-referential way.
Hypervigilance and rumination
Self-consciousness
was characterized as an aversive psychological state. According to this
model, people experiencing self-consciousness will be highly motivated
to reduce it, trying to make sense of what they are experiencing. These
attempts promote hypervigilance and rumination in a circular
relationship: more hypervigilance generates more rumination, whereupon
more rumination generates more hypervigilance. Hypervigilance can be
thought of as a way to appraise threatening social information, but in
contrast to adaptive vigilance, hypervigilance will produce elevated
levels of arousal, fear, anxiety, and threat perception. Rumination is another possible response to threatening social
information. Rumination can be related to the paranoid social cognition
because it can increase negative thinking about negative events, and
evoke a pessimistic explanatory style.
Judgmental and cognitive biases
Three main judgmental consequences have been identified:
The sinister attribution error: This bias captures the tendency
that social perceivers have to overattribute lack of trustworthiness to
others.
The overly personalistic construal of social interaction: Refers to
the inclination that paranoid perceiver has to interpret others' action
in a disproportional self-referential way, increasing the belief that
they are the target of others' thoughts and actions. A special kind of
bias in the biased punctuation of social interaction, which entail an
overperception of causal linking among independent events.
The exaggerated perception of conspiracy: Refers to the disposition
that the paranoid perceiver has to overattribute social coherence and
coordination to others' actions.
Meta-analyses have confirmed that individuals with paranoia tend to
jump to conclusions and are incorrigible in their judgements, even for
delusion-neutral scenarios.
Pascal's wager is a philosophical argument advanced by Blaise Pascal (1623–1662), a French mathematician, philosopher, physicist, and theologian. This argument posits that individuals essentially engage in a life-defining gamble regarding the belief in the existence of God.
Pascal contends that a rational person should adopt a lifestyle consistent with the existence of God
and should strive to believe in God. The reasoning for this stance
involves the potential outcomes: if God does not exist, the believer
incurs only finite losses, potentially sacrificing certain pleasures and
luxuries; if God does exist, the believer stands to gain immeasurably,
as represented for example by an eternity in Heaven in Abrahamic tradition, while simultaneously avoiding boundless losses associated with an eternity in Hell.
The first written expression of this wager is in Pascal's Pensées ("Thoughts"), a posthumous compilation of previously unpublished notes. Pascal's wager is the first formal application of decision theory, existentialism, pragmatism, and voluntarism.
Critics of the wager question the ability to provide definitive proof of God's existence. The argument from inconsistent revelations
highlights the presence of various belief systems, each claiming
exclusive access to divine truths. Additionally, the argument from
inauthentic belief raises concerns about the genuineness of faith in God
if it is motivated solely by potential benefits and losses.
The wager
The wager uses the following logic (excerpts from Pensées, part III, §233):
"God is, or God is not. Reason cannot decide between the two alternatives"
"A Game is being played ... where heads or tails will turn up"
"You must wager; it is not optional"
"Let us weigh the gain and the loss in wagering that God is. Let us
estimate these two chances. If you gain, you gain all; if you lose, you
lose nothing"
"Wager, then, without hesitation that He is. ... There is here an
infinity of an infinitely happy life to gain, a chance of gain against a
finite number of chances of loss, and what you stake is finite. And so
our proposition is of infinite force when there is the finite to stake
in a game where there are equal risks of gain and of loss, and the
infinite to gain."
"But some cannot believe. They should then 'at least learn your
inability to believe...' and 'Endeavour then to convince' themselves."
Pascal asks the reader to analyze humankind's position, where our
actions can be enormously consequential, but our understanding of those
consequences is flawed. While we can discern a great deal through reason, we are ultimately forced to gamble. Pascal cites a number of distinct areas of uncertainty in human life:
Category
Quotation(s)
Uncertainty in all
"This is what I see, and what troubles me. I look on all sides, and
everywhere I see nothing but obscurity. Nature offers me nothing that is
not a matter of doubt and disquiet."
Uncertainty in man's purpose
"For after all what is man in nature? A nothing in relation to
infinity, all in relation to nothing, a central point between nothing
and all and infinitely far from understanding either."
Uncertainty in reason
"There is nothing so conformable to reason as this disavowal of reason."
Uncertainty in science
"There is no doubt that natural laws exist, but once this fine reason of ours was corrupted, it corrupted everything."
