Dyson believed global warming is caused merely (also signed the World Climate Declaration that there is no Climate Emergency; https://clintel.org/world-climate-declaration/) by increased carbon dioxide
but that some of the effects of this are favourable and not taken into
account by climate scientists, such as increased agricultural yield. He
was skeptical about the simulation models used to predict climate change,
arguing that political efforts to reduce causes of climate change
distract from other global problems that should take priority.
Biography
Early life
Born on 15 December 1923, at Crowthorne in Berkshire, England, Dyson was the son of Mildred Lucy (Atkey) and George Dyson.
His father, a prominent composer, was later knighted. His mother had a
law degree, and after Dyson was born she worked as a social worker.
Dyson had one sibling, his older sister, Alice, who remembered him as a
boy surrounded by encyclopedias and always calculating on sheets of
paper. At the age of four he tried to calculate the number of atoms in the Sun. As a child, he showed an interest in large numbers and in the solar system, and was strongly influenced by the book Men of Mathematics by Eric Temple Bell. Politically, Dyson says he was "brought up as a socialist".
From 1936 to 1941 Dyson was a scholar at Winchester College, where his father was Director of Music. At age 17 he studied mathematics with G. H. Hardy at Trinity College, Cambridge (where he won a scholarship at age 15), and at age 19 was assigned to war work in the Operational Research Section (ORS) of the Royal Air Force's Bomber Command, where he developed analytical methods for calculating the ideal density for bomber formations to help the Royal Air Force bomb German targets during World War II. After the war, Dyson was readmitted to Trinity College, where he obtained a BA degree in mathematics. From 1946 to 1949 he was a fellow of his college, occupying rooms just below those of the philosopher Ludwig Wittgenstein, who resigned his professorship in 1947.
In 1947 Dyson published two papers in number theory.
Friends and colleagues described him as shy and self-effacing, with a
contrarian streak that his friends find refreshing but his intellectual
opponents find exasperating. "I have the sense that when consensus is
forming like ice hardening on a lake, Dyson will do his best to chip at
the ice", Steven Weinberg said of him. His friend the neurologist and author Oliver Sacks
said: "A favourite word of Freeman's about doing science and being
creative is the word 'subversive'. He feels it's rather important not
only to be not orthodox, but to be subversive, and he's done that all
his life."
Career in the United States
On G. I. Taylor's advice and recommendation, Dyson moved to the United States in 1947 as a Commonwealth Fellow to earn a physics doctorate with Hans Bethe at Cornell University (1947–1948). There he made the acquaintance of Richard Feynman.
The budding English physicist recognized the brilliance of the
flamboyant American and worked with him. He then moved to the Institute
for Advanced Study (1948–1949), before returning to England (1949–51),
where he was a research fellow at the University of Birmingham.
In 1949, Dyson demonstrated the equivalence of two formulations of quantum electrodynamics (QED): Richard Feynman's diagrams and the operator method developed by Julian Schwinger and Shin'ichirō Tomonaga. He was the first person after their creator to appreciate the power of Feynman diagrams
and his paper written in 1948 and published in 1949 was the first to
make use of them. He said in that paper that Feynman diagrams were not
just a computational tool but a physical theory and developed rules for
the diagrams that completely solved the renormalization
problem. Dyson's paper and also his lectures presented Feynman's
theories of QED in a form that other physicists could understand,
facilitating the physics community's acceptance of Feynman's work. J. Robert Oppenheimer,
in particular, was persuaded by Dyson that Feynman's new theory was as
valid as Schwinger's and Tomonaga's. Also in 1949, in related work,
Dyson invented the Dyson series. It was this paper that inspired John Ward to derive his celebrated Ward–Takahashi identity.
Dyson joined the faculty at Cornell as a physics professor in
1951, though he still had no doctorate. In December 1952 Oppenheimer,
the director of the Institute for Advanced Study in Princeton, New Jersey, offered Dyson a lifetime appointment at the Institute, "for proving me wrong", in Oppenheimer's words. Dyson remained at the Institute until the end of his career. In 1957 he became a US citizen.
In 1958 Dyson was a member of the design team under Edward Teller for TRIGA, a small, inherently safe nuclear reactor used throughout the world in hospitals and universities for the production of medical isotopes.
A seminal paper by Dyson came in 1966, when, together with Andrew Lenard and independently of Elliott H. Lieb and Walter Thirring, he proved rigorously that the Pauli exclusion principle plays the main role in the stability of bulk matter.
Hence it is not the electromagnetic repulsion between outer-shell
orbital electrons that prevents two stacked wood blocks from coalescing
into a single piece, but the exclusion principle applied to electrons
and protons that generates the classical macroscopic normal force. In condensed matter physics, Dyson also analysed the phase transition of the Ising model in one dimension and spin waves.
Around 1979 Dyson worked with the Institute for Energy Analysis on climate studies. This group, under Alvin Weinberg's
direction, pioneered multidisciplinary climate studies, including a
strong biology group. Also during the 1970s, Dyson worked on climate
studies conducted by the JASON defense advisory group.
