In mathematical logic, New Foundations (NF) is an axiomatic set theory, conceived by Willard Van Orman Quine as a simplification of the theory of types of Principia Mathematica.
Quine first proposed NF in a 1937 article titled "New Foundations for
Mathematical Logic"; hence the name. Much of this entry discusses NFU, an important variant of NF due to Jensen (1969) and exposited in Holmes (1998).
In 1940 and in a revision of 1951, Quine introduced an extension of NF
sometimes called "Mathematical Logic" or "ML", that included proper classes as well as sets.
New Foundations has a universal set, so it is a non-well-founded set theory. That is to say, it is an axiomatic set theory that allows infinite descending chains of membership such as … xn ∈ xn-1 ∈ … ∈ x2 ∈ x1. It avoids Russell's paradox by permitting only stratifiable formulas to be defined using the axiom schema of comprehension. For instance x ∈ y is a stratifiable formula, but x ∈ x is not (for details of how this works see below).
New Foundations has a universal set, so it is a non-well-founded set theory. That is to say, it is an axiomatic set theory that allows infinite descending chains of membership such as … xn ∈ xn-1 ∈ … ∈ x2 ∈ x1. It avoids Russell's paradox by permitting only stratifiable formulas to be defined using the axiom schema of comprehension. For instance x ∈ y is a stratifiable formula, but x ∈ x is not (for details of how this works see below).
The type theory TST
The primitive predicates of Russellian unramified typed set theory (TST), a streamlined version of the theory of types, are equality () and membership (). TST has a linear hierarchy of types: type 0 consists of individuals otherwise undescribed. For each (meta-) natural number n, type n+1 objects are sets of type n objects; sets of type n have members of type n-1.
Objects connected by identity must have the same type. The following
two atomic formulas succinctly describe the typing rules: and . (Quinean set theory seeks to eliminate the need for such superscripts.)
The axioms of TST are:
- Extensionality: sets of the same (positive) type with the same members are equal;
- An axiom schema of comprehension, namely:
- If is a formula, then the set exists.
- In other words, given any formula , the formula is an axiom where represents the set and is not free in .
This type theory is much less complicated than the one first set out in the Principia Mathematica, which included types for relations whose arguments were not necessarily all of the same type. In 1914, Norbert Wiener showed how to code the ordered pair as a set of sets, making it possible to eliminate relation types in favor of the linear hierarchy of sets described here.
Quinean set theory
Axioms and stratification
The
well-formed formulas of New Foundations (NF) are the same as the
well-formed formulas of TST, but with the type annotations erased. The
axioms of NF are:
- Extensionality: Two objects with the same elements are the same object;
- A comprehension schema: All instances of TST Comprehension but with type indices dropped (and without introducing new identifications between variables).
By convention, NF's Comprehension schema is stated using the concept of stratified formula and making no direct reference to types. A formula is said to be stratified if there exists a function f from pieces of syntax to the natural numbers, such that for any atomic subformula of we have f(y) = f(x) + 1, while for any atomic subformula of , we have f(x) = f(y). Comprehension then becomes:
- exists for each stratified formula .
Even the indirect reference to types implicit in the notion of stratification can be eliminated. Theodore Hailperin showed in 1944 that Comprehension is equivalent to a finite conjunction of its instances, so that NF can be finitely axiomatized without any reference to the notion of type.
Comprehension may seem to run afoul of problems similar to those in naive set theory, but this is not the case. For example, the existence of the impossible Russell class is not an axiom of NF, because cannot be stratified.
Ordered pairs
Relations and functions are defined in TST (and in NF and NFU) as sets of ordered pairs in the usual way. The usual definition of the ordered pair, first proposed by Kuratowski
in 1921, has a serious drawback for NF and related theories: the
resulting ordered pair necessarily has a type two higher than the type
of its arguments (its left and right projections). Hence for purposes of determining stratification, a function is three types higher than the members of its field.
If one can define a pair in such a way that its type is the same type as that of its arguments (resulting in a type-level
ordered pair), then a relation or function is merely one type higher
than the type of the members of its field. Hence NF and related theories
usually employ Quine's set-theoretic definition of the
ordered pair, which yields a type-level ordered pair. Holmes (1998) takes the ordered pair and its left and right projections
as primitive. Fortunately, whether the ordered pair is type-level by
definition or by assumption (i.e., taken as primitive) usually does not
matter.