Uncertainty in religion
"If I saw no signs of a divinity, I would fix myself in denial. If I
saw everywhere the marks of a Creator, I would repose peacefully in
faith. But seeing too much to deny Him, and too little to assure me, I
am in a pitiful state, and I would wish a hundred times that if a god
sustains nature it would reveal Him without ambiguity."
"We understand nothing of the works of God unless we take it as a
principle that He wishes to blind some and to enlighten others."
Uncertainty in skepticism
"It is not certain that everything is uncertain."
Pascal describes humanity as a finite being trapped within divine incomprehensibility,
briefly thrust into being from non-being, with no explanation of "Why?"
or "What?" or "How?" On Pascal's view, human finitude constrains our
ability to achieve truth reliably.
Given that reason alone cannot determine whether God exists,
Pascal concludes that this question functions as a coin toss. However,
even if we do not know the outcome of this coin toss, we must base our
actions on some expectation about the consequence. We must decide
whether to live as though God exists, or whether to live as though God
does not exist, even though we may be mistaken in either case.
In Pascal's assessment, participation in this wager is not
optional. Merely by existing in a state of uncertainty, we are forced to
choose between the available courses of action for practical purposes.
Pascal's description of the wager
The Pensées passage on Pascal's wager is as follows:
If there is a God, He is infinitely
incomprehensible, since, having neither parts nor limits, He has no
affinity to us. We are then incapable of knowing either what He is or if
He is. ...
... "God is, or He is not." But to which side shall we incline?
Reason can decide nothing here. There is infinite chaos that separated
us. A game is being played at the extremity of this infinite distance
where heads or tails will turn up. What will you wager? According to
reason, you can do neither the one thing nor the other; according to
reason, you can defend neither of the propositions.
Do not, then, reprove for error those who have made a choice; for
you know nothing about it. "No, but I blame them for having made, not
this choice, but a choice; for again both he who chooses heads and he
who chooses tails are equally at fault, they are both in the wrong. The
true course is not to wager at all."
Yes; but you must wager. It is not optional. You are embarked.
Which will you choose then? Let us see. Since you must choose, let us
see which interests you least. You have two things to lose, the true and
the good; and two things to stake, your reason and your will, your
knowledge and your happiness; and your nature has two things to shun,
error and misery. Your reason is no more shocked in choosing one rather
than the other since you must of necessity choose. This is one point
settled. But your happiness? Let us weigh the gain and the loss in
wagering that God is. Let us estimate these two chances. If you gain,
you gain all; if you lose, you lose nothing. Wager, then, without
hesitation that He is.
"That is very fine. Yes, I must wager; but I may perhaps wager too
much." Let us see. Since there is an equal risk of gain and of loss, if
you had only to gain two lives, instead of one, you might still wager.
But if there were three lives to gain, you would have to play (since you
are under the necessity of playing), and you would be imprudent, when
you are forced to play, not to change your life to gain three at a game
where there is an equal risk of loss and gain. But there is an eternity
of life and happiness. And this being so, if there were an infinity of
chances, of which one only would be for you, you would still be right in
wagering one to win two, and you would act stupidly, being obliged to
play, by refusing to stake one life against three at a game in which out
of an infinity of chances there is one for you if there were an
infinity of an infinitely happy life to gain. But there is here an
infinity of an infinitely happy life to gain, a chance of gain against a
finite number of chances of loss, and what you stake is finite.
Pascal begins by painting a situation where both the existence and
non-existence of God are impossible to prove by human reason. So,
supposing that reason cannot determine the truth between the two
options, one must "wager" by weighing the possible consequences.
Pascal's assumption is that, when it comes to making the decision, no
one can refuse to participate; withholding assent is impossible because
we are already "embarked", effectively living out the choice.
We only have two things to stake, our "reason" and our "happiness". Pascal considers that if there is "equal
risk of loss and gain" (i.e. a coin toss), then human reason is
powerless to address the question of whether God exists. That being the
case, then human reason can only decide the question according to
possible resulting happiness of the decision, weighing the gain and loss
in believing that God exists and likewise in believing that God does
not exist.
He points out that if a wager were between the equal chance of
gaining two lifetimes of happiness and gaining nothing, then a person
would be a fool to bet on the latter. The same would go if it were three
lifetimes of happiness versus nothing. He then argues that it is simply
unconscionable by comparison to bet against an eternal life of
happiness for the possibility of gaining nothing. The wise decision is
to wager that God exists, since "If you gain, you gain all; if you lose,
you lose nothing", meaning one can gain eternal life
if God exists, but if not, one will be no worse off in death than if
one had not believed. On the other hand, if you bet against God, win or
lose, you either gain nothing or lose everything. You are either
unavoidably annihilated (in which case, nothing matters one way or the
other) or miss the opportunity of eternal happiness. In note 194,
speaking about those who live apathetically betting against God, he sums
up by remarking, "It is to the glory of religion to have for enemies
men so unreasonable".