Dyson retired from the Institute for Advanced Study in 1994. In 1998 he joined the board of the Solar Electric Light Fund. As of 2003 he was president of the Space Studies Institute, the space research organization founded by Gerard K. O'Neill; as of 2013 he was on its board of trustees. Dyson was a longtime member of the JASON group.
Dyson won numerous scientific awards, but never a Nobel Prize. Nobel physics laureate Steven Weinberg said that the Nobel committee
"fleeced" Dyson, but Dyson remarked in 2009, "I think it's almost true
without exception if you want to win a Nobel Prize, you should have a
long attention span, get hold of some deep and important problem and
stay with it for ten years. That wasn't my style." Dyson was a regular contributor to The New York Review of Books, and published a memoir, Maker of Patterns: An Autobiography Through Letters in 2018.
With his first wife, the Swiss mathematician Verena Huber-Dyson, Dyson had two children, Esther and George. In 1958, he married Imme Jung (born 1936), a masters runner, and they had four more children, Dorothy, Mia, Rebecca, and Emily Dyson.
Dyson's eldest daughter, Esther, is a digital technology
consultant and investor; she has been called "the most influential woman
in all the computer world". His son George is a historian of science, one of whose books is Project Orion: The Atomic Spaceship 1957–1965.
Death
Dyson died at a hospital near Princeton, New Jersey, on 28 February 2020 at age 96 from complications following a fall.
Concepts
Biotechnology and genetic engineering
Dyson admitted his record as a prophet was mixed, but thought it is
better to be wrong than vague, and that in meeting the world's material
needs, technology must be beautiful and cheap.
My book The Sun, the Genome, and the Internet
(1999) describes a vision of green technology enriching villages all
over the world and halting the migration from villages to megacities.
The three components of the vision are all essential: the sun to provide
energy where it is needed, the genome to provide plants that can
convert sunlight into chemical fuels cheaply and efficiently, the
Internet to end the intellectual and economic isolation of rural
populations. With all three components in place, every village in Africa
could enjoy its fair share of the blessings of civilization.
Dyson coined the term "green technologies", based on biology instead of physics or chemistry, to describe new species of microorganisms and plants designed to meet human needs. He argued that such technologies would be based on solar power rather than the fossil fuels whose use he saw as part of what he calls "gray technologies" of industry. He believed that genetically engineered crops, which he described as green, can help end rural poverty, with a movement based in ethics to end the inequitable distribution of wealth on the planet.
The Origin of Life
Dyson favored the dual origin theory: that life first formed as cells, then enzymes, and finally, much later, genes. This was first propounded by the Russian Alexander Oparin. J. B. S. Haldane developed the same theory independently.
In Dyson's version of the theory life evolved in two stages, widely
separated in time. Because of the biochemistry he regards it as too
unlikely that genes could have developed fully blown in one process.
Current cells contain adenosine triphosphate or ATP and adenosine 5'-monophosphate
or AMP, which greatly resemble each other but have completely different
functions. ATP transports energy around the cell, and AMP is part of
RNA and the genetic apparatus. Dyson proposed that in a primitive early
cell containing ATP and AMP, RNA and replication came into existence
only because of the similarity between AMP and RNA. He suggested that
AMP was produced when ATP molecules lost two of their phosphate
radicals, and then one cell somewhere performed Eigen's experiment and produced RNA.
There is no direct evidence for the dual origin theory, because
once genes developed, they took over, obliterating all traces of the
earlier forms of life. In the first origin, the cells were probably just
drops of water held together by surface tension, teeming with enzymes
and chemical reactions, and having a primitive kind of growth or
replication. When the liquid drop became too big, it split into two
drops. Many complex molecules formed in these "little city economies"
and the probability that genes would eventually develop in them was much
greater than in the prebiotic environment.
Artist's concept of Dyson rings, forming a stable Dyson swarm, or "Dyson sphere"
Dyson sphere
In 1960 Dyson wrote a short paper for the journal Science titled "Search for Artificial Stellar Sources of Infrared Radiation". In it he speculated that a technologically advanced extraterrestrialcivilization
might surround its native star with artificial structures to maximize
the capture of the star's energy. Eventually the civilization would
enclose the star, intercepting electromagnetic radiation with wavelengths from visible light downward and radiating waste heat outward as infrared radiation. One method of searching for extraterrestrial civilizations would be to look for large objects radiating in the infrared range of the electromagnetic spectrum.
One should
expect that, within a few thousand years of its entering the stage of
industrial development, any intelligent species should be found
occupying an artificial biosphere which surrounds its parent star.
Dyson conceived that such structures would be clouds of asteroid-sized space habitats, though science fiction writers have preferred a solid structure: either way, such an artifact is often called a Dyson sphere,
although Dyson used the term "shell". Dyson said that he used the term
"artificial biosphere" in the article to mean a habitat, not a shape. The general concept of such an energy-transferring shell had been advanced decades earlier by author Olaf Stapledon in his 1937 novel Star Maker, a source Dyson credited publicly.
