The doctrine of spontaneous generation was coherently synthesized by Aristotle, who compiled and expanded the work of earlier natural philosophers
and the various ancient explanations for the appearance of organisms,
and was taken as scientific fact for two millennia. Though challenged in
the 17th and 18th centuries by the experiments of Francesco Redi and Lazzaro Spallanzani, spontaneous generation was not disproved until the work of Louis Pasteur and John Tyndall in the mid-19th century.
Rejection of spontaneous generation is no longer controversial among
biologists. By the middle of the 19th century, experiments of Louis
Pasteur and others refuted the traditional theory of spontaneous
generation and supported biogenesis.
Description and terms
Spontaneous
generation refers both to the supposed processes by which different
types of life might repeatedly emerge from specific sources other than
seeds, eggs, or parents, and also to theoretical principles presented in
support of any such phenomena. Crucial to this doctrine are the ideas
that life comes from non-life and that no causal agent, such as a
parent, is needed. The hypothetical processes by which life routinely
emerges from nonliving matter on a time scale of minutes, weeks, or
years (e.g. in the supposed seasonal generation of mice and other
animals from the mud of the Nile) are sometimes referred to as abiogenesis. Such ideas have no operative principles in common with the modern hypothesis of abiogenesis,
which asserts that life emerged in the early ages of the planet, over a
time span of at least millions of years, and subsequently diversified,
and that there is no evidence of any subsequent repetition of the event.
The term equivocal generation, sometimes known as heterogenesis or xenogenesis,
describes the supposed process by which one form of life arises from a
different, unrelated form, such as tapeworms from the bodies of their
hosts.
In the years following Louis Pasteur's
1859 experiment, the term "spontaneous generation" fell increasingly
out of favor. Experimentalists used a variety of terms for the study of
the origin of life from nonliving materials. Heterogenesis was applied to the generation of living things from once-living organic matter (such as boiled broths), and Henry Charlton Bastian proposed the term archebiosis
for life originating from inorganic materials. Disliking the randomness
and unpredictability implied by the term "'spontaneous' generation," in
1870 Bastian coined the term biogenesis to refer to the formation of life from nonliving matter. Soon thereafter, however, English biologist Thomas Henry Huxley proposed the term abiogenesis to refer to this same process and adopted biogenesis for the process by which life arises from existing life; it is this latter set of definitions that became dominant.
Antiquity
Presocratic philosophers
Active in the 6th and 5th centuries BCE, early Greek philosophers, called physiologoi in antiquity (Greek: φυσιολόγοι; in English, physical or natural philosophers), attempted to give natural explanations of phenomena that had previously been ascribed to the agency of the gods. The physiologoi sought the material principle or arche
(Greek: ἀρχή) of things, emphasizing the rational unity of the external
world and rejecting theological or mythological explanations.
Anaximander, who believed that all things arose from the elemental nature of the universe, the apeiron
(ἄπειρον) or the "unbounded" or "infinite," was likely the first
western thinker to propose that life developed spontaneously from
nonliving matter. The primal chaos of the apeiron,
eternally in motion, served as a substratum in which elemental
opposites (e.g., wet and dry, hot and cold) generated and shaped the
many and varied things in the world. According to Hippolytus of Rome
in the third century CE, Anaximander claimed that fish or fish-like
creatures were first formed in the "wet" when acted on by the heat of
the sun and that these aquatic creatures gave rise to human beings. Censorinus, writing in the 3rd century, reports:
Anaximander of Miletus considered that from warmed up water and earth emerged either fish or entirely fishlike animals. Inside these animals, men took form and embryos were held prisoners until puberty; only then, after these animals burst open, could men and women come out, now able to feed themselves.
Anaximenes,
a pupil of Anaximander, thought that air was the element that imparted
life and endowed creatures with motion and thought. He proposed that
plants and animals, including human beings, arose from a primordial
terrestrial slime, a mixture of earth and water, combined with the sun's
heat. Anaxagoras,
too, believed that life emerged from a terrestrial slime. However, he
held that the seeds of plants existed in the air from the beginning, and
those of animals in the aether. Xenophanes
traced the origin of man back to the transitional period between the
fluid stage of the earth and the formation of land, under the influence
of the sun.
In what has occasionally been seen as a prefiguration of a concept of natural selection, Empedocles
accepted the spontaneous generation of life but held that different
forms, made up of differing combinations of parts, spontaneously arose
as though by trial and error: successful combinations formed the species
we now see, whereas unsuccessful forms failed to reproduce.