Inability to believe
Pascal addressed the difficulty that reason and rationality pose to genuine belief by proposing that "acting as if [one] believed" could "cure [one] of unbelief":
But at least learn your inability
to believe, since reason brings you to this, and yet you cannot believe.
Endeavor then to convince yourself, not by increase of proofs of God,
but by the abatement of your passions. You would like to attain faith,
and do not know the way; you would like to cure yourself of unbelief and
ask the remedy for it. Learn of those who have been bound like you, and
who now stake all their possessions. These are people who know the way
which you would follow, and who are cured of an ill of which you would
be cured. Follow the way by which they began; by acting as if they
believed, taking the holy water, having masses said, etc. Even this will
naturally make you believe, and deaden your acuteness.
Given these values, the option of living as if God exists (B)
dominates the option of living as if God does not exist (¬B), as long as
one assumes a positive probability that God exists. In other words, the
expected value gained by choosing B is greater than or equal to that of
choosing ¬B.
In fact, according to decision theory, the only value that
matters in the above matrix is the +∞ (infinitely positive). Any matrix
of the following type (where f1, f2, and f3 are all negative or finite positive numbers) results in (B) as being the only rational decision.
God exists (G)
God does not exist (¬G)
Belief (B)
+∞
f1
Disbelief (¬B)
f2
f3
Misunderstanding of the wager
Pascal's intent was not to provide an argument to convince atheists to believe, but (a) to show the fallacy of attempting to use logical reasoning
to prove or disprove God, and (b) to persuade atheists to sinlessness,
as an aid to attaining faith ("it is this which will lessen the
passions, which are your stumbling-blocks"). As Laurent Thirouin writes
(note that the numbering of the items in the Pensees is not standardized; Thirouin's 418 is this article's 233):
The celebrity of fragment 418 has
been established at the price of mutilation. By titling this text "the
wager", readers have been fixated only on one part of Pascal's
reasoning. It doesn't conclude with a QED at the end of the mathematical
part. The unbeliever who had provoked this long analysis to counter his
previous objection ("Maybe I bet too much") is still not ready to join
the apologist on the side of faith. He put forward two new objections,
undermining the foundations of the wager: the impossibility to know, and
the obligation of playing.
To be put at the beginning of Pascal's planned book, the wager was
meant to show that logical reasoning cannot support faith or lack
thereof:
We have to accept reality and
accept the reaction of the libertine when he rejects arguments he is
unable to counter. The conclusion is evident: if men believe or refuse
to believe, it is not how some believers sometimes say and most
unbelievers claim because their own reason justifies the position they
have adopted. Belief in God doesn't depend upon rational evidence, no
matter which position.
Frederick Copleston
writes that Pascal did not intend the wager as proof of God's existence
or even a substitute for such proofs. He argues that the wager must be
understood in the context of Pascal addressing the wager to those who
"though they are also unconvinced by the arguments of sceptics and
atheists" also "remain in a state of suspended judgment". Pascal's aim
was to prepare "their minds and the production of dispositions
favourable to belief".
Criticism
Criticism of Pascal's wager began soon after it was published. Non-believers questioned the "benefits" of a deity whose "realm" is beyond reason and the religiously orthodox, who primarily took issue with the wager's deistic and agnostic
language. Believers criticized it for not proving God's existence, the
encouragement of false belief, and the problem of which religion and
which God should be worshipped.
Laplace
The probabilist mathematician Pierre Simon de Laplace
ridiculed the use of probability in theology, believing that even
following Pascal's reasoning, it is not worth making a bet, for the hope
of profit – equal to the product of the value of the testimonies
(infinitely small) and the value of the happiness they promise (which is
significant but finite) – must necessarily be infinitely small.
Failure to prove the existence of God
Voltaire (another prominent French writer of the age of Enlightenment),
a generation after Pascal, regarded the idea of the wager as a "proof
of God" as "indecent and childish", adding, "the interest I have to
believe a thing is no proof that such a thing exists". Pascal, however, did not advance the wager as a proof of God's
existence but rather as a necessary pragmatic decision which is
"impossible to avoid" for any living person. He argued that abstaining from making a wager is not an option and that
"reason is incapable of divining the truth"; thus, a decision of
whether to believe in the existence of God must be made by "considering
the consequences of each possibility".