Dyson tree
Dyson also proposed the creation of a Dyson tree, a genetically engineered plant capable of growing on a comet.
He suggested that comets could be engineered to contain hollow spaces
filled with a breathable atmosphere, thus providing self-sustaining
habitats for humanity in the outer Solar System.
Plants
could grow greenhouses ... just as turtles grow shells and polar bears
grow fur and polyps build coral reefs in tropical seas. These plants
could keep warm by the light from a distant Sun and conserve the oxygen
that they produce by photosynthesis. The greenhouse would consist of a
thick skin providing thermal insulation, with small transparent windows
to admit sunlight. Outside the skin would be an array of simple lenses,
focusing sunlight through the windows into the interior ... Groups of
greenhouses could grow together to form extended habitats for other
species of plants and animals.
Space colonies
I've done some historical research on the costs of the Mayflower's
voyage, and on the Mormons' emigration to Utah, and I think it's
possible to go into space on a much smaller scale. A cost on the order
of $40,000 per person [1978 dollars, $143,254 in 2013 dollars] would be
the target to shoot for; in terms of real wages, that would make it
comparable to the colonization of America. Unless it's brought down to
that level it's not really interesting to me, because otherwise it would
be a luxury that only governments could afford.
Dyson was interested in space travel since he was a child, reading such science fiction classics as Olaf Stapledon's Star Maker. As a young man, he worked for General Atomics on the nuclear-powered Orion
spacecraft. He hoped Project Orion would put men on Mars by 1965,
Saturn by 1970. For a quarter-century Dyson was unhappy about how the
government conducts space travel:
The problem
is, of course, that they can't afford to fail. The rules of the game
are that you don't take a chance, because if you fail, then probably
your whole program gets wiped out.
Dyson still hoped for cheap space travel, but was resigned to waiting
for private entrepreneurs to develop something new and inexpensive.
No law of
physics or biology forbids cheap travel and settlement all over the
solar system and beyond. But it is impossible to predict how long this
will take. Predictions of the dates of future achievements are
notoriously fallible. My guess is that the era of cheap unmanned
missions will be the next fifty years, and the era of cheap manned
missions will start sometime late in the twenty-first century.
Any affordable program of manned exploration must be centered in
biology, and its time frame tied to the time frame of biotechnology; a
hundred years, roughly the time it will take us to learn to grow
warm-blooded plants, is probably reasonable.
Space exploration
A direct search for life in Europa's ocean would today be prohibitively
expensive. Impacts on Europa give us an easier way to look for evidence
of life there. Every time a major impact occurs on Europa, a vast
quantity of water is splashed from the ocean into the space around
Jupiter. Some of the water evaporates, and some condenses into snow.
Creatures living in the water far enough from the impact have a chance
of being splashed intact into space and quickly freeze-dried. Therefore,
an easy way to look for evidence of life in Europa's ocean is to look
for freeze-dried fish in the ring of space debris orbiting Jupiter.
Freeze-dried fish orbiting Jupiter is a fanciful notion, but nature in
the biological realm has a tendency to be fanciful. Nature is usually
more imaginative than we are. ... To have the best chance of success, we
should keep our eyes open for all possibilities.
Dyson's eternal intelligence
Dyson proposed that an immortal group of intelligent beings could escape the prospect of heat death by extending time to infinity while expending only a finite amount of energy. This is also known as the Dyson scenario.
Dyson's transform
His concept "Dyson's transform" led to one of the most important lemmas of Olivier Ramaré's theorem: that every even integer can be written as a sum of no more than six primes.
Dyson and Hugh Montgomery discovered an intriguing connection between quantum physics and Montgomery's pair correlation conjecture about the zeros of the Zeta function. The primes 2, 3, 5, 7, 11, 13, 17, 19, ... are described by the Riemann Zeta function, and Dyson had previously developed a description of quantum physics based on m by m arrays of totally random numbers. Montgomery and Dyson discovered that the eigenvalues
of these matrices are spaced apart in exactly the same manner as
Montgomery conjectured for the nontrivial zeros of the Zeta function. Andrew Odlyzko has verified the conjecture on a computer, using his Odlyzko–Schönhage algorithm to calculate many zeros.
There are in nature one, two, and three dimensional quasicrystals. Mathematicians define a quasicrystal as a set of discrete points whose Fourier transform
is also a set of discrete points. Odlyzko has done extensive
computations of the Fourier transform of the nontrivial zeros of the
Zeta function, and they seem to form a one-dimensional quasicrystal.
This would in fact follow from the Riemann hypothesis.
In number theory, the crank of a partition is a certain integer associated with the partition in number theory. Dyson first introduced the term without a definition in a 1944 paper in a journal published by the Mathematics Society of Cambridge University. He then gave a list of properties this yet-to-be-defined quantity should have. In 1988, George E. Andrews and Frank Garvan discovered a definition for the crank satisfying the properties Dyson had hypothesized.
