A back-to-the-land movement is any of various agrarian movements across different historical periods. The common thread is a call for people to take up smallholding and to grow food from the land with an emphasis on a greater degree of self-sufficiency, autonomy, and local community than found in a conventional industrial or postindustrial way of life. Some of the motives behind such movements have included social reform, land reform, and civilian war efforts. Groups involved have included political reformers, counterculture hippies, and religious separatists.
History
The concept was popularized in the United States at the beginning of the 20th century by activist Bolton Hall, who set up vacant lot farming in New York City and wrote many books on the subject; and by his follower Ralph Borsodi,
who is known for his practical experiments in self-sufficient living
during the 1920s and 1930s. The practice, however, was strong in Europe even before that time.
Between the mid-1960s and mid-1970s, the USA had a revived
back-to-the-land movement, with substantial numbers of people migrating
from cities to rural areas.
The back-to-the-land movement has ideological links to distributism, a 1920s and 1930s attempt to find a "Third Way" between capitalism and socialism.
Historical precedents
The American social commentator and poet Gary Snyder
has related that the many back-to-the-land population movements
throughout the centuries, and throughout the world, can be largely
attributed to the occurrence of severe urban problems where people felt
the need to live a better life or were otherwise simply trying to
survive.
The historian and philosopher of urbanism Jane Jacobs remarked in an interview with Stewart Brand that with the Fall of Rome city dwellers re-inhabited the rural areas of the region.
From another point of departure, Yi-Fu Tuan takes a view that such trends have often been privileged and motivated by sentiment, who wrote in his book Topophilia
(1974): "Awareness of the past is an important element in the love of
place." Tuan writes that an appreciation of nature springs from wealth,
privilege, and the antithetical values of cities. He argues that
literature about land (and, subsequently, about going back to the land)
is largely sentimental: "Little is known about the farmer's attitudes to
nature..." Tuan finds historical instances of the desire of the
civilized to escape civilization in the Hellenistic, Roman, Augustan, and Romantic eras, as well as, from one of the earliest recorded myths, the Epic of Gilgamesh.
North America
Regarding
North America, many individuals and households have moved from urban or
suburban circumstances to rural ones at different times; for instance,
the economic theorist and land-based American experimenter Ralph Borsodi (author of Flight from the City) is said to have influenced thousands of urban-living people to try a modern homesteading life during the Great Depression.
After World War II, interest in moving to rural land once again began to rise. In 1947, Betty MacDonald published what became a popular book, The Egg and I, telling her story of marrying and then moving to a small farm on the Olympic Peninsula in Washington state. This story was the basis of a successful comedy film starring Claudette Colbert and Fred MacMurray.
The Canadian writer Farley Mowat says that many returned veterans after World War II sought a meaningful life far from the ignobility of modern warfare, regarding his own experience as typical of the pattern. In Canada, those who sought a life completely outside the cities, suburbs, and towns frequently moved into semi-wilderness environs.
During the 1960s and 1970s, the phenomenon of the rural
relocation trend became sizable enough to be identified in the American
demographic statistics.
The roots of this movement can perhaps be traced to some of Bradford Angier's books, such as At Home in the Woods (1951) and We Like it Wild (1963), Louise Dickinson Rich's We Took to the Woods (1942) and subsequent books, or perhaps even more compellingly to the publication of Helen and Scott Nearing's book, Living the Good Life (1954). This book chronicles the Nearings' move to an older house in a rural area of Vermont and their self-sufficient and simple lifestyle.
In their initial move, the Nearings were driven by the circumstances of
the Great Depression and influenced by earlier writers, particularly Henry David Thoreau. Their book was published six years after A Sand County Almanac, by the ecologist and environmental activist Aldo Leopold,
was published in 1948. Influences aside, the Nearings had planned and
worked hard, developing their homestead and life according to a
twelve-point plan they had drafted.
The narrative of Phil Cousineau's documentary film Ecological Design: Inventing the Future asserts that in the decades after World War II,
"The world was forced to confront the dark shadow of science and
industry... There was a clarion call for a return to a life of human
scale." By the late 1960s, many people had recognized that, leaving
their city or suburban lives, they completely lacked any familiarity
with such basics of life as food sources (for instance, what a potato
plant looks like, or the act of milking a cow)—and they felt out of
touch with nature, in general. While the back-to-the-land movement was
not strictly part of the counterculture of the 1960s, the two movements had some overlap in participation.