Aristotle
In his biological works, the natural philosopher Aristotle theorized
extensively the reproduction of various animals, whether by sexual, parthenogenetic, or spontaneous generation. In accordance with his fundamental theory of hylomorphism,
which held that every physical entity was a compound of matter and
form, Aristotle's basic theory of sexual reproduction contended that the
male's seed
imposed form, the set of characteristics passed down to offspring on
the "matter" (menstrual blood) supplied by the female. Thus female
matter is the material cause of generation—it supplies the matter that will constitute the offspring—while the male semen is the efficient cause, the factor that instigates and delineates the thing's existence. Yet, as proposed in the History of Animals, many creatures form not through sexual processes but by spontaneous generation:
Now there is one property that animals are found to have in common with plants. For some plants are generated from the seed of plants, whilst other plants are self-generated through the formation of some elemental principle similar to a seed; and of these latter plants some derive their nutriment from the ground, whilst others grow inside other plants ... So with animals, some spring from parent animals according to their kind, whilst others grow spontaneously and not from kindred stock; and of these instances of spontaneous generation some come from putrefying earth or vegetable matter, as is the case with a number of insects, while others are spontaneously generated in the inside of animals out of the secretions of their several organs.
— Aristotle, History of Animals, Book V, Part 1
According to this theory, living things may come forth from nonliving
things in a manner roughly analogous to the "enformation of the female
matter by the agency of the male seed" seen in sexual reproduction. Nonliving materials, like the seminal fluid present in sexual generation, contain pneuma (πνεῦμα, "breath"), or "vital heat".
According to Aristotle, pneuma had more "heat" than regular air did,
and this heat endowed the substance with certain vital properties:
The power of every soul seems to have shared in a different and more divine body than the so called [four] elements ... For every [animal], what makes the seed generative inheres in the seed and is called its "heat." But this is not fire or some such power, but instead the pneuma that is enclosed in the seed and in foamy matter, this being analogous to the element of the stars. This is why fire does not generate any animal ... but the heat of the sun and the heat of animals does, not only the heat that fills the seed, but also any other residue of [the animal's] nature that may exist similarly possesses this vital principle.
— Aristotle, Generation of Animals, 736b29ff.
Aristotle drew an analogy between the "foamy matter" (τὸ ἀφρῶδες)
found in nature and the "seed" of an animal, which he viewed as being a
kind of foam itself (composed, as it was, from a mixture of water and
pneuma). For Aristotle, the generative materials of male and female
animals (semen and menstrual blood) were essentially refinements, made
by male and female bodies according to their respective proportions of
heat, of ingested food, which was, in turn, a byproduct of the elements
earth and water. Thus any creature, whether generated sexually from
parents or spontaneously through the interaction of vital heat and
elemental matter, was dependent on the proportions of pneuma and the
various elements which Aristotle believed comprised all things.
While Aristotle recognized that many living things emerged from
putrefying matter, he pointed out that the putrefaction was not the
source of life, but the byproduct of the action of the "sweet" element
of water.
Animals and plants come into being in earth and in liquid because there is water in earth, and air in water, and in all air is vital heat so that in a sense all things are full of soul. Therefore living things form quickly whenever this air and vital heat are enclosed in anything. When they are so enclosed, the corporeal liquids being heated, there arises as it were a frothy bubble.
— Aristotle, Generation of Animals, Book III, Part 11
With varying degrees of observational confidence, Aristotle theorized
the spontaneous generation of a range of creatures from different sorts
of inanimate matter. The testaceans (a genus which for Aristotle included bivalves
and snails), for instance, were characterized by spontaneous generation
from mud, but differed based upon the precise material they grew in—for
example, clams and scallops in sand, oysters in slime, and the barnacle and the limpet in the hollows of rocks.
Latin and early Christian sources
Vitruvius, a Roman architect and writer of the 1st century BCE, advised that libraries be placed facing eastwards to benefit from morning light, but not towards the south or the west as those winds generate bookworms.
Aristotle claimed that eels were lacking in sex and lacking milt, spawn and the passages for either. Rather, he asserted eels emerged from earthworms. Later authors dissented. Pliny the Elder
did not argue against the anatomic limits of eels, but stated that eels
reproduce by budding, scraping themselves against rocks, liberating
particles that become eels. Athenaeus
described eels as entwining and discharging a fluid which would settle
on mud and generate life. On the other hand, Athenaeus also dissented
towards spontaneous generation, claiming that a variety of anchovy did not generate from roe, as Aristotle stated, but rather, from sea foam.
As the dominant view of philosophers and thinkers continued to be
in favour of spontaneous generation, some Christian theologians
accepted the view. Augustine of Hippo discussed spontaneous generation in The City of God and The Literal Meaning of Genesis, citing Biblical passages such as "Let the waters bring forth abundantly the moving creature that hath life" (Genesis 1:20) as decrees that would enable ongoing creation.