Astrochicken
Astrochicken is the name given to a thought experiment Dyson expounded in his book Disturbing the Universe (1979). He contemplated how humanity could build a small, self-replicating automaton that could explore space more efficiently than a manned craft could. He attributed the general idea to John von Neumann, based on a lecture von Neumann gave in 1948 titled The General and Logical Theory of Automata. Dyson expanded on von Neumann's automata theories and added a biological component.
Projects Dyson collaborated on
Lumpers and splitters
John von Neumann
Dyson suggested that philosophers can be broadly, if simplistically,
divided into lumpers and splitters. These roughly correspond to Platonists, who regard the world as made up of ideas, and materialists, who imagine it divided into atoms.
Views
Climate change
Dyson agreed that anthropogenicglobal warming exists and that one of its main causes is the increase of carbon dioxide in the atmosphere resulting from the burning of fossil fuels. He said that in many ways increased atmospheric carbon dioxide is beneficial, and that it is increasing biological growth, agricultural yields and forests. He believed that existing simulation models of climate change
fail to account for some important factors, and that the results thus
contain too great a margin of error to reliably predict future trends.
Dyson's views on global warming were criticized. Climate scientist James Hansen
said that Dyson "doesn't know what he's talking about ... If he's going
to wander into something with major consequences for humanity and other
life on the planet, then he should first do his homework – which he
obviously has not done on global warming."
Dyson replied that "[m]y objections to the global warming propaganda
are not so much over the technical facts, about which I do not know
much, but it's rather against the way those people behave and the kind
of intolerance to criticism that a lot of them have."
In 2008 Dyson endorsed the now common usage of "global warming" as synonymous with global anthropogenic climate change,
but argued that political efforts to reduce the causes of climate
change distract from other global problems that should take priority.
Since originally taking interest in climate studies in the 1970s, Dyson suggested that carbon dioxide
levels in the atmosphere could be controlled by planting fast-growing
trees. He calculated that it would take a trillion trees to remove all
carbon from the atmosphere.
In a 2014 interview he said, "What I'm convinced of is that we don't
understand climate ... It will take a lot of very hard work before that
question is settled."
At the British Bomber Command, Dyson and colleagues proposed removing two gun turrets from the RAF Lancaster bombers, to cut the catastrophic losses due to German fighters in the Battle of Berlin. A Lancaster without turrets could fly 50 mph (80 km/h) faster and be much more maneuverable.
All our
advice to the commander in chief [went] through the chief of our
section, who was a career civil servant. His guiding principle was to
tell the commander in chief things that the commander in chief liked to
hear ... To push the idea of ripping out gun turrets, against the
official mythology of the gallant gunner defending his crew mates ...
was not the kind of suggestion the commander in chief liked to hear.
I agreed emphatically with Henry Stimson.
Once we had got ourselves into the business of bombing cities, we might
as well do the job competently and get it over with. I felt better that
morning than I had felt for years ... Those fellows who had built the
atomic bombs obviously knew their stuff ... Later, much later, I would
remember [the downside].
I am
convinced that to avoid nuclear war it is not sufficient to be afraid of
it. It is necessary to be afraid, but it is equally necessary to
understand. And the first step in understanding is to recognize that the
problem of nuclear war is basically not technical but human and
historical. If we are to avoid destruction we must first of all
understand the human and historical context out of which destruction
arises.
In 1967, in his capacity as a military adviser, Dyson wrote an
influential paper on the issue of possible US use of tactical nuclear
weapons in the Vietnam War.
When a general said in a meeting, "I think it might be a good idea to
throw in a nuke now and then, just to keep the other side guessing ..."
Dyson became alarmed and obtained permission to write a report on the
pros and cons of using such weapons from a purely military point of
view. (This report, Tactical Nuclear Weapons in Southeast Asia, published by the Institute for Defense Analyses, was obtained, with some redactions, by the Nautilus Institute for Security and Sustainability under the Freedom of Information act in 2002.)
It was sufficiently objective that both sides in the debate based their
arguments on it. Dyson says that the report showed that, even from a
narrow military point of view, the US was better off not using nuclear
weapons.
Dyson was raised in what he described as a "watered-down Church of England Christianity". He was a nondenominational Christian and attended various churches, from Presbyterian to Roman Catholic. Regarding doctrinal or Christological issues, he said, "I am neither a saint nor a theologian. To me, good works are more important than theology."
Science and
religion are two windows that people look through, trying to understand
the big universe outside, trying to understand why we are here. The two
windows give different views, but they look out at the same universe.
Both views are one-sided, neither is complete. Both leave out essential
features of the real world. And both are worthy of respect.
Trouble arises when either science or religion claims universal
jurisdiction, when either religious or scientific dogma claims to be
infallible. Religious creationists and scientific materialists are
equally dogmatic and insensitive. By their arrogance they bring both
science and religion into disrepute. The media exaggerate their numbers
and importance. The media rarely mention the fact that the great
majority of religious people belong to moderate denominations that treat
science with respect, or the fact that the great majority of scientists
treat religion with respect so long as religion does not claim
jurisdiction over scientific questions.
Dyson partially disagreed with the famous remark by his fellow physicist Steven Weinberg
that "With or without religion, good people can behave well and bad
people can do evil; but for good people to do evil – that takes
religion."