Many people were attracted to getting more in touch with the
basics mentioned. Still, the movement could also have been fueled by the
negatives of modern life: rampant consumerism, the failings of government and society, including the Vietnam War, and a perceived general urban deterioration, including growing public concern about air and water pollution. Events such as the Watergate scandal and the 1973 energy crisis
contributed to these views. Some people rejected the struggle and
boredom of "moving up the company ladder." Paralleling the desire for
reconnection with nature was a desire to reconnect with physical work.
Farmer and author Gene Logsdon expressed the aim aptly as: "the kind of
independence that defines success in terms of how much food, clothing,
shelter, and contentment I could produce for myself rather than how much
I could buy."
One prominent segment within the movement included those who were
familiar with rural life and farming, had skills, and wanted land of
their own on which they could demonstrate that organic farming could be made practical and economically successful.
Besides the Nearings and other authors writing later along
similar lines, another influence from the world of American publishing
was the Whole Earth Catalogs. Stewart Brand
and a circle of friends and family began the effort in 1968 because
Brand believed that there was a groundswell of biologists, designers,
engineers, sociologists, organic farmers, and social experimenters who
wished to transform civilization along lines that might be called "sustainable".
Brand and cohorts created a catalog of "tools"—defined broadly to
include useful books, design aids, maps, gardening implements, carpentry
and masonry tools, metalworking equipment, and more.
Another important publication was The Mother Earth News, a periodical (originally on newsprint) that was founded a couple years after the Catalog.
Ultimately gaining a large circulation, the magazine was focused on
how-to articles, personal stories of successful and budding
homesteaders, interviews with key thinkers, and the like. The magazine
stated its philosophy was based on returning to people a greater measure
of control of their own lives.
Many of the North American back-to-the-landers of the 1960s and 1970s used the Mother Earth News, the Whole Earth Catalog
series, and derivative publications. As time went on, however, the
movement drew more people into it, more or less independently of any
impetus from the publishing world.
Antireductionism is the position in science and metaphysics that stands in contrast to reductionism
(anti-holism) by advocating that not all properties of a system can be
explained in terms of its constituent parts and their interactions.
General concepts
The opposite of reductionism is holism, a word coined by Jan Smuts in Holism and Evolution,
that understanding a system can be done only as a whole. One form of
antireductionism (epistemological) holds that we simply are not capable
of understanding systems at the level of their most basic constituents,
and so the program of reductionism must fail. The other kind of
antireductionism (ontological) holds that such a complete explanation in
terms of basic constituents is not possible even in principle for some
systems. Robert Laughlin, e.g. supports this view. Disciplines such as cybernetics and systems theory embrace a
non-reductionist view of science, sometimes going as far as explaining
phenomena at a given level of hierarchy in terms of phenomena at a
higher level, in a sense, the opposite of a reductionist approach.
Although breaking complex phenomena into parts is a key method in
science, there are those complex phenomena (e.g. in physics,
psychology, sociology, ecology) where the approach does not work.
Antireductionism also arises in academic fields such as history,
economics, anthropology, medicine, and biology as attempts to explain
complex phenomena using reductionist models do not provide satisfactory
insight.
Specific views
An example of antireductionism in psychology is Donald Davidson's proposed ontology
of what he calls 'events' and its use "to provide an antireductionist
answer to the mind/matter debate ...[and to show that]...the
impossibility of intertranslating the two idioms by means of psychophysical laws blocks any analytically reductive relation between...the mental and the physical".
Karl Popper was a famous proponent of antireductionism. In his essay Of clouds and clocks,
Popper classified phenomena into two types: "clock" phenomena with a
mechanical basis and "cloud" phenomena which are indivisible and depend
upon emergence for explanation.
For example, Popper thought that a materialist explanation of consciousness is not possible. The view of reductionists about consciousness is explained by Max Velmans:
Most reductionists accept that consciousness seems to be different from brain states (or functions) but claim that science will discover
it to be nothing more than a state or function of the brain. In short,
they mostly accept that brains states and conscious states are conceivably different, but deny that they are actually different (in the universe we happen to inhabit).
Velmans himself is not in agreement with this reductionist stance. Opposition to this mind = brain reductionism is found in many authors. An often mentioned issue is that science cannot explain the hard problem of consciousness, the subjective feelings called qualia. Another objection, whose explicit formulation is due to the physicist and philosopher Thomas Kuhn,
is that science is not a self-contained entity, because the theories
it uses are creations of the human mind, not inevitable results of
experiment and observation, and the criteria for adoption of a
particular theory are not definitive in selecting between alternatives,
but require subjective input. Even the claim that science is based upon testability of its theories has been met with qualifications.