The existence of a type-level ordered pair implies Infinity, and NFU + Infinity
interprets NFU + "there is a type level ordered pair" (they are not
quite the same theory, but the differences are inessential). Conversely,
NFU + Infinity + Choice proves the existence of a type-level ordered pair.
Admissibility of useful large sets
NF (and NFU + Infinity + Choice, described below and known consistent) allow the construction of two kinds of sets that ZFC and its proper extensions disallow because they are "too large" (some set theories admit these entities under the heading of proper classes):
- The universal set V. Because is a stratified formula, the universal set V = {x | x=x} exists by Comprehension. An immediate consequence is that all sets have complements, and the entire set-theoretic universe under NF has a Boolean structure.
- Cardinal and ordinal numbers. In NF (and TST), the set of all sets having n elements (the circularity here is only apparent) exists. Hence Frege's definition of the cardinal numbers works in NF and NFU: a cardinal number is an equivalence class of sets under the relation of equinumerosity: the sets A and B are equinumerous if there exists a bijection between them, in which case we write . Likewise, an ordinal number is an equivalence class of well-ordered sets.
Finite axiomatizability
New Foundations can be finitely axiomatized.
Cartesian closure
The category whose objects are the sets of NF and whose arrows are the functions between those sets is not Cartesian closed; Cartesian closure can be a useful property for a category of sets. Since NF lacks Cartesian closure, not every function curries as one might intuitively expect, and NF is not a topos.
For many years, the outstanding problem with NF has been that it has not conclusively been proved to be relatively consistent to any other well-known axiomatic system in which arithmetic can be modelled. NF disproves Choice, and thus proves Infinity (Specker, 1953). But it is also known (Jensen, 1969) that allowing urelements (multiple distinct objects lacking members) yields NFU, a theory that is consistent relative to Peano arithmetic;
if Infinity and Choice are added, the resulting theory has the same
consistency strength as type theory with infinity or bounded Zermelo set
theory. (NFU corresponds to a type theory TSTU, where type 0 has
urelements, not just a single empty set.) There are other relatively
consistent variants of NF.
NFU is, roughly speaking, weaker than NF because in NF, the power
set of the universe is the universe itself, while in NFU, the power set
of the universe may be strictly smaller than the universe (the power
set of the universe contains only sets, while the universe may contain
urelements). In fact, this is necessarily the case in NFU+"Choice".
Specker has shown that NF is equiconsistent with TST + Amb, where Amb is the axiom scheme of typical ambiguity which asserts for any formula , being the formula obtained by raising every type index in
by one. NF is also equiconsistent with the theory TST augmented with a
"type shifting automorphism", an operation which raises type by one,
mapping each type onto the next higher type, and preserves equality and
membership relations (and which cannot be used in instances of Comprehension:
it is external to the theory). The same results hold for various
fragments of TST in relation to the corresponding fragments of NF.
In the same year (1969) that Jensen proved NFU consistent, Grishin proved consistent. is the fragment of NF with full extensionality (no urelements) and those instances of Comprehension
which can be stratified using just three types. This theory is a very
awkward medium for mathematics (although there have been attempts to
alleviate this awkwardness), largely because there is no obvious
definition for an ordered pair. Despite this awkwardness, is very interesting because every infinite model of TST restricted to three types satisfies Amb. Hence for every such model there is a model of with the same theory. This does not hold for four types: is the same theory as NF, and we have no idea how to obtain a model of TST with four types in which Amb holds.
In 1983, Marcel Crabbé proved consistent a system he called NFI,
whose axioms are unrestricted extensionality and those instances of Comprehension in which no variable is assigned a type higher than that of the set asserted to exist. This is a predicativity
restriction, though NFI is not a predicative theory: it admits enough
impredicativity to define the set of natural numbers (defined as the
intersection of all inductive sets; note that the inductive sets
quantified over are of the same type as the set of natural numbers being
defined). Crabbé also discussed a subtheory of NFI, in which only
parameters (free variables) are allowed to have the type of the set
asserted to exist by an instance of Comprehension. He called the
result "predicative NF" (NFP); it is, of course, doubtful whether any
theory with a self-membered universe is truly predicative. Holmes has shown that NFP has the same consistency strength as the predicative theory of types of Principia Mathematica without the Axiom of reducibility.