Weinberg's
statement is true as far as it goes, but it is not the whole truth. To
make it the whole truth, we must add an additional clause: "And for bad
people to do good things – that [also] takes religion." The main point
of Christianity is that it is a religion for sinners. Jesus made that
very clear. When the Pharisees asked his disciples, "Why eateth your
Master with publicans and sinners?" he said, "I come to call not the
righteous but sinners to repentance." Only a small fraction of sinners
repent and do good things but only a small fraction of good people are
led by their religion to do bad things.
While Dyson called himself a Christian, he identified himself as agnostic about some of the specifics of his faith. For example, in reviewing The God of Hope and the End of the World by John Polkinghorne, Dyson wrote:
I am myself
a Christian, a member of a community that preserves an ancient heritage
of great literature and great music, provides help and counsel to young
and old when they are in trouble, educates children in moral
responsibility, and worships God in its own fashion. But I find
Polkinghorne's theology altogether too narrow for my taste. I have no
use for a theology that claims to know the answers to deep questions but
bases its arguments on the beliefs of a single tribe. I am a practicing
Christian but not a believing Christian. To me, to worship God means to
recognize that mind and intelligence are woven into the fabric of our
universe in a way that altogether surpasses our comprehension.
In The God Delusion (2006), atheist activist Richard Dawkins singled out Dyson for accepting the Templeton Prize in 2000: "It would be taken as an endorsement of religion by one of the world's most distinguished physicists." In 2000, Dyson declared that he was a (non-denominational) Christian, and he disagreed with Dawkins on several occasions, as when he criticized Dawkins' understanding of evolution.
Dyson published a number of collections of speculations and
observations about technology, science, and the future. In 1996, he was
awarded the Lewis Thomas Prize for Writing about Science.
In 2000, Dyson was awarded the Templeton Prize for Progress in Religion.
In 2003, Dyson was awarded the Telluride Tech Festival Award of Technology in Telluride, Colorado.
In 2011, Dyson received as one of twenty distinguished Old Wykehamists at the Ad Portas celebration, the highest honor that Winchester College bestows.
Advanced Quantum Mechanics, World Scientific, 2007, ISBN978-981-270-661-4. Freely available at: arXiv:quant-ph/0608140. (Dyson's 1951 Cornell lecture notes transcribed by David Derbes)
A Many-Colored Glass: Reflections on the Place of Life in the Universe, University of Virginia Press, 2007. Review
Birds and Frogs: Selected Papers, 1990–2014, World Scientific Publishing Company, 2015.
In philosophy, Leibniz is most noted for his optimism, i.e. his conclusion that our universe is, in a restricted sense, the best possible one that God could have created, an idea that was often lampooned by others such as Voltaire. Leibniz, along with René Descartes and Baruch Spinoza, was one of the three great 17th-century advocates of rationalism. The work of Leibniz anticipated modern logic and analytic philosophy, but his philosophy also assimilates elements of the scholastic tradition, notably that conclusions are produced by applying reason to first principles or prior definitions rather than to empirical evidence.
Leibniz made major contributions to physics and technology, and anticipated notions that surfaced much later in philosophy, probability theory, biology, medicine, geology, psychology, linguistics, and computer science. He wrote works on philosophy, politics, law, ethics, theology, history, and philology. Leibniz also contributed to the field of library science. While serving as overseer of the Wolfenbüttel library in Germany, he devised a cataloging system that would serve as a guide for many of Europe's largest libraries. Leibniz's contributions to this vast array of subjects were scattered in various learned journals, in tens of thousands of letters, and in unpublished manuscripts. He wrote in several languages, but primarily in Latin, French and German as well as English, Italian and Dutch. There is no complete gathering of the writings of Leibniz translated into English.
21. Juny am Sontag 1646 Ist mein
Sohn Gottfried Wilhelm, post sextam vespertinam 1/4 uff 7 uhr abents zur
welt gebohren, im Wassermann.
In English:
On Sunday 21 June [NS: 1 July] 1646, my son Gottfried Wilhelm was born into the world a quarter before seven in the evening, in Aquarius.
Leibniz was baptized on 3 July of that year at St. Nicholas Church, Leipzig; his godfather was the Lutheran theologian Martin Geier [de]. His father died when he was six years old, and from that point on he was raised by his mother.
Leibniz's father had been a Professor of Moral Philosophy at the University of Leipzig,
and the boy later inherited his father's personal library. He was given
free access to it from the age of seven. While Leibniz's schoolwork was
largely confined to the study of a small canon
of authorities, his father's library enabled him to study a wide
variety of advanced philosophical and theological works—ones that he
would not have otherwise been able to read until his college years. Access to his father's library, largely written in Latin, also led to his proficiency in the Latin language, which he achieved by the age of 12. He also composed 300 hexameters of Latin verse, in a single morning, for a special event at school at the age of 13.