Voltaire's critique concerns not the nature of the Pascalian
wager as proof of God's existence, but the contention that the very
belief Pascal tried to promote is not convincing. Voltaire hints at the
fact that Pascal, as a Jansenist, believed that only a small, and already predestined, portion of humanity would eventually be saved by God.
Voltaire explained that no matter how far someone is tempted with rewards to believe in Christian salvation, the result will be at best a faint belief. Pascal, in his Pensées,
agrees with this, not stating that people can choose to believe (and
therefore make a safe wager), but rather that some cannot believe.
As Étienne Souriau
explained, in order to accept Pascal's argument, the bettor needs to be
certain that God seriously intends to honour the bet; he says that the
wager assumes that God also accepts the bet, which is not proved;
Pascal's bettor is here like the fool who seeing a leaf floating on a
river's waters and quivering at some point, for a few seconds, between
the two sides of a stone, says: "I bet a million with Rothschild that it
takes finally the left path." And, effectively, the leaf passed on the
left side of the stone, but unfortunately for the fool Rothschild never
said "I [will take that] bet".
Since there have been many religions throughout history, and
therefore many conceptions of God (or gods), some assert that all of
them need to be factored into the wager, in an argumentation known as
the argument from inconsistent revelations. This, its proponents argue,
would lead to a high probability of believing in "the wrong god" and
would eliminate the mathematical advantage Pascal claimed with his
wager. Denis Diderot, a contemporary of Voltaire, expressed this opinion when asked about the wager, saying "an Imam could reason the same way". J. L. Mackie
writes that "the church within which alone salvation is to be found is
not necessarily the Church of Rome, but perhaps that of the Anabaptists or the Mormons or the Muslim Sunnis or the worshipers of Kali or of Odin."
Pascal considers this type of objection briefly in the notes compiled into the Pensées, and dismisses it:
What say [the unbelievers] then?
"Do we not see," say they, "that the brutes live and die like men, and
Turks like Christians? They have their ceremonies, their prophets, their
doctors, their saints, their monks, like us," etc.
If you care but little to know the truth, that is enough to leave you in
repose. But if you desire with all your heart to know it, it is not
enough; look at it in detail. That would be sufficient for a question in
philosophy; but not here, where everything is at stake. And yet, after a
superficial reflection of this kind, we go to amuse ourselves, etc. Let
us inquire of this same religion whether it does not give a reason for
this obscurity; perhaps it will teach it to us.
Pascal says that the skepticism of unbelievers who rest content with
the many-religions objection has seduced them into a fatal "repose". If
they were really bent on knowing the truth, they would be persuaded to
examine "in detail" whether Christianity is like any other religion, but
they just cannot be bothered. Their objection might be sufficient were the subject concerned merely
some "question in philosophy", but not "here, where everything is at
stake". In "a matter where they themselves, their eternity, their all
are concerned", they can manage no better than "a superficial reflection" ("une reflexion légère") and, thinking they have scored a point by asking a leading question, they go off to amuse themselves.
As Pascal scholars observe, Pascal regarded the many-religions
objection as a rhetorical ploy, a "trap" that he had no intention of
falling into.
David Wetsel notes that Pascal's treatment of the pagan religions
is brisk: "As far as Pascal is concerned, the demise of the pagan
religions of antiquity speaks for itself. Those pagan religions which
still exist in the New World, in India, and in Africa are not even worth
a second glance. They are obviously the work of superstition and
ignorance and have nothing in them which might interest "les gens habiles" ('clever men'). Islam warrants more attention, being distinguished from paganism (which
for Pascal presumably includes all the other non-Christian religions)
by its claim to be a revealed religion. Nevertheless, Pascal concludes
that the religion founded by Mohammed can on several counts be shown to
be devoid of divine authority, and that therefore, as a path to the
knowledge of God, it is as much a dead end as paganism." Judaism, in view of its close links to Christianity, he deals with elsewhere.
The many-religions objection is taken more seriously by some later apologists of the wager, who argue that of the rival options only those awarding infinite happiness affect the wager's dominance.