According to Alexander Rosenberg and David Kaplan, the conflict between physicalism and antireductionism can be resolved, that "both reductionists and antireductionists accept that given our cognitive interests and limitations, non-molecular explanations may not be improved, corrected or grounded in molecular ones". However, others find that the conflict between reductionism and
antireductionism is "one of the central problems in the philosophy of
psychology...an updated version of the old mind-body problem:
how levels of theories in the behavioral and brain sciences relate to
one another. Many contemporary philosophers of mind believe that
cognitive-psychological theories are not reducible to neurological
theories...most nonreductive physicalists prefer the idea of a one-way dependence of the mental on the physical."
In physics, a parity transformation (also called parity inversion) is the flip in the sign of onespatialcoordinate. In three dimensions, it can also refer to the simultaneous flip in the sign of all three spatial coordinates (a point reflection or point inversion):
It can also be thought of as a test for chirality of a physical phenomenon, in that a parity inversion transforms a phenomenon into its mirror image.
All fundamental interactions of elementary particles, with the exception of the weak interaction, are symmetric under parity transformation. As established by the Wu experiment conducted at the US National Bureau of Standards by Chinese-American scientist Chien-Shiung Wu,
the weak interaction is chiral and thus provides a means for probing
chirality in physics. In her experiment, Wu took advantage of the
controlling role of weak interactions in radioactive decay of atomic isotopes to establish the chirality of the weak force.
By contrast, in interactions that are symmetric under parity,
such as electromagnetism in atomic and molecular physics, parity serves
as a powerful controlling principle underlying quantum transitions.
A matrix representation of P (in any number of dimensions) has determinant equal to −1, and hence is distinct from a rotation, which has a determinant equal to 1. In a two-dimensional plane, a simultaneous flip of all coordinates in sign is not a parity transformation; it is the same as a 180° rotation.
In quantum mechanics, wave functions that are unchanged by a parity transformation are described as even functions, while those that change sign under a parity transformation are odd functions.
Quantum theory predicts that states in a Hilbert space do not need to transform under representations of the group of rotations, but only under projective representations. The word projective
refers to the fact that if one projects out the phase of each state,
where we recall that the overall phase of a quantum state is not
observable, then a projective representation reduces to an ordinary
representation. All representations are also projective
representations, but the converse is not true, therefore the projective
representation condition on quantum states is weaker than the
representation condition on classical states.
The projective representations of any group are isomorphic to the ordinary representations of a central extension of the group. For example, projective representations of the 3-dimensional rotation group, which is the special orthogonal group SO(3), are ordinary representations of the special unitary group SU(2). Projective representations of the rotation group that are not representations are called spinors and so quantum states may transform not only as tensors but also as spinors.
If one adds to this a classification by parity, these can be extended, for example, into notions of
scalars (P = +1) and pseudoscalars (P = −1) which are rotationally invariant.
vectors (P = −1) and axial vectors (also called pseudovectors) (P = +1) which both transform as vectors under rotation.
One can define reflections such as
which also have negative determinant and form a valid parity
transformation. Then, combining them with rotations (or successively
performing x-, y-, and z-reflections) one can
recover the particular parity transformation defined earlier. The first
parity transformation given does not work in an even number of
dimensions, though, because it results in a positive determinant. In
even dimensions only the latter example of a parity transformation (or
any reflection of an odd number of coordinates) can be used.
Parity forms the abelian group due to the relation . All Abelian groups have only one-dimensional irreducible representations. For , there are two irreducible representations: one is even under parity, , the other is odd, .
These are useful in quantum mechanics. However, as is elaborated
below, in quantum mechanics states need not transform under actual
representations of parity but only under projective representations and
so in principle a parity transformation may rotate a state by any phase.
Representations of O(3)
An
alternative way to write the above classification of scalars,
pseudoscalars, vectors and pseudovectors is in terms of the
representation space that each object transforms in. This can be given
in terms of the group homomorphism which defines the representation. For a matrix
scalars: , the trivial representation
pseudoscalars:
vectors: , the fundamental representation
pseudovectors:
When the representation is restricted to , scalars and pseudoscalars transform identically, as do vectors and pseudovectors.
Classical mechanics
Newton's equation of motion
(if the mass is constant) equates two vectors, and hence is invariant
under parity. The law of gravity also involves only vectors and is also,
therefore, invariant under parity.