Middle Ages
From the fall of the Roman Empire in 5th century to the East-West Schism
in 1054, the influence of Greek science declined, although spontaneous
generation generally went unchallenged. New descriptions were made. Of
the numerous beliefs, some had doctrinal implications outside of the Book of Genesis. For example, the idea that a variety of bird known as the barnacle goose emerged from a crustacean known as the goose barnacle, had implications on the practice of fasting during Lent. In 1188, Gerald of Wales, after having traveled in Ireland, argued that the "unnatural" generation of barnacle geese was evidence for the virgin birth.
Where the practice of fasting during Lent allowed fish, but prohibited
fowl, the idea that the goose was in fact a fish suggested that its
consumption be permitted during Lent. The practice was eventually
prohibited by decree of Pope Innocent III in 1215.
Aristotle, in Arabic translation, was reintroduced to Western
Europe. During the 13th century, Aristotle reached his greatest
acceptance. With the availability of Latin translations Saint Albertus Magnus and his student, Saint Thomas Aquinas, raised Aristotelianism to its greatest prominence. Albert wrote a paraphrase of Aristotle, De causis et processu universitatis, in which he removed some and incorporated other commentaries by Arabic scholars.
The influential writings of Aquinas, on both the physical and
metaphysical, are predominantly Aristotelian, but show numerous other
influences.
Spontaneous generation is discussed as a fact in literature well into the Renaissance. Where, in passing, Shakespeare discusses snakes and crocodiles forming from the mud of the Nile (Ant 2.7 F1), Izaak Walton
again raises the question of the origin of eels "as rats and mice, and
many other living creatures, are bred in Egypt, by the sun's heat when
it shines upon the overflowing of the river...". While the ancient
question of the origin of eels remained unanswered and the additional
idea that eels reproduced from corruption of age was mentioned, the
spontaneous generation of rats and mice engendered no debate.
The Dutch biologist and microscopist Jan Swammerdam
(1637 - 1680) rejected the concept that one animal could arise from
another or from putrification by chance because it was impious and like
others found the concept of spontaneous generation irreligious, and he
associated it with atheism and Godless opinion.
Modern tests
Jan Baptist van Helmont
(1580–1644) used experimental techniques, such as growing a willow for
five years and showing it increased mass while the soil showed a trivial
decrease in comparison. As the process of photosynthesis was not understood, he attributed the increase of mass to the absorption of water.
His notes also describe a recipe for mice (a piece of soiled cloth plus
wheat for 21 days) and scorpions (basil, placed between two bricks and
left in sunlight). His notes suggest he may even have done these
things.
Where Aristotle held that the embryo was formed by a coagulation in the uterus, William Harvey (1578 – 1657) by way of dissection of deer, showed that there was no visible embryo during the first month.
Although his work predated the microscope, this led him to suggest
that life came from invisible eggs. In the frontispiece of his book Exercitationes de Generatione Animalium (Essays on the Generation of Animals), he made an expression of biogenesis: "omnia ex ovo" (everything from eggs).
The ancient beliefs were subjected to testing. In 1668, Francesco Redi challenged the idea that maggots arose spontaneously from rotting meat. In the first major experiment to challenge spontaneous generation, he placed meat in a variety of sealed, open, and partially covered containers.
Realizing that the sealed containers were deprived of air, he used
"fine Naples veil", and observed no worm on the meat, but they appeared
on the cloth.
Redi used his experiments to support the preexistence theory put forth
by the Church at that time, which maintained that living things
originated from parents. In scientific circles Redi's work very soon had great influence, as evidenced in a letter from John Ray in 1671 to members of the Royal Society of London:
Whether there be any spontaneous or anomalous generation of animals, as has been the constant opinion of naturalists heretofore, I think there is good reason to question. It seems to me at present most probable, that there is no such thing; but that even all insects are the natural issue of parents of the same species with themselves. F. Redi has gone a good way in proving this, having cleared the point concerning generation ex materia putrida. But still there remain two great difficulties. The first is, to give an account of the production of insects bred in the by-fruits and excrescencies of vegetables, which the said Redi doubts not to ascribe to the vegetative soul of the plant that yields those excrescencies. But for this I refer you to Mr. Lister. The second, to render an account of insects bred in the bodies of other animals. I hope shortly to be able to give you an account of the generation of some of those insects which have been thought to be spontaneous, and which seem as unlikely as any to be after the ordinary and usual way.
Pier Antonio Micheli,
around 1729, observed that when fungal spores were placed on slices of
melon the same type of fungi were produced that the spores came from,
and from this observation he noted that fungi did not arise from
spontaneous generation.
In 1745, John Needham
performed a series of experiments on boiled broths. Believing that
boiling would kill all living things, he showed that when sealed right
after boiling, the broths would cloud, allowing the belief in
spontaneous generation to persist. His studies were rigorously
scrutinized by his peers and many of them agreed.