In the opinion of these apologists "finite, semi-blissful promises such
as Kali's or Odin's" therefore drop out of consideration. Also, the infinite bliss that the rival conception of God offers has
to be mutually exclusive. If Christ's promise of bliss can be attained
concurrently with Jehovah's and Allah's (all three being identified as the God of Abraham),
there is no conflict in the decision matrix in the case where the cost
of believing in the wrong conception of God is neutral
(limbo/purgatory/spiritual death), although this would be countered with
an infinite cost in the case where not believing in the correct
conception of God results in punishment (hell).
Ecumenical interpretations of the wager argue that it could even be suggested that believing in a generic God,
or a god by the wrong name, is acceptable so long as that conception of
God has similar essential characteristics of the conception of God
considered in Pascal's wager (perhaps the God of Aristotle).
Proponents of this line of reasoning suggest that either all of the
conceptions of God or gods throughout history truly boil down to just a
small set of "genuine options", or that if Pascal's wager can simply
bring a person to believe in "generic theism", it has done its job.
Pascal argues implicitly for the uniqueness of Christianity in
the wager itself, writing: "If there is a God, He is infinitely
incomprehensible ... Who then can blame the Christians for not being
able to give reasons for their beliefs, professing as they do a religion
which they cannot explain by reason?"
Argument from inauthentic belief
Some critics argue that Pascal's wager, for those who cannot believe, suggests feigning belief to gain eternal reward. Richard Dawkins
argues that this would be dishonest and immoral and that, in addition
to this, it is absurd to think that God, being just and omniscient,
would not see through this deceptive strategy on the part of the
"believer", thus nullifying the benefits of the wager. William James in his 'Will to Believe'
states that "We feel that a faith in masses and holy water adopted
wilfully after such a mechanical calculation would lack the inner soul
of faith's reality; and if we were ourselves in the place of the Deity,
we should probably take particular pleasure in cutting off believers of
this pattern from their infinite reward. It is evident that unless there
be some pre-existing tendency to believe in masses and holy water, the
option offered to the will by Pascal is not a living option".
Since these criticisms are concerned not with the validity of the
wager itself, but with its possible aftermath—namely that a person who
has been convinced of the overwhelming odds in favor of belief might
still find themself unable to sincerely believe—they are tangential to
the thrust of the wager. What such critics are objecting to is Pascal's
subsequent advice to an unbeliever who, having concluded that the only
rational way to wager is in favor of God's existence, points out,
reasonably enough, that this by no means makes them a believer. This
hypothetical unbeliever complains, "I am so made that I cannot believe.
What would you have me do?" Pascal, far from suggesting that God can be deceived by outward show,
says that God does not regard it at all: "God looks only at what is
inward." For a person who is already convinced of the odds of the wager but
cannot seem to put their heart into the belief, he offers practical
advice.
Explicitly addressing the question of inability to believe,
Pascal argues that if the wager is valid, the inability to believe is
irrational, and therefore must be caused by feelings: "your inability to
believe, because reason compels you to [believe] and yet you cannot,
[comes] from your passions." This inability, therefore, can be overcome
by diminishing these irrational sentiments: "Learn from those who were
bound like you. ... Follow the way by which they began; by acting as if
they believed, taking the holy water, having masses said, etc. Even this
will naturally make you believe, and deaden your acuteness.—'But this
is what I am afraid of.'—And why? What have you to lose?"
An uncontroversial doctrine in both Roman Catholic and Protestant
theology is that mere belief in God is insufficient to attain
salvation, the standard cite being James 2:19 (the following is from the KJV):
"Thou believest that there is one God; thou doest well: the devils also
believe, and tremble." Salvation requires "faith" not just in the sense
of belief, but of trust and obedience. Pascal and his sister, a nun, were among the leaders of Roman Catholicism's Jansenist school of thought
whose doctrine of salvation was close to Protestantism in emphasizing
faith over works. Both Jansenists and Protestants followed St. Augustine in this emphasis (Martin Luther belonged to the Augustinian Order of monks). Augustine wrote
So our faith has to be
distinguished from the faith of the demons. Our faith, you see, purifies
the heart, their faith makes them guilty. They act wickedly, and so
they say to the Lord, "What have you to do with us?" When you hear the
demons saying this, do you imagine they don't recognize him? "We know
who you are," they say. "You are the Son of God" (Lk 4:34). Peter says
this and he is praised for it; the demon says it, and is condemned.
Why's that, if not because the words may be the same, but the heart is
very different? So let us distinguish our faith, and see that believing
is not enough. That's not the sort of faith that purifies the heart.
