The existence of God is a subject of debate in the philosophy of religion and popular culture.
A wide variety of arguments for and against the existence of God can be categorized as metaphysical, logical, empirical, subjective or scientific. In philosophical terms, the question of the existence of God involves the disciplines of epistemology (the nature and scope of knowledge) and ontology (study of the nature of being, existence, or reality) and the theory of value (since some definitions of God include "perfection").
The Western tradition of philosophical discussion of the existence of God began with Plato and Aristotle, who made arguments that would now be categorized as cosmological. Other arguments for the existence of God have been proposed by St. Anselm, who formulated the first ontological argument; Ibn Rushd (Averroes) and Thomas Aquinas, who presented their own versions of the cosmological argument (the kalam argument and the first way, respectively); René Descartes, who said that the existence of a benevolent God is logically necessary for the evidence of the senses to be meaningful. John Calvin argued for a sensus divinitatis, which gives each human a knowledge of God's existence. Atheists view arguments for the existence of God as insufficient, mistaken or outweighed by arguments against it, whereas some religions, such as Jainism, reject the possibility of a creator deity. Philosophers who have provided arguments against the existence of God include Friedrich Nietzsche and Bertrand Russell.
A wide variety of arguments for and against the existence of God can be categorized as metaphysical, logical, empirical, subjective or scientific. In philosophical terms, the question of the existence of God involves the disciplines of epistemology (the nature and scope of knowledge) and ontology (study of the nature of being, existence, or reality) and the theory of value (since some definitions of God include "perfection").
The Western tradition of philosophical discussion of the existence of God began with Plato and Aristotle, who made arguments that would now be categorized as cosmological. Other arguments for the existence of God have been proposed by St. Anselm, who formulated the first ontological argument; Ibn Rushd (Averroes) and Thomas Aquinas, who presented their own versions of the cosmological argument (the kalam argument and the first way, respectively); René Descartes, who said that the existence of a benevolent God is logically necessary for the evidence of the senses to be meaningful. John Calvin argued for a sensus divinitatis, which gives each human a knowledge of God's existence. Atheists view arguments for the existence of God as insufficient, mistaken or outweighed by arguments against it, whereas some religions, such as Jainism, reject the possibility of a creator deity. Philosophers who have provided arguments against the existence of God include Friedrich Nietzsche and Bertrand Russell.
History
A common misconception is that theism is ancient while atheism is modern, but mankind has been making arguments for and against the existence of deities—including, with the rise of monotheism, God—since the dawn of human history. Bronze Age texts such as the Vedas present various arguments against the deities, such as the problem of evil and the Ultimate Boeing 747 gambit, as well as arguments for the deities, such as argument from morality and Pascal's wager. From the ancient Greeks to the medieval Japanese people to the Native Americans, the arguments for and against deities are as old as the idea of a deity itself. Some atheists and theists
see the antiquity of their beliefs as a worthy tradition to carry on,
while others believe arguing about the existence of a God is a
never-ending cycle that produces little fulfillment.
Positions
Positions on the existence of God can be divided along numerous axes,
producing a variety of orthogonal classifications. Theism and atheism
are positions of belief (or lack of it), while gnosticism and agnosticism are positions of knowledge (or the lack of it). Ignosticism concerns belief about God's conceptual coherence. Apatheism concerns belief about the practical importance of whether God exists.
For the purposes of discussion, Richard Dawkins described seven "milestones" on his spectrum of theistic probability:
- Strong theist. 100% probability that God exists. In the words of C.G. Jung: "I do not believe, I know."
- De facto theist. Very high probability but short of 100%. "I don't know for certain, but I strongly believe in God and live my life on the assumption that he is there."
- Leaning towards theism. Higher than 50% but not very high. "I am very uncertain, but I am inclined to believe in God."
- Completely impartial. Exactly 50%. "God's existence and nonexistence are exactly equiprobable."
- Leaning towards atheism. Lower than 50% but not very low. "I do not know whether God exists but I'm inclined to be skeptical."
- De facto atheist. Very low probability, but short of zero. "I don't know for certain but I think God is very improbable, and I live my life on the assumption that he is not there."
- Strong atheist. "I know there is no God, with the same conviction as Jung knows there is one."
Theism
The Catholic Church, following the teachings of Paul the Apostle, Thomas Aquinas, and the First Vatican Council, affirms that God's existence "can be known with certainty from the created world by the natural light of human reason".
Traditional religious definition of God: personal, omnipotent, benevolent, transcendent
In classical theism,
God is characterized as the metaphysically ultimate being (the first,
timeless, absolutely simple and sovereign being, who is devoid of any anthropomorphic qualities), in distinction to other conceptions such as theistic personalism, open theism, and process theism. Classical theists do not believe that God can be completely defined. They believe it would contradict the transcendent nature of God for mere humans to define him. Robert Barron explains by analogy that it seems impossible for a two-dimensional object to conceive of three-dimensional humans.
In modern Western societies, the concepts of God typically entail a monotheistic, supreme, ultimate, and personal being, as found in the Christian, Islamic and Jewish traditions. In monotheistic religions outside the Abrahamic traditions,
the existence of God is discussed in similar terms. In these
traditions, God is also identified as the author (either directly or by
inspiration) of certain texts, or that certain texts describe specific
historical events caused by the God in question or communications from
God (whether in direct speech or via dreams or omens). Some traditions
also believe that God is the entity which is currently answering prayers
for intervention or information or opinions.