Since 2015, several candidate proofs by Randall Holmes of the
consistency of NF relative to ZF have been available both on arxiv and
on the logician's home page. Holmes demonstrates the equiconsistency of a
'weird' variant of TST, namely TTTλ - 'tangled type theory with λ-types' - with NF. Holmes next shows that TTTλ
is consistent relative to ZFA, that is, ZF with atoms but without
choice. Holmes demonstrates this by constructing in ZFA+C, that is, ZF
with atoms and choice, a class model of ZFA which includes 'tangled webs
of cardinals' . The candidate proofs are all rather long, but no
irrecoverable faults have been identified by the NF community as yet.
How NF(U) avoids the set-theoretic paradoxes
NF steers clear of the three well-known paradoxes of set theory. That NFU, a consistent (relative to Peano arithmetic) theory, also avoids the paradoxes may increase one's confidence in this fact.
The Russell paradox: An easy matter; is not a stratified formula, so the existence of is not asserted by any instance of Comprehension. Quine said that he constructed NF with this paradox uppermost in mind.
Cantor's paradox of the largest cardinal number exploits the application of Cantor's theorem to the universal set. Cantor's theorem says (given ZFC) that the power set of any set is larger than (there can be no injection (one-to-one map) from into ). Now of course there is an injection from into , if is the universal set! The resolution requires that one observes that makes no sense in the theory of types: the type of is one higher than the type of .
The correctly typed version (which is a theorem in the theory of types
for essentially the same reasons that the original form of Cantor's theorem works in ZF) is , where is the set of one-element subsets of . The specific instance of this theorem of interest is :
there are fewer one-element sets than sets (and so fewer one-element
sets than general objects, if we are in NFU). The "obvious" bijection
from the universe to the one-element sets is not a set; it is not a set
because its definition is unstratified. Note that in all known models
of NFU it is the case that ; Choice allows one not only to prove that there are urelements but that there are many cardinals between and .
One can now introduce some useful notions. A set which satisfies the intuitively appealing is said to be Cantorian: a Cantorian set satisfies the usual form of Cantor's theorem. A set which satisfies the further condition that , the restriction of the singleton map to A, is a set is not only Cantorian set but strongly Cantorian.
The Burali-Forti paradox of the largest ordinal number goes as follows. Define (following naive set theory) the ordinals as equivalence classes of well-orderings under isomorphism. There is an obvious natural well-ordering on the ordinals; since it is a well-ordering it belongs to an ordinal . It is straightforward to prove (by transfinite induction) that the order type of the natural order on the ordinals less than a given ordinal is itself. But this means that is the order type of the ordinals and so is strictly less than the order type of all the ordinals — but the latter is, by definition, itself!
The solution to the paradox in NF(U) starts with the observation
that the order type of the natural order on the ordinals less than is of a higher type than . Hence a type level ordered pair is two types higher than the type of its arguments and the usual Kuratowski ordered pair four types higher. For any order type , we can define an order type one type higher: if , then is the order type of the order . The triviality of the T operation is only a seeming one; it is easy to show that T is a strictly monotone (order preserving) operation on the ordinals.
Now the lemma on order types may be restated in a stratified manner: the order type of the natural order on the ordinals is or
depending on which pair is used (we assume the type level pair
hereinafter). From this one may deduce that the order type on the
ordinals is , and thus .
Hence the T operation is not a function; there cannot be a strictly
monotone set map from ordinals to ordinals which sends an ordinal
downward! Since T is monotone, we have , a "descending sequence" in the ordinals which cannot be a set.
One might assert that this result shows that no model of NF(U) is
"standard", since the ordinals in any model of NFU are externally not
well-ordered. One need not take a position on this, but can note that it
is also a theorem of NFU that any set model of NFU has non-well-ordered
"ordinals"; NFU does not conclude that the universe V is a model of NFU, despite V being a set, because the membership relation is not a set relation.
For a further development of mathematics in NFU, with a comparison to the development of the same in ZFC, see implementation of mathematics in set theory.
The system ML (Mathematical Logic)
ML is an extension of NF that includes proper classes as well as sets.
The set theory of the 1940 first edition of Quine's Mathematical Logic married NF to the proper classes of NBG set theory, and included an axiom schema of unrestricted comprehension for proper classes. However J. Barkley Rosser (1942) proved that the system presented in Mathematical Logic was subject to the Burali-Forti paradox. This result does not apply to NF. Hao Wang (1950)
showed how to amend Quine's axioms for ML so as to avoid this problem,
and Quine included the resulting axiomatization in the 1951 second and
final edition of Mathematical Logic.
