Common knowledge is a special kind of knowledge for a group of agents. There is common knowledge of p in a group of agents G when all the agents in G know p, they all know that they know p, they all know that they all know that they know p, and so on ad infinitum.
The concept was first introduced in the philosophical literature by David Kellogg Lewis in his study Convention (1969). The sociologist Morris Friedell defined common knowledge in a 1969 paper. It was first given a mathematical formulation in a set-theoretical framework by Robert Aumann (1976). Computer scientists grew an interest in the subject of epistemic logic in general – and of common knowledge in particular – starting in the 1980s. There are numerous puzzles based upon the concept which have been extensively investigated by mathematicians such as John Conway.
The philosopher Stephen Schiffer, in his 1972 book Meaning, independently developed a notion he called "mutual knowledge" which functions quite similarly to Lewis's and Friedel's 1969 "common knowledge".
Example
Puzzle
The idea of common knowledge is often introduced by some variant of induction puzzles:
On an island, there are k people who have blue eyes, and
the rest of the people have green eyes. At the start of the puzzle, no
one on the island ever knows their own eye color. By rule, if a person
on the island ever discovers they have blue eyes, that person must leave
the island at dawn; anyone not making such a discovery always sleeps
until after dawn. On the island, each person knows every other person's
eye color, there are no reflective surfaces, and there is no
communication of eye color.
At some point, an outsider comes to the island, calls together
all the people on the island, and makes the following public
announcement: "At least one of you has blue eyes". The outsider,
furthermore, is known by all to be truthful, and all know that all know
this, and so on: it is common knowledge that he is truthful, and thus it
becomes common knowledge that there is at least one islander who has
blue eyes. The problem: assuming all persons on the island are
completely logical and that this too is common knowledge, what is the
eventual outcome?
Solution
The answer is that, on the kth dawn after the announcement, all the blue-eyed people will leave the island.
Proof
The solution can be seen with an inductive argument. If k = 1
(that is, there is exactly one blue-eyed person), the person will
recognize that he alone has blue eyes (by seeing only green eyes in the
others) and leave at the first dawn. If k = 2, no one will leave at the first dawn. The two blue-eyed people, seeing only one person with blue eyes, and that no one left on the 1st dawn (and thus that k > 1), will leave on the second dawn. Inductively, it can be reasoned that no one will leave at the first k − 1 dawns if and only if there are at least k blue-eyed people. Those with blue eyes, seeing k − 1 blue-eyed people among the others and knowing there must be at least k, will reason that they must have blue eyes and leave.
What's most interesting about this scenario is that, for k > 1,
the outsider is only telling the island citizens what they already
know: that there are blue-eyed people among them. However, before this
fact is announced, the fact is not common knowledge.
For k = 2, it is merely "first-order" knowledge. Each
blue-eyed person knows that there is someone with blue eyes, but each
blue eyed person does not know that the other blue-eyed person has this same knowledge.
For k = 3, it is "second order" knowledge. Each blue-eyed
person knows that a second blue-eyed person knows that a third person
has blue eyes, but no one knows that there is a third blue-eyed person with that knowledge, until the outsider makes his statement.
In general: For k > 1, it is "(k − 1)th order"
knowledge. Each blue-eyed person knows that a second blue-eyed person
knows that a third blue-eyed person knows that.... (repeat for a total
of k − 1 levels) a kth person has blue eyes, but no one knows that there is a "kth" blue-eyed person with that knowledge, until the outsider makes his statement. The notion of common knowledge
therefore has a palpable effect. Knowing that everyone knows does make a
difference. When the outsider's public announcement (a fact already
known to all, unless k=1 then the one person with blue eyes would not
know until the announcement) becomes common knowledge, the blue-eyed
people on this island eventually deduce their status, and leave.