Many Islamic scholars have used philosophical and rational arguments to prove the existence of God. For example, Ibn Rushd,
a 12th-century Islamic scholar, philosopher, and physician, states
there are only two arguments worthy of adherence, both of which are
found in what he calls the "Precious Book" (The Qur'an). Rushd cites
“providence” and “invention” in using the Qur'an's parables to claim the
existence of God. Rushd argues that the Earth's weather patterns are
conditioned to support human life; thus, if the planet is so
finely-tuned to maintain life, then it suggests a fine tuner - God. The
Sun and the Moon are not just random objects floating in the Milky Way,
rather they serve us day and night, and the way nature works and how
life is formed, humankind benefits from it. Rushd essentially comes to a
conclusion that there has to be a higher being who has made everything
perfectly to serve the needs of human beings.
Moses ben Maimon, widely known as Maimonides,
was a Jewish scholar who tried to logically prove the existence of God.
Maimonides offered proofs for the existence of God, but he did not
begin with defining God first, like many others do. Rather, he used the
description of the earth and the universe to prove the existence of God.
He talked about the Heavenly bodies and how they are committed to
eternal motion. Maimonides argued that because every physical object is
finite, it can only contain a finite amount of power. If everything in
the universe, which includes all the planets and the stars, is finite,
then there has to be an infinite power to push forth the motion of
everything in the universe. Narrowing down to an infinite being, the
only thing that can explain the motion is an infinite being (meaning
God) which is neither a body nor a force in the body. Maimonides
believed that this argument gives us a ground to believe that God is,
not an idea of what God is. He believed that God cannot be understood or
be compared.
Non-personal definitions of God
In pantheism,
God and the universe are considered to be the same thing. In this
view, the natural sciences are essentially studying the nature of God.
This definition of God creates the philosophical problem that a universe
with God and one without God are the same, other than the words used to
describe it.
Deism and panentheism
assert that there is a God distinct from, or which extends beyond
(either in time or in space or in some other way) the universe. These
positions deny that God intervenes in the operation of the universe,
including communicating with humans personally. The notion that God
never intervenes or communicates with the universe, or may have evolved
into the universe (as in pandeism), makes it difficult, if not by definition impossible, to distinguish between a universe with God and one without.
Debate about how theism should be argued
In
Christian faith, theologians and philosophers make a distinction
between: (a) preambles of faith and (b) articles of faith. The preambles
include alleged truths contained in revelation which are nevertheless
demonstrable by reason, e.g., the immortality of the soul, the existence
of God. The articles of faith, on the other hand, contain truths that
cannot be proven or reached by reason alone and presuppose the truths of
the preambles, e.g., the Holy Trinity, is not demonstrable and
presupposes the existence of God.
The argument that the existence of God can be known to all, even
prior to exposure to any divine revelation, predates Christianity. Paul the Apostle
made this argument when he said that pagans were without excuse because
"since the creation of the world God's invisible nature, namely, his
eternal power and deity, has been clearly perceived in the things that
have been made". In this, Paul alludes to the proofs for a creator, later enunciated by Thomas Aquinas and others, but that had also been explored by the Greek philosophers.
Another apologetical school of thought, including Dutch and American Reformed thinkers (such as Abraham Kuyper, Benjamin Warfield, Herman Dooyeweerd), emerged in the late 1920s. This school was instituted by Cornelius Van Til, and came to be popularly called presuppositional apologetics
(though Van Til himself felt "transcendental" would be a more accurate
title). The main distinction between this approach and the more
classical evidentialist approach is that the presuppositionalist denies
any common ground between the believer and the non-believer, except that
which the non-believer denies, namely, the assumption of the truth of
the theistic worldview. In other words, presuppositionalists do not
believe that the existence of God can be proven by appeal to raw,
uninterpreted, or "brute" facts, which have the same (theoretical)
meaning to people with fundamentally different worldviews, because they
deny that such a condition is even possible. They claim that the only
possible proof for the existence of God is that the very same belief is
the necessary condition to the intelligibility of all other human
experience and action. They attempt to prove the existence of God by
means of appeal to the transcendental
necessity of the belief—indirectly (by appeal to the unavowed
presuppositions of the non-believer's worldview) rather than directly
(by appeal to some form of common factuality). In practice this school
utilizes what have come to be known as transcendental arguments.
In these arguments they claim to demonstrate that all human experience
and action (even the condition of unbelief, itself) is a proof for the
existence of God, because God's existence is the necessary condition of
their intelligibility.
Alvin Plantinga presents an argument for the existence of God using modal logic. Others have said that the logical and philosophical arguments for and against the existence of God miss the point. The word God
has a meaning in human culture and history that does not correspond to
the beings whose existence is supported by such arguments, assuming they
are valid. The real question is not whether a "most perfect being" or
an "uncaused first cause" exist. The real question is whether Jehovah, Zeus, Ra,
Krishna, or any gods of any religion exist, and if so, which gods? On
the other hand, many theists equate all monotheistic or henotheistic
"most perfect Beings", no matter what name is assigned to them/him, as
the one monotheistic God (one example would be understanding the Muslim Allah, Christian YHWH, and Chinese Shangdi
as different names for the same Being). Most of these arguments do not
resolve the issue of which of these figures is more likely to exist.
These arguments fail to make the distinction between immanent gods and a
Transcendent God.