Wang proved that if NF is consistent then so is the revised ML,
and also showed that the revised ML can prove the consistency of NF,
that is that NF and the revised ML are equiconsistent.
Models of NFU
There is a fairly simple method for producing models of NFU in bulk. Using well-known techniques of model theory, one can construct a nonstandard model of Zermelo set theory (nothing nearly as strong as full ZFC is needed for the basic technique) on which there is an external automorphism j (not a set of the model) which moves a rank of the cumulative hierarchy of sets. We may suppose without loss of generality that . We talk about the automorphism
moving the rank rather than the ordinal because we do not want to
assume that every ordinal in the model is the index of a rank.
The domain of the model of NFU will be the nonstandard rank . The membership relation of the model of NFU will be
It may now be proved that this actually is a model of NFU. Let
be a stratified formula in the language of NFU. Choose an assignment of
types to all variables in the formula which witnesses the fact that it
is stratified. Choose a natural number N greater than all types assigned to variables by this stratification.
Expand the formula into a formula in the language of the nonstandard model of Zermelo set theory with automorphism j using the definition of membership in the model of NFU. Application of any power of j to both sides of an equation or membership statement preserves its truth value because j is an automorphism. Make such an application to each atomic formula in in such a way that each variable x assigned type i occurs with exactly applications of j.
This is possible thanks to the form of the atomic membership statements
derived from NFU membership statements, and to the formula being
stratified. Each quantified sentence can be converted to the form (and similarly for existential quantifiers). Carry out this transformation everywhere and obtain a formula in which j is never applied to a bound variable.
Choose any free variable y in assigned type i. Apply uniformly to the entire formula to obtain a formula in which y appears without any application of j. Now exists (because j appears applied only to free variables and constants), belongs to , and contains exactly those y which satisfy the original formula
in the model of NFU. has this extension in the model of NFU (the application of j corrects for the different definition of membership in the model of NFU). This establishes that Stratified Comprehension holds in the model of NFU.
To see that weak Extensionality holds is straightforward: each nonempty element of
inherits a unique extension from the nonstandard model, the empty set
inherits its usual extension as well, and all other objects are
urelements.
The basic idea is that the automorphism j codes the "power set" of our "universe" into its externally isomorphic copy inside our "universe." The remaining objects not coding subsets of the universe are treated as urelements.
If is a natural number n, one gets a model of NFU which claims that the universe is finite (it is externally infinite, of course). If is infinite and the Choice holds in the nonstandard model of ZFC, one obtains a model of NFU + Infinity + Choice.
Self-sufficiency of mathematical foundations in NFU
For philosophical reasons, it is important to note that it is not necessary to work in ZFC
or any related system to carry out this proof. A common argument
against the use of NFU as a foundation for mathematics is that the
reasons for relying on it have to do with the intuition that ZFC is
correct. It is sufficient to accept TST (in fact TSTU). In outline: take
the type theory TSTU (allowing urelements in each positive type) as a
metatheory and consider the theory of set models of TSTU in TSTU (these
models will be sequences of sets (all of the same type in the metatheory) with embeddings of each into coding embeddings of the power set of into in a type-respecting manner). Given an embedding of into
(identifying elements of the base "type" with subsets of the base
type), embeddings may be defined from each "type" into its successor in a
natural way. This can be generalized to transfinite sequences with care.
Note that the construction of such sequences of sets is limited
by the size of the type in which they are being constructed; this
prevents TSTU from proving its own consistency (TSTU + Infinity can prove the consistency of TSTU; to prove the consistency of TSTU+Infinity one needs a type containing a set of cardinality , which cannot be proved to exist in TSTU+Infinity
without stronger assumptions). Now the same results of model theory can
be used to build a model of NFU and verify that it is a model of NFU in
much the same way, with the 's being used in place of
in the usual construction. The final move is to observe that since NFU
is consistent, we can drop the use of absolute types in our metatheory,
bootstrapping the metatheory from TSTU to NFU.