Formalization
Modal logic (syntactic characterization)
Common knowledge can be given a logical definition in multi-modal logic systems in which the modal operators are interpreted epistemically. At the propositional level, such systems are extensions of propositional logic. The extension consists of the introduction of a group G of agents, and of n modal operators Ki (with i = 1, ..., n) with the intended meaning that "agent i knows." Thus Ki (where is a formula of the calculus) is read "agent i knows ." We can define an operator EG with the intended meaning of "everyone in group G knows" by defining it with the axiom
By abbreviating the expression with and defining , we could then define common knowledge with the axiom
There is however a complication. The languages of epistemic logic are usually finitary, whereas the axiom above defines common knowledge as an infinite conjunction of formulas, hence not a well-formed formula of the language. To overcome this difficulty, a fixed-point definition of common knowledge can be given. Intuitively, common knowledge is thought of as the fixed point of the "equation" . In this way, it is possible to find a formula implying from which, in the limit, we can infer common knowledge of .
This syntactic characterization is given semantic content through so-called Kripke structures. A Kripke structure is given by (i) a set of states (or possible worlds) S, (ii) n accessibility relations , defined on , intuitively representing what states agent i considers possible from any given state, and (iii) a valuation function assigning a truth value,
in each state, to each primitive proposition in the language. The
semantics for the knowledge operator is given by stipulating that is true at state s iff is true at all states t such that . The semantics for the common knowledge operator, then, is given by taking, for each group of agents G, the reflexive and transitive closure of the , for all agents i in G, call such a relation , and stipulating that is true at state s iff is true at all states t such that .
Set theoretic (semantic characterization)
Alternatively (yet equivalently) common knowledge can be formalized using set theory (this was the path taken by the Nobel laureate Robert Aumann in his seminal 1976 paper). We will start with a set of states S. We can then define an event E as a subset of the set of states S. For each agent i, define a partition on S, Pi. This partition represents the state of knowledge of an agent in a state. In state s, agent i knows that one of the states in Pi(s) obtains, but not which one. (Here Pi(s) denotes the unique element of Pi containing s. Note that this model excludes cases in which agents know things that are not true.)
We can now define a knowledge function K in the following way:
That is, Ki(e) is the set of states where the agent will know that event e obtains. It is a subset of e.
Similar to the modal logic formulation above, we can define an operator for the idea that "everyone knows e".
As with the modal operator, we will iterate the E function, and . Using this we can then define a common knowledge function,
The equivalence with the syntactic approach sketched above can easily
be seen: consider an Aumann structure as the one just defined. We can
define a correspondent Kripke structure by taking (i) the same space S, (ii) accessibility relations that define the equivalence classes corresponding to the partitions , and (iii) a valuation function such that it yields value true to the primitive proposition p in all and only the states s such that , where is the event of the Aumann structure corresponding to the primitive proposition p. It is not difficult to see that the common knowledge accessibility function defined in the previous section corresponds to the finest common coarsening of the partitions for all , which is the finitary characterization of common knowledge also given by Aumann in the 1976 article.
Applications
Common
knowledge was used by David Lewis in his pioneering game-theoretical
account of convention. In this sense, common knowledge is a concept
still central for linguists and philosophers of language (see Clark
1996) maintaining a Lewisian, conventionalist account of language.
Robert Aumann
introduced a set theoretical formulation of common knowledge
(theoretically equivalent to the one given above) and proved the
so-called agreement theorem through which: if two agents have common prior probability over a certain event, and the posterior probabilities
are common knowledge, then such posterior probabilities are equal. A
result based on the agreement theorem and proven by Milgrom shows that,
given certain conditions on market efficiency and information,
speculative trade is impossible.
The concept of common knowledge is central in game theory.
For several years it has been thought that the assumption of common
knowledge of rationality for the players in the game was fundamental. It
turns out (Aumann and Brandenburger 1995) that, in 2-player games,
common knowledge of rationality is not needed as an epistemic condition
for Nash equilibrium strategies.
Computer scientists use languages incorporating epistemic logics
(and common knowledge) to reason about distributed systems. Such systems
can be based on logics more complicated than simple propositional
epistemic logic, see Wooldridge Reasoning about Artificial Agents,
2000 (in which he uses a first-order logic incorporating epistemic and
temporal operators) or van der Hoek et al. "Alternating Time Epistemic
Logic".
In his 2007 book, The Stuff of Thought: Language as a Window into Human Nature, Steven Pinker uses the notion of common knowledge to analyze the kind of indirect speech involved in innuendoes.