Some Christians note that the Christian faith teaches "salvation is by faith",
and that faith is reliance upon the faithfulness of God. The most
extreme example of this position is called fideism, which holds that
faith is simply the will to believe, and argues that if God's existence
were rationally demonstrable, faith in its existence would become
superfluous. Søren Kierkegaard
argued that objective knowledge, such as 1+1=2, is unimportant to
existence. If God could rationally be proven, his existence would be
unimportant to humans. It is because God cannot rationally be proven that his existence is important to us. In The Justification of Knowledge, the Calvinist theologian Robert L. Reymond
argues that believers should not attempt to prove the existence of God.
Since he believes all such proofs are fundamentally unsound, believers
should not place their confidence in them, much less resort to them in
discussions with non-believers; rather, they should accept the content
of revelation by faith. Reymond's position is similar to that of his
mentor Gordon Clark,
which holds that all worldviews are based on certain unprovable first
premises (or, axioms), and therefore are ultimately unprovable. The
Christian theist therefore must simply choose to start with Christianity
rather than anything else, by a "leap of faith". This position is also sometimes called presuppositional apologetics, but should not be confused with the Van Tillian variety.
Atheism
The atheistic conclusion is that the arguments and evidence both
indicate there is insufficient reason to believe that any gods exist,
and that personal subjective religious experiences say something about
the human experience rather than the nature of reality itself;
therefore, one has no reason to believe that a god exists.
Positive atheism
Positive atheism (also called "strong atheism" and "hard atheism") is a form of atheism that asserts that no deities exist. The strong atheist explicitly asserts the non-existence of gods.
Negative atheism
Negative
atheism (also called "weak atheism" and "soft atheism") is any type of
atheism other than positive, wherein a person does not believe in the
existence of any deities, but does not explicitly assert there to be
none.
Agnosticism
Agnosticism is the view that the truth value
of certain claims—especially claims about the existence of any deity,
but also other religious and metaphysical claims—is unknown or
unknowable. Agnosticism does not define one's belief or disbelief in gods; agnostics may still identify themselves as theists or atheists.
Strong agnosticism
Strong agnosticism is the belief that it is impossible for humans to know whether or not any deities exist.
Weak agnosticism
Weak agnosticism is the belief that the existence or nonexistence of deities is unknown but not necessarily unknowable.
Agnostic theism
Agnostic theism is the philosophical
view that encompasses both theism and agnosticism. An agnostic theist
believes in the existence of a god or God, but regards the basis of this
proposition as unknown or inherently unknowable. Agnostic theists may also insist on ignorance regarding the properties of the gods they believe in.
Agnostic atheism
Agnostic atheism is a philosophical position that encompasses both
atheism and agnosticism. Agnostic atheists are atheistic because they do
not hold a belief in the existence of any deity and agnostic because they claim that the existence of a deity is either unknowable in principle or currently unknown in fact.
The theologian Robert Flint explains:
If a man have failed to find any good reason for believing that there is a God, it is perfectly natural and rational that he should not believe that there is a God; and if so, he is an atheist, although he assume no superhuman knowledge, but merely the ordinary human power of judging of evidence. If he go farther, and, after an investigation into the nature and reach of human knowledge, ending in the conclusion that the existence of God is incapable of proof, cease to believe in it on the ground that he cannot know it to be true, he is an agnostic and also an atheist, an agnostic-atheist—an atheist because an agnostic."
Apatheism
An apatheist is someone who is not interested in accepting or denying
any claims that gods exist or do not exist. An apatheist lives as if
there are no gods and explains natural phenomena
without reference to any deities. The existence of gods is not
rejected, but may be designated unnecessary or useless; gods neither
provide purpose to life, nor influence everyday life, according to this view.
Ignosticism
The ignostic (or igtheist) usually concludes that the question of
God's existence or nonexistence is usually not worth discussing because
concepts like "God" are usually not sufficiently or clearly defined.
Ignosticism or igtheism is the theological position that every other
theological position (including agnosticism
and atheism) assumes too much about the concept of God and many other
theological concepts. It can be defined as encompassing two related
views about the existence of God. The view that a coherent definition of
God must be presented before the question of the existence of God can
be meaningfully discussed. Furthermore, if that definition is unfalsifiable, the ignostic takes the theological noncognitivist position that the question of the existence of God (per that definition) is meaningless. In this case, the concept of God is not considered meaningless; the
term "God" is considered meaningless. The second view is synonymous with
theological noncognitivism, and skips the step of first asking "What is
meant by 'God'?" before proclaiming the original question "Does God
exist?" as meaningless.
Some philosophers have seen ignosticism as a variation of agnosticism or atheism, while others have considered it to be distinct. An ignostic maintains that he cannot even say whether he is a theist or an atheist until a sufficient definition of theism is put forth.
The term "ignosticism" was coined in the 1960s by Sherwin Wine, a rabbi and a founding figure of Humanistic Judaism. The term "igtheism" was coined by the secular humanist Paul Kurtz in his 1992 book The New Skepticism.
Philosophical issues
The problem of the supernatural
One problem posed by the question of the existence of God is that traditional beliefs usually ascribe to God various supernatural powers. Supernatural beings may be able to conceal and reveal themselves for their own purposes, as for example in the tale of Baucis and Philemon.
In addition, according to concepts of God, God is not part of the
natural order, but the ultimate creator of nature and of the scientific
laws. Thus in Aristotelian philosophy,
God is viewed as part of the explanatory structure needed to support
scientific conclusions and any powers God possesses are—strictly
speaking—of the natural order that is derived from God's place as
originator of nature (see also Monadology).
In Karl Popper's philosophy of science,
belief in a supernatural God is outside the natural domain of
scientific investigation because all scientific hypotheses must be
falsifiable in the natural world. The non-overlapping magisteria view proposed by Stephen Jay Gould also holds that the existence (or otherwise) of God is irrelevant to and beyond the domain of science.