In April 1661 he enrolled in his father's former university at age 14, and completed his bachelor's degree in Philosophy in December 1662. He defended his Disputatio Metaphysica de Principio Individui (Metaphysical Disputation on the Principle of Individuation), which addressed the principle of individuation, on 9 June 1663. Leibniz earned his master's degree in Philosophy on 7 February 1664. He published and defended a dissertationSpecimen Quaestionum Philosophicarum ex Jure collectarum (An Essay of Collected Philosophical Problems of Right),
arguing for both a theoretical and a pedagogical relationship between
philosophy and law, in December 1664. After one year of legal studies,
he was awarded his bachelor's degree in Law on 28 September 1665. His dissertation was titled De conditionibus (On Conditions).
In early 1666, at age 19, Leibniz wrote his first book, De Arte Combinatoria (On the Combinatorial Art), the first part of which was also his habilitation thesis in Philosophy, which he defended in March 1666.
His next goal was to earn his license and Doctorate in Law, which
normally required three years of study. In 1666, the University of
Leipzig turned down Leibniz's doctoral application and refused to grant
him a Doctorate in Law, most likely due to his relative youth. Leibniz subsequently left Leipzig.
Leibniz then enrolled in the University of Altdorf and quickly submitted a thesis, which he had probably been working on earlier in Leipzig. The title of his thesis was Disputatio Inauguralis de Casibus Perplexis in Jure (Inaugural Disputation on Ambiguous Legal Cases).
Leibniz earned his license to practice law and his Doctorate in Law in
November 1666. He next declined the offer of an academic appointment at
Altdorf, saying that "my thoughts were turned in an entirely different
direction".
As an adult, Leibniz often introduced himself as "Gottfried von Leibniz". Many posthumously published editions of his writings presented his name on the title page as "Freiherr
G. W. von Leibniz." However, no document has ever been found from any
contemporary government that stated his appointment to any form of nobility.
1666–1676
Engraving of Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz
Leibniz's first position was as a salaried secretary to an alchemical society in Nuremberg. He knew fairly little about the subject at that time but presented himself as deeply learned. He soon met Johann Christian von Boyneburg (1622–1672), the dismissed chief minister of the Elector of Mainz, Johann Philipp von Schönborn.
Von Boyneburg hired Leibniz as an assistant, and shortly thereafter
reconciled with the Elector and introduced Leibniz to him. Leibniz then
dedicated an essay on law to the Elector in the hope of obtaining
employment. The stratagem worked; the Elector asked Leibniz to assist
with the redrafting of the legal code for the Electorate.
In 1669, Leibniz was appointed assessor in the Court of Appeal.
Although von Boyneburg died late in 1672, Leibniz remained under the
employment of his widow until she dismissed him in 1674.
Von Boyneburg did much to promote Leibniz's reputation, and the
latter's memoranda and letters began to attract favorable notice. After
Leibniz's service to the Elector there soon followed a diplomatic role.
He published an essay, under the pseudonym of a fictitious Polish
nobleman, arguing (unsuccessfully) for the German candidate for the
Polish crown. The main force in European geopolitics during Leibniz's
adult life was the ambition of Louis XIV of France, backed by French military and economic might. Meanwhile, the Thirty Years' War had left German-speaking Europe
exhausted, fragmented, and economically backward. Leibniz proposed to
protect German-speaking Europe by distracting Louis as follows. France
would be invited to take Egypt as a stepping stone towards an eventual conquest of the Dutch East Indies.
In return, France would agree to leave Germany and the Netherlands
undisturbed. This plan obtained the Elector's cautious support. In 1672,
the French government invited Leibniz to Paris for discussion, but the plan was soon overtaken by the outbreak of the Franco-Dutch War and became irrelevant. Napoleon's failed invasion of Egypt in 1798
can be seen as an unwitting, late implementation of Leibniz's plan,
after the Eastern hemisphere colonial supremacy in Europe had already
passed from the Dutch to the British.
Thus Leibniz went to Paris in 1672. Soon after arriving, he met Dutch physicist and mathematician Christiaan Huygens and realised that his own knowledge of mathematics and physics was patchy. With Huygens as his mentor, he began a program of self-study
that soon pushed him to making major contributions to both subjects,
including discovering his version of the differential and integral calculus. He met Nicolas Malebranche and Antoine Arnauld, the leading French philosophers of the day, and studied the writings of Descartes and Pascal, unpublished as well as published. He befriended a German mathematician, Ehrenfried Walther von Tschirnhaus; they corresponded for the rest of their lives.
When it became clear that France would not implement its part of
Leibniz's Egyptian plan, the Elector sent his nephew, escorted by
Leibniz, on a related mission to the English government in London, early
in 1673. There Leibniz came into acquaintance of Henry Oldenburg and John Collins. He met with the Royal Society
where he demonstrated a calculating machine that he had designed and
had been building since 1670. The machine was able to execute all four
basic operations (adding, subtracting, multiplying, and dividing), and
the society quickly made him an external member.
The mission ended abruptly when news of the Elector's death (12
February 1673) reached them. Leibniz promptly returned to Paris and not,
as had been planned, to Mainz. The sudden deaths of his two patrons in the same winter meant that Leibniz had to find a new basis for his career.