In classical electrodynamics, the charge density is a scalar, the electric field, , and current are vectors, but the magnetic field, is an axial vector. However, Maxwell's equations are invariant under parity because the curl of an axial vector is a vector.
Effect of spatial inversion on some variables of classical physics
The
two major divisions of classical physical variables have either even or
odd parity. The way into which particular variables and vectors sort
out into either category depends on whether the number of dimensions of space is either an odd or even number. The categories of odd or even given below for the parity transformation is a different, but intimately related issue.
The answers given below are correct for 3 spatial dimensions. In a
2 dimensional space, for example, when constrained to remain on the
surface of a planet, some of the variables switch sides.
Odd
Classical variables whose signs flip under space inversion are predominantly vectors. They include:
All masses, charges, coupling constants, and other scalar physical constants, except those associated with the weak force.
Quantum mechanics
Possible eigenvalues
Two
dimensional representations of parity are given by a pair of quantum
states which go into each other under parity. However, this
representation can always be reduced to linear combinations of states,
each of which is either even or odd under parity. One says that all irreducible representations of parity are one-dimensional.
In quantum mechanics, spacetime transformations act on quantum states. The parity transformation, , is a unitary operator, in general acting on a state as follows: .
One must then have , since an overall phase is unobservable. The operator ,
which reverses the parity of a state twice, leaves the spacetime
invariant, and so is an internal symmetry which rotates its eigenstates
by phases . If is an element of a continuous U(1) symmetry group of phase rotations, then is part of this U(1) and so is also a symmetry. In particular, we can define , which is also a symmetry, and so we can choose to call our parity operator, instead of . Note that and so has eigenvalues . Wave functions with eigenvalue under a parity transformation are even functions, while eigenvalue corresponds to odd functions. However, when no such symmetry group exists, it may be that all parity
transformations have some eigenvalues which are phases other than .
For electronic wavefunctions, even states are usually indicated by a subscript g for gerade (German: even) and odd states by a subscript u for ungerade (German: odd). For example, the lowest energy level of the hydrogen molecule ion (H2+) is labelled and the next-closest (higher) energy level is labelled .
The wave functions of a particle moving into an external potential, which is centrosymmetric
(potential energy invariant with respect to a space inversion,
symmetric to the origin), either remain invariable or change signs:
these two possible states are called the even state or odd state of the
wave functions.
The law of conservation of parity of particles states that, if an
isolated ensemble of particles has a definite parity, then the parity
remains invariable in the process of ensemble evolution. However this is
not true for the beta decay of nuclei, because the weak nuclear interaction violates parity.
The parity of the states of a particle moving in a spherically symmetric external field is determined by the angular momentum,
and the particle state is defined by three quantum numbers: total
energy, angular momentum and the projection of angular momentum.
Consequences of parity symmetry
When parity generates the Abelian group,
one can always take linear combinations of quantum states such that
they are either even or odd under parity (see the figure). Thus the
parity of such states is ±1. The parity of a multiparticle state is the
product of the parities of each state; in other words parity is a
multiplicative quantum number.
In quantum mechanics, Hamiltonians are invariant (symmetric) under a parity transformation if commutes with the Hamiltonian. In non-relativistic quantum mechanics, this happens for any scalar potential, i.e., , hence the potential is spherically symmetric. The following facts can be easily proven:
For a state of orbital angular momentum with z-axis projection , then .
If , then atomic dipole transitions only occur between states of opposite parity.
If , then a non-degenerate eigenstate of is also an eigenstate of the parity operator; i.e., a non-degenerate eigenfunction of is either invariant to or is changed in sign by .
Some of the non-degenerate eigenfunctions of are unaffected (invariant) by parity and the others are merely reversed in sign when the Hamiltonian operator and the parity operator commute:
The
overall parity of a many-particle system is the product of the parities
of the one-particle states. It is −1 if an odd number of particles are
in odd-parity states, and +1 otherwise. Different notations are in use
to denote the parity of nuclei, atoms, and molecules.
Atoms
Atomic orbitals have parity (−1)ℓ, where the exponent ℓ is the azimuthal quantum number.
The parity is odd for orbitals p, f, ... with ℓ = 1, 3, ..., and an
atomic state has odd parity if an odd number of electrons occupy these
orbitals. For example, the ground state of the nitrogen atom has the
electron configuration 1s22s22p3, and is identified by the term symbol 4So, where the superscript o denotes odd parity. However the third excited term at about 83,300 cm−1 above the ground state has electron configuration 1s22s22p23s has even parity since there are only two 2p electrons, and its term symbol is 4P (without an o superscript).