Scientists follow the scientific method, within which theories must be verifiable by physical experiment.
The majority of prominent conceptions of God explicitly or effectively
posit a being whose existence is not testable either by proof or
disproof. Therefore, the question of God's existence may lie outside the purview of modern science by definition. The Catholic Church maintains that knowledge of the existence of God is the "natural light of human reason". Fideists maintain that belief in God's existence may not be amenable to demonstration or refutation, but rests on faith alone.
Logical positivists such as Rudolf Carnap and A. J. Ayer
viewed any talk of gods as literal nonsense. For the logical
positivists and adherents of similar schools of thought, statements
about religious or other transcendent experiences can not have a truth value,
and are deemed to be without meaning, because such statements do not
have any clear verification criteria. As the Christian biologist Scott C. Todd
put it "Even if all the data pointed to an intelligent designer, such a
hypothesis is excluded from science because it is not naturalistic." This argument limits the domain of science to the empirically observable and limits the domain of God to the unprovable.
Nature of relevant proofs and arguments
John Polkinghorne suggests that the nearest analogy to the existence of God in physics is the ideas of quantum mechanics which are seemingly paradoxical but make sense of a great deal of disparate data.
Alvin Plantinga compares the question of the existence of God to the question of the existence of other minds, claiming both are notoriously impossible to "prove" against a determined skeptic.
One approach, suggested by writers such as Stephen D. Unwin, is to treat (particular versions of) theism and naturalism as though they were two hypotheses in the Bayesian
sense, to list certain data (or alleged data), about the world, and to
suggest that the likelihoods of these data are significantly higher
under one hypothesis than the other.
Most of the arguments for, or against, the existence of God can be seen
as pointing to particular aspects of the universe in this way. In
almost all cases it is not seriously suggested by proponents of the
arguments that they are irrefutable, merely that they make one worldview
seem significantly more likely than the other. However, since an
assessment of the weight of evidence depends on the prior probability that is assigned to each worldview, arguments that a theist finds convincing may seem thin to an atheist and vice versa.
Philosophers, such as Wittgenstein, take a view that is considered anti-realist and oppose philosophical arguments related to God's existence. For instance, Charles Taylor
contends that the real is whatever will not go away. If we cannot
reduce talk about God to anything else, or replace it, or prove it
false, then perhaps God is as real as anything else.
In George Berkeley's A Treatise Concerning the Principles of Human Knowledge
of 1710, he argued that a "naked thought" cannot exist, and that a
perception is a thought; therefore only minds can be proven to exist,
since all else is merely an idea conveyed by a perception. From this
Berkeley argued that the universe is based upon observation and is
non-objective. However, he noted that the universe includes "ideas" not
perceptible to humankind, and that there must, therefore, exist an
omniscient superobserver, which perceives such things. Berkeley
considered this proof of the existence of the Christian god.
C.S. Lewis, in Mere Christianity and elsewhere, raised the argument from desire.
He posed that all natural desires have a natural object. One thirsts,
and there exists water to quench this thirst; One hungers, and there
exists food to satisfy this hunger. He then argued that the human desire
for perfect justice, perfect peace, perfect happiness, and other
intangibles strongly implies the existence of such things, though they
seem unobtainable on earth. He further posed that the unquenchable
desires of this life strongly imply that we are intended for a different
life, necessarily governed by a God who can provide the desired
intangibles.
Outside of Western thought
Existence in absolute truth is central to Vedanta
epistemology. Traditional sense perception based approaches were put
into question as possibly misleading due to preconceived or superimposed
ideas. But though all object-cognition can be doubted, the existence of
the doubter remains a fact even in nastika traditions of mayavada schools following Adi Shankara. The five eternal principles to be discussed under ontology, beginning with God or Isvara, the Ultimate Reality cannot be established by the means of logic alone, and often require superior proof.
In Vaisnavism Vishnu, or his intimate ontological form of Krishna, is equated to the personal absolute God of the Western traditions. Aspects of Krishna as svayam bhagavan in original Absolute Truth, sat chit ananda, are understood originating from three essential attributes of Krishna's form, i.e., "eternal existence" or sat, related to the brahman aspect; "knowledge" or chit, to the paramatman; and "bliss" or ananda in Sanskrit, to bhagavan.
Arguments for the existence of God
Empirical arguments
Argument from beauty
One form of the argument from beauty is that the elegance of the laws of physics, which have been empirically discovered, or the elegant laws of mathematics, which are abstract but which have empirically proven to be useful, is evidence of a creator deity who has arranged these things to be beautiful and not ugly.
Argument from consciousness
The argument from consciousness
claims that human consciousness cannot be explained by the physical
mechanisms of the human body and brain, therefore, asserting that there
must be non-physical aspects to human consciousness. This is held as
indirect evidence of God, given that notions about souls and the afterlife
in Christianity and Islam would be consistent with such a claim.
Critics point out that non-physical aspects of consciousness could exist
in a universe without any gods; for example, some religions that
believe in reincarnation are compatible with atheism, monotheism, and polytheism.
The notion of the soul was created before modern understanding of neural networks and the physiology of the brain. Decades of experimentation lead cognitive science to consider thought and emotion as physical processes although the experience of consciousness still remains poorly understood. The hard problem of consciousness
remains as to whether different people subjectively experience the
world in the same way — for example, that the color blue looks the same
inside the minds of different people, though this is a philosophical
problem with both physical and non-physical explanations.