In this regard, a 1669 invitation from Duke John Frederick of Brunswick
to visit Hanover proved to have been fateful. Leibniz had declined the
invitation, but had begun corresponding with the duke in 1671. In 1673,
the duke offered Leibniz the post of counsellor. Leibniz very
reluctantly accepted the position two years later, only after it became
clear that no employment was forthcoming in Paris, whose intellectual
stimulation he relished, or with the Habsburg imperial court.
In 1675 he tried to get admitted to the French Academy of Sciences
as a foreign honorary member, but it was considered that there were
already enough foreigners there and so no invitation came. He left Paris
in October 1676.
House of Hanover, 1676–1716
Leibniz managed to delay his arrival in Hanover until the end of 1676
after making one more short journey to London, where Newton accused him
of having seen Newton's unpublished work on calculus in advance.
This was alleged to be evidence supporting the accusation, made
decades later, that he had stolen calculus from Newton. On the journey
from London to Hanover, Leibniz stopped in The Hague where he met van Leeuwenhoek, the discoverer of microorganisms. He also spent several days in intense discussion with Spinoza, who had just completed his masterwork, the Ethics.
In 1677, he was promoted, at his request, to Privy Counselor of
Justice, a post he held for the rest of his life. Leibniz served three
consecutive rulers of the House of Brunswick as historian, political
adviser, and most consequentially, as librarian of the ducal library. He thenceforth employed his pen on all the various political, historical, and theological matters involving the House of Brunswick; the resulting documents form a valuable part of the historical record for the period.
Leibniz began promoting a project to use windmills to improve the
mining operations in the Harz Mountains. This project did little to
improve mining operations and was shut down by Duke Ernst August in
1685.
Among the few people in north Germany to accept Leibniz were the Electress Sophia of Hanover (1630–1714), her daughter Sophia Charlotte of Hanover (1668–1705), the Queen of Prussia and his avowed disciple, and Caroline of Ansbach, the consort of her grandson, the future George II.
To each of these women he was correspondent, adviser, and friend. In
turn, they all approved of Leibniz more than did their spouses and the
future king George I of Great Britain.
The population of Hanover was only about 10,000, and its
provinciality eventually grated on Leibniz. Nevertheless, to be a major
courtier to the House of Brunswick
was quite an honor, especially in light of the meteoric rise in the
prestige of that House during Leibniz's association with it. In 1692,
the Duke of Brunswick became a hereditary Elector of the Holy Roman Empire. The British Act of Settlement 1701 designated the Electress Sophia and her descent as the royal family of England, once both King William III and his sister-in-law and successor, Queen Anne,
were dead. Leibniz played a role in the initiatives and negotiations
leading up to that Act, but not always an effective one. For example,
something he published anonymously in England, thinking to promote the
Brunswick cause, was formally censured by the British Parliament.
The Brunswicks tolerated the enormous effort Leibniz devoted to
intellectual pursuits unrelated to his duties as a courtier, pursuits
such as perfecting calculus, writing about other mathematics, logic,
physics, and philosophy, and keeping up a vast correspondence. He began
working on calculus in 1674; the earliest evidence of its use in his
surviving notebooks is 1675. By 1677 he had a coherent system in hand,
but did not publish it until 1684. Leibniz's most important mathematical
papers were published between 1682 and 1692, usually in a journal which
he and Otto Mencke founded in 1682, the Acta Eruditorum.
That journal played a key role in advancing his mathematical and
scientific reputation, which in turn enhanced his eminence in diplomacy,
history, theology, and philosophy.
The Elector Ernest Augustus commissioned Leibniz to write a history of the House of Brunswick, going back to the time of Charlemagne
or earlier, hoping that the resulting book would advance his dynastic
ambitions. From 1687 to 1690, Leibniz traveled extensively in Germany,
Austria, and Italy, seeking and finding archival materials bearing on
this project. Decades went by but no history appeared; the next Elector
became quite annoyed at Leibniz's apparent dilatoriness. Leibniz never
finished the project, in part because of his huge output on many other
fronts, but also because he insisted on writing a meticulously
researched and erudite book based on archival sources, when his patrons
would have been quite happy with a short popular book, one perhaps
little more than a genealogy
with commentary, to be completed in three years or less. They never
knew that he had in fact carried out a fair part of his assigned task:
when the material Leibniz had written and collected for his history of
the House of Brunswick was finally published in the 19th century, it
filled three volumes.
In 1708, John Keill,
writing in the journal of the Royal Society and with Newton's presumed
blessing, accused Leibniz of having plagiarised Newton's calculus. Thus began the calculus priority dispute
which darkened the remainder of Leibniz's life. A formal investigation
by the Royal Society (in which Newton was an unacknowledged
participant), undertaken in response to Leibniz's demand for a
retraction, upheld Keill's charge. Historians of mathematics writing
since 1900 or so have tended to acquit Leibniz, pointing to important
differences between Leibniz's and Newton's versions of calculus.