Lazzaro Spallanzani
modified the Needham experiment in 1768, attempting to exclude the
possibility of introducing a contaminating factor between boiling and
sealing. His technique involved boiling the broth in a sealed container
with the air partially evacuated to prevent explosions. Although he did
not see growth, the exclusion of air left the question of whether air
was an essential factor in spontaneous generation.
However, by that time there was already widespread scepticism among
major scientists, to the principle of spontaneous generation.
Observation was increasingly demonstrating that whenever there was
sufficiently careful investigation of mechanisms of biological
reproduction, it was plain that processes involved basing of new
structures on existing complex structures, rather from chaotic muds or
dead materials. Joseph Priestley, after he had fled to America and not long before his death, wrote a letter that was read to the American Philosophical Society in 1803. It said in part:
There is nothing in modern philosophy that appears to me so extraordinary, as the revival of what has long been considered as the exploded doctrine of equivocal, or, as Dr. Darwin calls it, spontaneous generation; by which is meant the production of organized bodies from substances that have no organization, as plants and animals from no pre-existing germs of the same kinds, plants without seeds, and animals without sexual intercourse.
The germ of an organized body, the seed of a plant, or the embrio of an animal, in its first discoverable state, is now found to be the future plant or animal in miniature, containing every thing essential to it when full grown, only requiring to have the several organs enlarged, and the interstices filled with extraneous nutritious matter. When the external form undergoes the greatest change, as from an aquatic insect to a flying gnat, a caterpillar to a crysalis, a crysalis to a butterfly, or a tadpole to a frog, there is nothing new in the organization; all the parts of the gnat, the butterfly, and the frog, having really existed, though not appearing to the common observer in the forms in which they are first seen. In like manner, every thing essential to the oak is found in the acorn.
In 1837, Charles Cagniard de la Tour, a physicist, and Theodor Schwann, one of the founders of cell theory, published their independent discovery of yeast in alcoholic fermentation. They used the microscope to examine foam left over from the process of brewing beer. Where Leeuwenhoek described "small spheroid globules", they observed yeast cells undergo cell division.
Fermentation would not occur when sterile air or pure oxygen was
introduced if yeast were not present. This suggested that airborne microorganisms, not spontaneous generation, was responsible.
However, although the idea of spontaneous generation had been in
decline for nearly a century, its supporters did not abandon it all at
once. As James Rennie wrote:
...inability to trace the origin of minute plants and insects led to the doctrine of what is called spontaneous or equivocal generation, of which the fancies above-mentioned are some 'of the prominent branches. The experiments of Redi on the hatching of insects from eggs, which were published at Florence in 1668, first brought discredit upon this doctrine, though it had always a few eminent disciples. At present it is maintained by a considerable number -of distinguished naturalists, such as Blumenbach, Cuvier, Bory de St. Vincent, R. Brown, &c. "The notion or spontaneous generation," says Bory, " is at first revolting to a rational mind, but it is, notwithstanding, demonstrable by the microscope. The fact is averred : Willer has seen it, I have seen it, and twenty other observers have seen it: the pandorinia exhibit it every instant. "These pandorinia he elsewhere describes as probably nothing more than " animated scions of Zoocarpae". It would be unprofitable to go into any lengthened discussion upon this mysterious subject; and we have great doubts whether the ocular demonstration by the microscope would succeed except in the hands of a disciple of the school. Even with naturalists, whose business it is to deal with facts, the reason is often wonderfully influenced by the imagination...
Pasteur and Tyndall
Louis Pasteur's
1859 experiment is widely seen as having settled the question of
spontaneous generation. He boiled a meat broth in a flask that had a
long neck that curved downward, like that of a goose or swan. The idea
was that the bend in the neck prevented falling particles from reaching
the broth, while still allowing the free flow of air. The flask
remained free of growth for an extended period. When the flask was
turned so that particles could fall down the bends, the broth quickly
became clouded.
However, minority objections were persistent and not always
unreasonable, given that the experimental difficulties were far more
challenging than the popular accounts suggest. The investigations of John Tyndall,
a correspondent of Pasteur and a great admirer of Pasteur's work, were
decisive in disproving spontaneous generation and dealing with lingering
issues. Still, even Tyndall encountered difficulties in dealing with
the effects of microbial spores,
which were not well understood in his day. Like Pasteur, he boiled his
cultures to sterilize them, and some types of bacterial spores can
survive boiling. The autoclave,
which eventually came into universal application in medical practice
and microbiology to sterilise equipment, was not an instrument that had
come into use at the time of Tyndall's experiments, let alone those of
Pasteur.
In 1862, the French Academy of Sciences
paid a special attention to the issue and established a prize "to him
who by well-conducted experiments throws new light on the question of
the so-called spontaneous generation" and appointed a commission to
judge the winner.