Molecules
The
complete (rotational-vibrational-electronic-nuclear spin)
electromagnetic Hamiltonian of any molecule commutes with (or is
invariant to) the parity operation P (or E*, in the notation introduced
by Longuet-Higgins) and its eigenvalues can be given the parity symmetry label + or −
as they are even or odd, respectively. The parity operation involves
the inversion of electronic and nuclear spatial coordinates at the
molecular center of mass.
Centrosymmetric molecules at equilibrium have a centre of
symmetry at their midpoint (the nuclear center of mass). This includes
all homonuclear diatomic molecules as well as certain symmetric molecules such as ethylene, benzene, xenon tetrafluoride and sulphur hexafluoride. For centrosymmetric molecules, the point group contains the operation i which is not to be confused with the parity operation. The operation i
involves the inversion of the electronic and vibrational displacement
coordinates at the nuclear centre of mass. For centrosymmetric molecules
the operation i commutes with the rovibronic
(rotation-vibration-electronic) Hamiltonian and can be used to label
such states. Electronic and vibrational states of centrosymmetric
molecules are either unchanged by the operation i, or they are changed in sign by i. The former are denoted by the subscript g and are called gerade, while the latter are denoted by the subscript u and are called ungerade. The complete electromagnetic Hamiltonian of a centrosymmetric molecule
does not commute with the point group inversion operation i because of the effect of the nuclear hyperfine Hamiltonian. The nuclear hyperfine Hamiltonian can mix the rotational levels of g and u vibronic states (called ortho-para mixing) and give rise to ortho-para transitions.
In
atomic nuclei, the state of each nucleon (proton or neutron) has even
or odd parity, and nucleon configurations can be predicted using the nuclear shell model.
As for electrons in atoms, the nucleon state has odd overall parity if
and only if the number of nucleons in odd-parity states is odd. The
parity is usually written as a + (even) or − (odd) following the nuclear
spin value. For example, the oxygen isotope17O(5/2+)
has spin 5/2 and even parity. The shell model explains this because the
first 16 nucleons are paired so that each pair has spin zero and even
parity, and the last nucleon is in the 1d5/2 shell, which has even parity since ℓ = 2 for a d orbital.
Quantum field theory
If one can show that the vacuum state is invariant under parity, , the Hamiltonian is parity invariant and the quantization conditions remain unchanged under parity, then it follows that every state has good parity, and this parity is conserved in any reaction.
To show that quantum electrodynamics
is invariant under parity, we have to prove that the action is
invariant and the quantization is also invariant. For simplicity we will
assume that canonical quantization
is used; the vacuum state is then invariant under parity by
construction. The invariance of the action follows from the classical
invariance of Maxwell's equations. The invariance of the canonical
quantization procedure can be worked out, and turns out to depend on the
transformation of the annihilation operator:
where denotes the momentum of a photon and refers to its polarization state. This is equivalent to the statement that the photon has odd intrinsic parity. Similarly all vector bosons can be shown to have odd intrinsic parity, and all axial-vectors to have even intrinsic parity.
A straightforward extension of these arguments to scalar field theories shows that scalars have even parity. That is, , since
This is true even for a complex scalar field. (Details of spinors are dealt with in the article on the Dirac equation, where it is shown that fermions and antifermions have opposite intrinsic parity.)
With fermions, there is a slight complication because there is more than one spin group.
Applying the parity operator twice leaves the coordinates unchanged, meaning that P2 must act as one of the internal symmetries of the theory, at most changing the phase of a state. For example, the Standard Model has three global U(1) symmetries with charges equal to the baryon numberB, the lepton numberL, and the electric chargeQ. Therefore, the parity operator satisfies P2 = eiαB+iβL+iγQ for some choice of α, β, and γ. This operator is also not unique in that a new parity operator P' can always be constructed by multiplying it by an internal symmetry such as P' = PeiαB for some α.
To see if the parity operator can always be defined to satisfy P2 = 1, consider the general case when P2 = Q for some internal symmetry Q present in the theory. The desired parity operator would be P' = PQ−1/2. If Q is part of a continuous symmetry group then Q−1/2 exists, but if it is part of a discrete symmetry then this element need not exist and such a redefinition may not be possible.