Argument from design
The teleological argument, or the argument from design, asserts that certain features of the universe and of living things must be the product of an intelligent cause. Its proponents are mainly Christians.
Rational warrant
Philosopher Stephen Toulmin is notable for his work in the history of ideas that features the (rational) warrant: a statement that connects the premises to a conclusion.
Joseph Hinman applied Toulmin's approach in his argument for the existence of God, particularly in his book The Trace of God: A Rational Warrant for Belief.
Instead of attempting to prove the existence of God, Hinman argues you
can "demonstrate the rationally-warranted nature of belief".
Hinman uses a wide range of studies, including ones by Robert
Wuthnow, Andrew Greeley, Mathes and Kathleen Nobel to establish that
mystical experiences are life-transformative in a way that is
significant, positive and lasting.
He draws on additional work to add several additional major points to
his argument. First, the people who have these experiences not only do
not exhibit traditional signs of mental illness but, often, are in
better mental and physical health than the general population due to the
experience. Second, the experiences work. In other words, they provide a framework for navigating life that is useful and effective. All of the evidence of the positive effects of the experience upon people's lives he, adapting a term from Derrida, terms "the trace of God": the footprints left behind that point to the impact.
Finally, he discusses how both religious experience and belief in God is, and has always been, normative among humans:
people do not need to prove the existence of God. If there is no need
to prove, Hinman argues, and the Trace of God (for instance, the impact
of mystical experiences on them), belief in God is rationally warranted.
Inductive arguments
Some have put forward arguments for the existence of God based on inductive reasoning.
For example, one class of philosophers asserts that the proofs for the
existence of God present a fairly large probability though not absolute
certainty. A number of obscure points, they say, always remain; an act
of faith is required to dismiss these difficulties. This view is
maintained, among others, by the Scottish statesman Arthur Balfour in his book The Foundations of Belief (1895). The opinions set forth in this work were adopted in France by Ferdinand Brunetière, the editor of the Revue des deux Mondes.
Many orthodox Protestants express themselves in the same manner, as,
for instance, Dr. E. Dennert, President of the Kepler Society, in his
work Ist Gott tot?
Logical arguments
Aquinas' Five Ways
In article 3, question 2, first part of his Summa Theologica, Thomas Aquinas developed his five arguments for God's existence. These arguments are grounded in an Aristotelian ontology and make use of the infinite regression argument.
Aquinas did not intend to fully prove the existence of God as he is
orthodoxly conceived (with all of his traditional attributes), but
proposed his Five Ways as a first stage, which he built upon later in
his work. Aquinas' Five Ways argued from the unmoved mover, first cause, necessary being, argument from degree, and the argument from final cause.
- The unmoved mover argument asserts that, from our experience of motion in the universe (motion being the transition from potentiality to actuality) we can see that there must have been an initial mover. Aquinas argued that whatever is in motion must be put in motion by another thing, so there must be an unmoved mover.
- Aquinas' argument from first cause started with the premise that it is impossible for a being to cause itself (because it would have to exist before it caused itself) and that it is impossible for there to be an infinite chain of causes, which would result in infinite regress. Therefore, there must be a first cause, itself uncaused.
- The argument from necessary being asserts that all beings are contingent, meaning that it is possible for them not to exist. Aquinas argued that if everything can possibly not exist, there must have been a time when nothing existed; as things exist now, there must exist a being with necessary existence, regarded as God.
- Aquinas argued from degree, considering the occurrence of degrees of goodness. He believed that things which are called good, must be called good in relation to a standard of good—a maximum. There must be a maximum goodness that which causes all goodness.
- The argument from final cause asserts the view that non-intelligent objects are ordered towards a purpose. Aquinas argued that these objects cannot be ordered unless they are done so by an intelligent being, which means that there must be an intelligent being to move objects to their ends: God.
Cosmological argument
The cosmological, or "first cause" argument asserts that since
everything that begins to exist has a cause, and the universe began to
exist, the universe must have had a cause which was itself not caused.
This ultimate first cause is identified with God. Christian apologist William Lane Craig gives a version of this argument in the following form:
- Whatever begins to exist has a cause.
- The Universe began to exist.
- Therefore, the Universe had a cause.
Ontological argument
The ontological argument has been formulated by philosophers including St. Anselm and René Descartes. The argument proposes that God's existence is self-evident. The logic, depending on the formulation, reads roughly as follows:
Whatever is contained in a clear and distinct idea of a thing must be predicated of that thing; but a clear and distinct idea of an absolutely perfect Being contains the idea of actual existence; therefore since we have the idea of an absolutely perfect Being such a Being must really exist.
Thomas Aquinas criticized the argument for proposing a definition of
God which, if God is transcendent, should be impossible for humans.
Immanuel Kant criticized the proof from a logical standpoint: he stated
that the term "God" really signifies two different terms: both idea of
God, and God. Kant concluded that the proof is equivocation, based on
the ambiguity of the word God.
Kant also challenged the argument's assumption that existence is a
predicate (of perfection) because it does not add anything to the
essence of a being. If existence is not a predicate, then it is not necessarily true that the greatest possible being exists.
A common rebuttal to Kant's critique is that, although "existence" does
add something to both the concept and the reality of God, the concept
would be vastly different if its referent is an unreal Being. Another response to Kant is attributed to Alvin Plantinga, who says
that even if one were to grant that existence is not a real predicate, necessary existence, which is the correct formulation of an understanding of God, is a real predicate.