Facts about the automorphism j
The automorphism j of a model of this kind is closely related to certain natural operations in NFU. For example, if W is a well-ordering in the nonstandard model (we suppose here that we use Kuratowski pairs
so that the coding of functions in the two theories will agree to some
extent) which is also a well-ordering in NFU (all well-orderings of NFU
are well-orderings in the nonstandard model of Zermelo set theory, but
not vice versa, due to the formation of urelements in the construction of the model), and W has type α in NFU, then j(W) will be a well-ordering of type T(α) in NFU.
In fact, j is coded by a function in the model of NFU. The function in the nonstandard model which sends the singleton of any element of to its sole element, becomes in NFU a function which sends each singleton {x}, where x is any object in the universe, to j(x). Call this function Endo and let it have the following properties: Endo is an injection from the set of singletons into the set of sets, with the property that Endo( {x} ) = {Endo( {y} ) | y∈x} for each set x.
This function can define a type level "membership" relation on the
universe, one reproducing the membership relation of the original
nonstandard model.
Strong axioms of infinity
In this section, the effect is considered of adding various "strong axioms of infinity" to our usual base theory, NFU + Infinity + Choice. This base theory, known consistent, has the same strength as TST + Infinity, or Zermelo set theory with Separation restricted to bounded formulas (Mac Lane set theory).
One can add to this base theory strong axioms of infinity familiar from the ZFC
context, such as "there exists an inaccessible cardinal," but it is
more natural to consider assertions about Cantorian and strongly
Cantorian sets. Such assertions not only bring into being large cardinals of the usual sorts, but strengthen the theory on its own terms.
The weakest of the usual strong principles is:
- Rosser's Axiom of Counting. The set of natural numbers is a strongly Cantorian set.
To see how natural numbers are defined in NFU, see set-theoretic definition of natural numbers. The original form of this axiom given by Rosser was "the set {m|1≤m≤n} has n members", for each natural number n. This intuitively obvious assertion is unstratified: what is provable in NFU is "the set {m|1≤m≤n} has members" (where the T operation on cardinals is defined by ; this raises the type of a cardinal by one). For any cardinal number (including natural numbers) to assert is equivalent to asserting that the sets A
of that cardinality are Cantorian (by a usual abuse of language, we
refer to such cardinals as "Cantorian cardinals"). It is straightforward
to show that the assertion that each natural number is Cantorian is
equivalent to the assertion that the set of all natural numbers is
strongly Cantorian.
Counting is consistent with NFU, but increases its
consistency strength noticeably; not, as one would expect, in the area
of arithmetic, but in higher set theory. NFU + Infinity proves that each exists, but not that exists; NFU + Counting (easily) proves Infinity, and further proves the existence of for each n, but not the existence of .
Counting implies immediately that one does not need to assign types to variables restricted to the set of natural numbers for purposes of stratification; it is a theorem that the power set
of a strongly Cantorian set is strongly Cantorian, so it is further not
necessary to assign types to variables restricted to any iterated power
set of the natural numbers, or to such familiar sets as the set of real
numbers, the set of functions from reals to reals, and so forth. The
set-theoretical strength of Counting is less important in
practice than the convenience of not having to annotate variables known
to have natural number values (or related kinds of values) with
singleton brackets, or to apply the T operation in order to get stratified set definitions.
Counting implies Infinity; each of the axioms below needs to be adjoined to NFU + Infinity to get the effect of strong variants of Infinity; Ali Enayat has investigated the strength of some of these axioms in models of NFU + "the universe is finite".
A model of the kind constructed above satisfies Counting just in case the automorphism j fixes all natural numbers in the underlying nonstandard model of Zermelo set theory.
The next strong axiom we consider is the
- Axiom of strongly Cantorian separation: For any strongly Cantorian set A and any formula (not necessarily stratified!) the set {x∈A|φ} exists.
Immediate consequences include Mathematical Induction for unstratified conditions (which is not a consequence of Counting; many but not all unstratified instances of induction on the natural numbers follow from Counting).
This axiom is surprisingly strong. Unpublished work of Robert Solovay shows that the consistency strength of the theory NFU* = NFU + Counting + Strongly Cantorian Separation is the same as that of Zermelo set theory + Replacement.
This axiom holds in a model of the kind constructed above (with Choice) if the ordinals which are fixed by j and dominate only ordinals fixed by j
in the underlying nonstandard model of Zermelo set theory are standard,
and the power set of any such ordinal in the model is also standard.
This condition is sufficient but not necessary.