Since Pascal's position was that "saving" belief in God required more than logical assent, accepting the wager could only be a first step. Hence his advice on what steps one could take to arrive at belief.
Some other critics have objected to Pascal's wager on the grounds that he wrongly assumes
what type of epistemic character God would likely value in his rational
creatures if he existed.
Earlier versions and other wager arguments
The sophistProtagoras
had an agnostic position regarding the gods, but he nevertheless
continued to worship the gods. This could be considered as an early
version of the Wager.
In the famous tragedy of EuripidesBacchae, Kadmos states an early version of Pascal's wager. It is noteworthy that at the end of the tragedy Dionysos,
the god to whom Kadmos referred, appears and punishes him for thinking
in this way. Euripides, quite clearly, considered and dismissed the
wager in this tragedy.
The stoic philosopher and Roman EmperorMarcus Aurelius expressed a similar sentiment in the second book of Meditations,
saying "Since it is possible that thou mayest depart from life this
very moment, regulate every act and thought accordingly. But to go away
from among men, if there are gods, is not a thing to be afraid of, for
the gods will not involve thee in evil; but if indeed they do not exist,
or if they have no concern about human affairs, what is it to me to
live in a universe devoid of gods or devoid of Providence?"
In the Sanskrit classic Sārasamuccaya, Vararuci makes a similar argument to Pascal's wager.
Muslim ImamJa'far al-Sadiq
is recorded to have postulated variations of the wager on several
occasions in different forms, including his famed 'Tradition of the
Myrobalan Fruit.' In the Shi'ihadith book al-Kafi,
al-Sadiq declares to an atheist "If what you say is correct – and it is
not – then we will both succeed. But if what I say is correct – and it
is – then I will succeed, and you will be destroyed."
An instantiation of this argument, within the Islamic kalam tradition, was discussed by Imam al-Haramayn al-Juwayni (d. 478/1085) in his Kitab al-irshad ila-qawati al-adilla fi usul al-i'tiqad, or A Guide to the Conclusive Proofs for the Principles of Belief.
The Christian apologist Arnobius of Sicca (d. 330) stated an early version of the argument in his book Against the Pagans,
arguing "is it not more rational, of two things uncertain and hanging
in doubtful suspense, rather to believe that which carries with it some
hopes, than that which brings none at all?"
A close parallel just before Pascal's time occurred in the Jesuit Antoine Sirmond's On the Immortality of the Soul
(1635), which explicitly compared the choice of religion to playing
dice and argued "However long and happy the space of this life may be,
while ever you place it in the other pan of the balance against a
blessed and flourishing eternity, surely it will seem to you ... that
the pan will rise on high."
The Atheist's Wager, popularised by the philosopher Michael Martin and published in his 1990 book Atheism: A Philosophical Justification, is an atheistic wager argument in response to Pascal's wager.
A 2008 philosophy book, How to Make Good Decisions and Be Right All the Time,
presents a secular revision of Pascal's wager: "What does it hurt to
pursue value and virtue? If there is value, then we have everything to
gain, but if there is none, then we haven’t lost anything.... Thus, we
should seek value."
Pascal's mugging, a dialogue written by philosopher Nick Bostrom,
shows that a rational victim can be made to give up his wallet in
exchange for a weakly credible promise of astronomical repayment. As in Pascal's Wager, a small but certain downside is outweighed by a large but unlikely upside.
In a 2014 article, philosopher Justin McBrayer argued we ought to
remain agnostic about the existence of God but nonetheless believe
because of the good that comes in the present life from believing in
God. "The gist of the renewed wager is that theists do better than
non-theists regardless of whether or not God exists."
Climate change
Since at least 1992, some scholars have analogized Pascal's wager to decisions about climate change. Two differences from Pascal's wager are posited regarding climate
change: first, climate change is more likely than Pascal's God to exist,
as there is scientific evidence for one but not the other. Secondly, the calculated penalty for unchecked climate change would be large, but is not generally considered to be infinite. Magnate Warren Buffett
has written that climate change "bears a similarity to Pascal's Wager
on the Existence of God. Pascal, it may be recalled, argued that if
there were only a tiny probability that God truly existed, it made sense
to behave as if He did because the rewards could be infinite whereas
the lack of belief risked eternal misery. Likewise, if there is only a
1% chance the planet is heading toward a truly major disaster and delay
means passing a point of no return, inaction now is foolhardy."