Subjective arguments
Arguments from historical events or personages
- The sincere seeker's argument, espoused by Muslim Sufis of the Tasawwuf tradition, posits that every individual who follows a formulaic path towards guidance, arrives at the same destination of conviction in the existence of God and specifically in the monotheistic tenets and laws of Islam. This could only be true if the formula and supplication were being answered by the same Divine entity being addressed, as claimed in Islamic revelations. This was formally organized by Imam Abu Hamid Al-Ghazali in such notable works as "Deliverance from Error" and "The Alchemy of Happiness," in Arabic "Kimiya-yi sa'adat". The path includes following the golden rule of no harm to others and treating others with compassion, silence or minimal speech, seclusion, daily fasting or minimalist diet of water and basic nourishment, honest wages, and daily supplication towards "the Creator of the Universe" for guidance.
- Christianity and Judaism assert that God intervened in key specific moments in history, especially at the Exodus and the giving of the Ten Commandments in front of all the tribes of Israel, positing an argument from empirical evidence stemming from sheer number of witnesses, thus demonstrating his existence.
- Christological arguments assert that certain events of the Christian New Testament are historically accurate, and prove God's existence, namely:
- The Resurrection of Jesus (an argument from miracles)
- The claims of Jesus, as a morally upstanding person, to be the son of God (an argument from authority)
- The belief of Jesus, as a wise person, that God exists (an argument from authority)
- Islam asserts that the revelation of its holy book, the Qur'an, and its unique literary attributes, vindicate its divine authorship, and thus the existence of God.
- The Church of Jesus Christ of Latter-day Saints, also known as Mormonism, similarly asserts that the miraculous appearance of God, Jesus Christ, and angels to Joseph Smith and others and subsequent finding and translation of the Book of Mormon establishes the existence of God. The whole Latter Day Saint movement makes the same claim for example Community of Christ, Church of Christ (Temple Lot), Church of Jesus Christ (Bickertonite), Church of Jesus Christ of Latter Day Saints (Strangite), Church of Jesus Christ (Cutlerite), etc
- The Church of Jesus Christ of Latter Day Saints (Strangite), similarly asserts that the finding and translation of the Plates of Laban, also known as the Brass Plates, into the Book of the Law of the Lord and Voree plates by James Strang, One Mighty and Strong, establishes the existence of God.
- Various sects that have broken from the Church of Christ (Temple Lot) (such as Church of Christ "With the Elijah Message" and Church of Christ (Assured Way)) claim that the message brought by John the Baptist, One Mighty and Strong, to Otto Fetting and W. A. Draves in The Word of the Lord Brought to Mankind by an Angel establishes the existence of God.
Arguments from testimony
Arguments
from testimony rely on the testimony or experience of witnesses,
possibly embodying the propositions of a specific revealed religion.
Swinburne argues that it is a principle of rationality that one should
accept testimony unless there are strong reasons for not doing so.
- The witness argument gives credibility to personal witnesses, contemporary and throughout the ages. A variation of this is the argument from miracles (also referred to as "the priest stories") which relies on testimony of supernatural events to establish the existence of God.
- The majority argument argues that the theism of people throughout most of recorded history and in many different places provides prima facie demonstration of God's existence.
Arguments grounded in personal experiences
- The sincere seeker's argument, espoused by Muslim Sufis of the Tasawwuf tradition, posits that every individual who follows a formulaic path towards guidance, arrives at the same destination of conviction in the existence of God and specifically in the monotheistic tenets and laws of Islam. This apparent natural law for guidance and belief could only be consistent if the formula and supplication were being answered by the same Divine entity being addressed, as claimed in Islamic revelations. This was formally organized by Imam Abu Hamid Al-Ghazali in such notable works as "Deliverance from Error" and "The Alchemy of Happiness," in Arabic "Kimiya-yi sa'ādat". The path includes following the golden rule of no harm to others and treating others with compassion, silence or minimal speech, seclusion, daily fasting or minimalist diet of water and basic nourishment, honest wages, and daily supplication towards "the Creator of the Universe" for guidance.
- The Argument from a proper basis argues that belief in God is "properly basic"; that it is similar to statements like "I see a chair" or "I feel pain". Such beliefs are non-falsifiable and, thus, neither provable nor disprovable; they concern perceptual beliefs or indisputable mental states.
- In Germany, the School of Friedrich Heinrich Jacobi taught that human reason is able to perceive the suprasensible. Jacobi distinguished three faculties: sense, reason, and understanding. Just as sense has immediate perception of the material so has reason immediate perception of the immaterial, while the understanding brings these perceptions to a person's consciousness and unites them to one another. God's existence, then, cannot be proven (Jacobi, like Immanuel Kant, rejected the absolute value of the principle of causality), it must be felt by the mind.
- The same theory was advocated in Germany by Friedrich Schleiermacher, who assumed an inner religious sense by means of which people feel religious truths. According to Schleiermacher, religion consists solely in this inner perception, and dogmatic doctrines are inessential.
- Brahma Kumaris religion was established in 1936, when God was said to enter the body of diamond merchant Lekhraj Kripalani (1876–1969) in Hyderabad, Sindh and started to speak through him.
Hindu arguments
The school of Vedanta argues that one of the proofs of the existence of God is the law of karma. In a commentary to Brahma Sutras (III, 2, 38, and 41), Adi Sankara
argues that the original karmic actions themselves cannot bring about
the proper results at some future time; neither can super sensuous,
non-intelligent qualities like adrsta
by themselves mediate the appropriate, justly deserved pleasure and
pain. The fruits, according to him must be administered through the
action of a conscious agent, namely, a supreme being (Ishvara). The Nyaya school make similar arguments.