The Standard Model exhibits a (−1)F symmetry, where F is the fermionnumber operator counting how many fermions are in a state. Since all particles in the Standard Model satisfy F = B + L, the discrete symmetry is also part of the eiα(B + L) continuous symmetry group. If the parity operator satisfied P2 = (−1)F, then it can be redefined to give a new parity operator satisfying P2 = 1. But if the Standard Model is extended by incorporating Majorananeutrinos, which have F = 1 and B + L = 0, then the discrete symmetry (−1)F
is no longer part of the continuous symmetry group and the desired
redefinition of the parity operator cannot be performed. Instead it
satisfies P4 = 1 so the Majorana neutrinos would have intrinsic parities of ±i.
Neutrons are fermions and so obey Fermi–Dirac statistics,
which implies that the final state is antisymmetric. Using the fact
that the deuteron has spin one and the pion spin zero together with the
antisymmetry of the final state they concluded that the two neutrons
must have orbital angular momentum
The total parity is the product of the intrinsic parities of the
particles and the extrinsic parity of the spherical harmonic function
Since the orbital momentum changes from zero to one in this process, if
the process is to conserve the total parity then the products of the
intrinsic parities of the initial and final particles must have opposite
sign. A deuteron nucleus is made from a proton and a neutron, and so
using the aforementioned convention that protons and neutrons have
intrinsic parities equal to
they argued that the parity of the pion is equal to minus the product
of the parities of the two neutrons divided by that of the proton and
neutron in the deuteron, explicitly from which they concluded that the pion is a pseudoscalar particle.
P-symmetry: A clock built like its mirrored image behaves like the mirrored image of the original clock.
P-asymmetry: A clock built like its mirrored image that does not behave like a mirrored image of the original clock.
Although parity is conserved in electromagnetism and gravity, it is violated in weak interactions, and perhaps, to some degree, in strong interactions. The Standard Model incorporates parity violation by expressing the weak interaction as a chiral
gauge interaction. Only the left-handed components of particles and
right-handed components of antiparticles participate in charged weak
interactions in the Standard Model. This implies that parity is not a
symmetry of our universe, unless a hidden mirror sector exists in which parity is violated in the opposite way.
An obscure 1928 experiment, undertaken by R. T. Cox, G. C. McIlwraith, and B. Kurrelmeyer, had in effect reported parity violation in weak decays, but, since the appropriate concepts had not yet been developed, those results had no impact. In 1929, Hermann Weyl explored, without any evidence, the existence of a two-component massless particle of spin one-half. This idea was rejected by Pauli, because it implied parity violation.
By the mid-20th century, it had been suggested by several
scientists that parity might not be conserved (in different contexts),
but without solid evidence these suggestions were not considered
important. Then, in 1956, a careful review and analysis by theoretical
physicists Tsung-Dao Lee and Chen-Ning Yang went further, showing that while parity conservation had been verified in decays by the strong or electromagnetic interactions, it was untested in the weak interaction. They proposed several possible direct experimental tests. They were mostly ignored,but Lee was able to convince his Columbia colleague Chien-Shiung Wu to try it. She needed special cryogenic facilities and expertise, so the experiment was done at the National Bureau of Standards.
Wu, Ambler, Hayward, Hoppes, and Hudson (1957) found a clear violation of parity conservation in the beta decay of cobalt-60.[19]
As the experiment was winding down, with double-checking in progress,
Wu informed Lee and Yang of their positive results, and saying the
results need further examination, she asked them not to publicize the
results first. However, Lee revealed the results to his Columbia
colleagues on 4 January 1957 at a "Friday lunch" gathering of the
Physics Department of Columbia. Three of them, R. L. Garwin, L. M. Lederman, and R. M. Weinrich, modified an existing cyclotron experiment, and immediately verified the parity violation. They delayed publication of their results until after Wu's group was
ready, and the two papers appeared back-to-back in the same physics
journal.
The discovery of parity violation explained the outstanding τ–θ puzzle in the physics of kaons.
In 2010, it was reported that physicists working with the Relativistic Heavy Ion Collider had created a short-lived parity symmetry-breaking bubble in quark–gluon plasmas. An experiment conducted by several physicists in the STAR collaboration, suggested that parity may also be violated in the strong interaction. It is predicted that this local parity violation manifests itself by chiral magnetic effect.
Intrinsic parity of hadrons
To
every particle one can assign an intrinsic parity as long as nature
preserves parity. Although weak interactions do not, one can still
assign a parity to any hadron by examining the strong interaction reaction that produces it, or through decays not involving the weak interaction, such as rho meson decay to pions.