Next is
- Axiom of Cantorian Sets: Every Cantorian set is strongly Cantorian.
This very simple and appealing assertion is extremely strong. Solovay
has shown the precise equivalence of the consistency strength of the
theory NFUA = NFU + Infinity + Cantorian Sets with that of ZFC + a schema asserting the existence of an n-Mahlo cardinal for each concrete natural number n.
Ali Enayat has shown that the theory of Cantorian equivalence classes
of well-founded extensional relations (which gives a natural picture of
an initial segment of the cumulative hierarchy of ZFC) interprets the
extension of ZFC with n-Mahlo cardinals directly. A permutation
technique can be applied to a model of this theory to give a model in
which the hereditarily strongly Cantorian sets with the usual membership
relation model the strong extension of ZFC.
This axiom holds in a model of the kind constructed above (with Choice) just in case the ordinals fixed by j in the underlying nonstandard model of ZFC are an initial (proper class) segment of the ordinals of the model.
Next consider the
- Axiom of Cantorian Separation: For any Cantorian set A and any formula (not necessarily stratified!) the set {x∈A|φ} exists.
This combines the effect of the two preceding axioms and is actually
even stronger (precisely how is not known). Unstratified mathematical
induction enables proving that there are n-Mahlo cardinals for every n, given Cantorian Sets, which gives an extension of ZFC that is even stronger than the previous one, which only asserts that there are n-Mahlos for each concrete natural number (leaving open the possibility of nonstandard counterexamples).
This axiom will hold in a model of the kind described above if every ordinal fixed by j is standard, and every power set of an ordinal fixed by j is also standard in the underlying model of ZFC. Again, this condition is sufficient but not necessary.
An ordinal is said to be Cantorian if it is fixed by T, and strongly Cantorian
if it dominates only Cantorian ordinals (this implies that it is itself
Cantorian). In models of the kind constructed above, Cantorian ordinals
of NFU correspond to ordinals fixed by j (they are not the same objects because different definitions of ordinal numbers are used in the two theories).
Equal in strength to Cantorian Sets is the
- Axiom of Large Ordinals: For each non-Cantorian ordinal , there is a natural number n such that .
Recall that is the order type of the natural order on all ordinals. This only implies Cantorian Sets if we have Choice (but is at that level of consistency strength in any case). It is remarkable that one can even define : this is the nth term of any finite sequence of ordinals s of length n such that , for each appropriate i. This definition is completely unstratified. The uniqueness of can be proved (for those n for which it exists) and a certain amount of common-sense reasoning about this notion can be carried out, enough to show that Large Ordinals implies Cantorian Sets in the presence of Choice. In spite of the knotty formal statement of this axiom, it is a very natural assumption, amounting to making the action of T on the ordinals as simple as possible.
A model of the kind constructed above will satisfy Large Ordinals, if the ordinals moved by j are exactly the ordinals which dominate some in the underlying nonstandard model of ZFC.
- Axiom of Small Ordinals: For any formula φ, there is a set A such that the elements of A which are strongly Cantorian ordinals are exactly the strongly Cantorian ordinals such that φ.
Solovay has shown the precise equivalence in consistency strength of NFUB = NFU + Infinity + Cantorian Sets + Small Ordinals with Morse–Kelley set theory plus the assertion that the proper class ordinal (the class of all ordinals) is a weakly compact cardinal. This is very strong indeed! Moreover, NFUB-, which is NFUB with Cantorian Sets omitted, is easily seen to have the same strength as NFUB.
A model of the kind constructed above will satisfy this axiom if every collection of ordinals fixed by j is the intersection of some set of ordinals with the ordinals fixed by j, in the underlying nonstandard model of ZFC.
Even stronger is the theory NFUM = NFU + Infinity + Large Ordinals + Small Ordinals. This is equivalent to Morse–Kelley set theory with a predicate on the classes which is a κ-complete nonprincipal ultrafilter on the proper class ordinal κ; in effect, this is Morse–Kelley set theory + "the proper class ordinal is a measurable cardinal"!
The technical details here are not the main point, which is that
reasonable and natural (in the context of NFU) assertions turn out to be
equivalent in power to very strong axioms of infinity in the ZFC
context. This fact is related to the correlation between the existence
of models of NFU, described above and satisfying these axioms, and the
existence of models of ZFC with automorphisms having special properties.