Other arguments
- The evolutionary argument against naturalism, which argues that naturalistic evolution is incapable of providing humans with the cognitive apparatus necessary for their knowledge to have positive epistemic status.
- An argument from belief in God being properly basic as presented by Alvin Plantinga.
- Argument from Personal Identity.
- Argument from the "divine attributes of scientific law".
Arguments against the existence of God
The arguments below aim to show that a god or set of gods does not exist—by showing a creator is unnecessary or contradictory, at odds with known scientific or historical facts, or that there is insufficient proof that a god does exist.
Empirical arguments
The following empirical arguments rely on observations or experimentation to yield their conclusions.
Arguments from inadequate revelations
The argument from inconsistent revelations contests the existence of the deity called God as described in scriptures—such as the Hindu Vedas, the Jewish Tanakh, the Christian Bible, the Muslim Qur'an, the Book of Mormon or the Baha'i Aqdas—by
identifying apparent contradictions between different scriptures,
within a single scripture, or between scripture and known facts.
Relatedly, the argument from parsimony (using Occam's razor) contends that since natural (non-supernatural) theories adequately explain the development of religion and belief in gods,
the actual existence of such supernatural agents is superfluous and may
be dismissed unless otherwise proven to be required to explain the
phenomenon.
The argument from "historical induction" concludes that since most theistic religions throughout history (e.g. ancient Egyptian religion, ancient Greek religion)
and their gods ultimately come to be regarded as untrue or incorrect,
all theistic religions, including contemporary ones, are therefore most
likely untrue/incorrect by induction. H. L. Mencken wrote a short piece about the topic entitled "Memorial Service" in 1922. It is implied as part of Stephen F. Roberts' popular quotation:
I contend that we are both atheists. I just believe in one fewer god than you do. When you understand why you dismiss all the other possible gods, you will understand why I dismiss yours.
The argument from nonbelief
contests the existence of an omnipotent god who wants humans to believe
in it by arguing that such a god would do a better job of gathering
believers.
Arguments from the poor design of the universe
The problem of evil contests the existence of a god who is both omnipotent and omnibenevolent by arguing that such a god should not permit the existence of evil or suffering. The theist responses are called theodicies. Similarly, the argument from poor design
contends that an all-powerful, benevolent creator god would not have
created lifeforms, including humans, which seem to exhibit poor design.
Richard Carrier
has argued that the universe itself seems to be very ill-designed for
life, because the vast majority of the space in the universe is utterly
hostile to it. This is arguably unexpected on the hypothesis that the
universe was designed by a god, especially a personal god. Carrier contends that such a god could have easily created a geocentric universe ex nihilo in the recent past,
in which most of the volume of the universe is inhabitable by humans
and other lifeforms— precisely the kind of universe that most humans
believed in until the rise of modern science. While a personal god might have created the kind of universe we observe, Carrier contends that this is not the kind of universe we would most likely
expect to see if such a god existed. He finally argues that, unlike
theism, our observations about the nature of the universe are strongly
expected on the hypothesis of atheism, since the universe would have to
be vast, very old, and almost completely devoid of life if life were to
have arisen by sheer chance.
Logical arguments
The following arguments deduce, mostly through self-contradiction, the non-existence of a God as "the Creator".
- Stephen Hawking and co-author Leonard Mlodinow state in their book The Grand Design that it is reasonable to ask who or what created the universe, but if the answer is God, then the question has merely been deflected to that of who created God. Both authors claim that it is possible to answer these questions purely within the realm of science, and without invoking any divine beings. Christian mathematicians and scientists, most notably Leonhard Euler, Bernard d'Espagnat and John Lennox, disagree with that kind of skeptical argument.
- No scientific evidence of God's existence has been found. Therefore, the scientific consensus is that whether God exists is unknown.
- A counter-argument against God as the Creator takes the assumption of the Cosmological argument ("the chicken or the egg"), that things cannot exist without creators, and applies it to God, setting up an infinite regress.
- Dawkins' Ultimate Boeing 747 gambit analogizes the above. Some theists argue that evolution is akin to a hurricane assembling a Boeing 747 — that the universe (or life) is too complex not to have been designed by someone, who theists call God. Dawkin's counter-argument is that such a God would himself be complex — the "Ultimate" Boeing 747 — and therefore require a designer.
- Theological noncognitivism is the argument that religious language – specifically, words such as "God" – are not cognitively meaningful and that irreducible definitions of God are circular.
- The analogy of Russell's teapot argues that the burden of proof for the existence of God lies with the theist rather than the atheist; it can be considered an extension of Occam's Razor.
Arguments from incompatible divine properties
Some arguments focus on the existence of specific conceptions of God as being omniscient, omnipotent, and morally perfect.
- The omnipotence paradox suggests that the concept of an omnipotent entity is logically contradictory by considering questions such as "Can God create a rock so big that He cannot move it?" or "If God is all powerful, could God create a being more powerful than Himself?"
- Similarly, the omniscience paradox argues that God cannot be omniscient because he would not know how to create something unknown to himself.
- Another argument points to the contradiction of omniscience and omnipotence arguing that God is bound to follow whatever God foreknows himself doing.
- Argument from free will contends that omniscience and the free will of humanity are incompatible and that any conception of God that incorporates both properties is therefore inherently contradictory: if God is omniscient, then God already knows humanity's future, contradicting the claim of free will.
- The anthropic argument states that if God is omniscient, omnipotent, and morally perfect, he would have created other morally perfect beings instead of imperfect ones, such as humans.
- The problem of hell is the idea that eternal damnation contradicts God's omnibenevolence and omnipresence.
- The Transcendental Argument for the Non-existence of God contests the existence of an intelligent Creator God by demonstrating that such a being would make logic and morality contingent, which is incompatible with the presuppositionalist assertion that they are necessary, and contradicts the efficacy of science.
- The "no reason" argument tries to show that an omnipotent and omniscient being would not have any reason to act in any way, specifically by creating the universe, because it would have no needs, wants, or desires since these very concepts are subjectively human. Since the universe exists, there is a contradiction, and therefore, an omnipotent god cannot exist. This argument is expounded upon by Scott Adams in the book God's Debris, which puts forward a form of Pandeism as its fundamental theological model. A similar argument is put forward in Ludwig von Mises's "Human Action". He referred to it as the "praxeological argument" and claimed that a perfect being would have long ago satisfied all its wants and desires and would no longer be able to take action in the present without proving that it had been unable to achieve its wants faster—showing it imperfect.
- The atheist-existential argument for the non-existence of a perfect sentient being states that if existence precedes essence, it follows from the meaning of the term sentient that a sentient being cannot be complete or perfect. It is touched upon by Jean-Paul Sartre in Being and Nothingness. Sartre's phrasing is that God would be a pour-soi [a being-for-itself; a consciousness] who is also an en-soi [a being-in-itself; a thing]: which is a contradiction in terms. The argument is echoed thus in Salman Rushdie's novel Grimus: "That which is complete is also dead."
Subjective arguments
Similar to the subjective
arguments for the existence of God, subjective arguments against the
supernatural mainly rely on the testimony or experience of witnesses, or
the propositions of a revealed religion in general.
- The witness argument gives credibility to personal witnesses, contemporary and from the past, who disbelieve or strongly doubt the existence of God.
- The conflicted religions argument notes that many religions give differing accounts as to what God is and what God wants; since all the contradictory accounts cannot be correct, many if not all religions must be incorrect.
- The disappointment argument claims that if, when asked for, there is no visible help from God, there is no reason to believe that there is a God.
Hindu arguments
Atheistic Hindu doctrines cite various arguments for rejecting a creator God or Ishvara. The Sāṁkhyapravacana Sūtra of the Samkhya
school states that there is no philosophical place for a creator God in
this system. It is also argued in this text that the existence of
Ishvara (God) cannot be proved and hence cannot be admitted to exist.
Classical Samkhya argues against the existence of God on metaphysical
grounds. For instance, it argues that an unchanging God cannot be the
source of an ever-changing world. It says God is a necessary
metaphysical assumption demanded by circumstances. The Sutras of Samkhya endeavor to prove that the idea of God is inconceivable and self-contradictory, and some commentaries speak plainly on this subject. The Sankhya- tattva-kaumudi,
commenting on Karika 57, argues that a perfect God can have no need to
create a world, and if God's motive is kindness, Samkhya questions
whether it is reasonable to call into existence beings who while
non-existent had no suffering. Samkhya postulates that a benevolent
deity ought to create only happy creatures, not an imperfect world like
the real world.
Charvaka, originally known as Lokāyata, a heterodox Hindu philosophy states that there is "no God, no samsara (rebirth), no karma, no duty, no fruits of merit, no sin." Proponents of the school of Mimamsa, which is based on rituals and orthopraxy,
decided that the evidence allegedly proving the existence of God is
insufficient. They argue that there is no need to postulate a maker for
the world, just as there is no need for an author to compose the Vedas
or a god to validate the rituals. Mimamsa argues that the gods named in the Vedas have no existence apart from the mantras that speak their names. In that regard, the power of the mantras is what is seen as the power of gods.
Psychological aspects
Several authors have offered psychological or sociological explanations for belief in the existence of God.
Psychologists observe that the majority of humans often ask
existential questions such as "why we are here" and whether life has
purpose. Some psychologists have posited that religious beliefs may recruit cognitive mechanisms in order to satisfy these questions. William James emphasized the inner religious struggle between melancholy and happiness, and pointed to trance as a cognitive mechanism. Sigmund Freud
stressed fear and pain, the need for a powerful parental figure, the
obsessional nature of ritual, and the hypnotic state a community can
induce as contributing factors to the psychology of religion.
Pascal Boyer's Religion Explained (2002), based in part on his anthropological field work, treats belief in God as the result of the brain's tendency towards agency detection.
Boyer suggests that, because of evolutionary pressures, humans err on
the side of attributing agency where there isn't any. In Boyer's view,
belief in supernatural entities spreads and becomes culturally fixed
because of their memorability. The concept of "minimally
counterintuitive" beings that differ from the ordinary in a small number
of ways (such as being invisible, able to fly, or having access to
strategic and otherwise secret information) leave a lasting impression
that spreads through word-of-mouth.
Scott Atran's In Gods We Trust: The Evolutionary Landscape of Religion (2002) makes a similar argument and adds examination of the socially coordinating aspects of shared belief. In Minds and Gods: The Cognitive Foundations of Religion, Todd Tremlin
follows Boyer in arguing that universal human cognitive process
naturally produces the concept of the supernatural. Tremlin contends
that an agency detection device (ADD) and a theory of mind
module (ToMM) lead humans to suspect an agent behind every event.
Natural events for which there is no obvious agent may be attributed to
God (c.f. Act of God).