In 1711, while traveling in northern Europe, the Russian TsarPeter the Great
stopped in Hanover and met Leibniz, who then took some interest in
Russian matters for the rest of his life. In 1712, Leibniz began a
two-year residence in Vienna, where he was appointed Imperial Court Councillor to the Habsburgs. On the death of Queen Anne in 1714, Elector George Louis became King George I of Great Britain,
under the terms of the 1701 Act of Settlement. Even though Leibniz had
done much to bring about this happy event, it was not to be his hour of
glory. Despite the intercession of the Princess of Wales, Caroline of
Ansbach, George I forbade Leibniz to join him in London until he
completed at least one volume of the history of the Brunswick family his
father had commissioned nearly 30 years earlier. Moreover, for George I
to include Leibniz in his London court would have been deemed insulting
to Newton, who was seen as having won the calculus priority dispute and
whose standing in British official circles could not have been higher.
Finally, his dear friend and defender, the Dowager Electress Sophia,
died in 1714.
Death
Leibniz died in Hanover
in 1716. At the time, he was so out of favor that neither George I (who
happened to be near Hanover at that time) nor any fellow courtier other
than his personal secretary attended the funeral. Even though Leibniz
was a life member of the Royal Society and the Berlin Academy of Sciences, neither organization saw fit to honor his death. His grave went unmarked for more than 50 years. Leibniz was eulogized by Fontenelle, before the French Academy of Sciences in Paris, which had admitted him as a foreign member in 1700. The eulogy was composed at the behest of the Duchess of Orleans, a niece of the Electress Sophia.
Personal life
Leibniz
never married. He complained on occasion about money, but the fair sum
he left to his sole heir, his sister's stepson, proved that the
Brunswicks had, by and large, paid him well. In his diplomatic
endeavors, he at times verged on the unscrupulous, as was all too often
the case with professional diplomats of his day. On several occasions,
Leibniz backdated and altered personal manuscripts, actions which put
him in a bad light during the calculus controversy.
On the other hand, he was charming, well-mannered, and not without humor and imagination. He had many friends and admirers all over Europe. Though he identified as a protestant, Leibniz learned to appreciate aspects of Catholicism through his patrons and colleagues. He never admitted the Protestant view of the Pope as an Antichrist. Leibniz was claimed as a philosophical theist. Leibniz remained committed to Trinitarian Christianity throughout his life.
Philosopher
Leibniz's
philosophical thinking appears fragmented, because his philosophical
writings consist mainly of a multitude of short pieces: journal
articles, manuscripts published long after his death, and many letters
to many correspondents. He wrote only two book-length philosophical
treatises, of which only the Théodicée of 1710 was published in his lifetime.
Leibniz dated his beginning as a philosopher to his Discourse on Metaphysics, which he composed in 1686 as a commentary on a running dispute between Nicolas Malebranche and Antoine Arnauld. This led to an extensive and valuable correspondence with Arnauld; it and the Discourse
were not published until the 19th century. In 1695, Leibniz made his
public entrée into European philosophy with a journal article titled
"New System of the Nature and Communication of Substances". Between 1695 and 1705, he composed his New Essays on Human Understanding, a lengthy commentary on John Locke's 1690 An Essay Concerning Human Understanding, but upon learning of Locke's 1704 death, lost the desire to publish it, so that the New Essays were not published until 1765. The Monadologie, composed in 1714 and published posthumously, consists of 90 aphorisms.
Leibniz met Spinoza
in 1676, read some of his unpublished writings, and has since been
suspected of appropriating some of Spinoza's ideas. While Leibniz
admired Spinoza's powerful intellect, he was also forthrightly dismayed
by Spinoza's conclusions, especially when these were inconsistent with Christian orthodoxy.
Unlike Descartes and Spinoza, Leibniz had a thorough university education in philosophy. He was influenced by his Leipzig professor Jakob Thomasius, who also supervised his BA thesis in philosophy. Leibniz also eagerly read Francisco Suárez, a Spanish Jesuit respected even in Lutheran universities. Leibniz was deeply interested in the new methods and conclusions of Descartes, Huygens, Newton, and Boyle,
but viewed their work through a lens heavily tinted by scholastic
notions. Yet it remains the case that Leibniz's methods and concerns
often anticipate the logic, and analytic and linguistic philosophy of the 20th century.
Principles
Leibniz variously invoked one or another of seven fundamental philosophical Principles:
Identity/contradiction. If a proposition is true, then its negation is false and vice versa.
Identity of indiscernibles.
Two distinct things cannot have all their properties in common. If
every predicate possessed by x is also possessed by y and vice versa,
then entities x and y are identical; to suppose two things indiscernible
is to suppose the same thing under two names. Frequently invoked in
modern logic and philosophy, the "identity of indiscernibles" is often
referred to as Leibniz's Law. It has attracted the most controversy and
criticism, especially from corpuscular philosophy and quantum mechanics.
Sufficient reason. "There must be a sufficient reason for anything to exist, for any event to occur, for any truth to obtain."
Pre-established harmony.
"[T]he appropriate nature of each substance brings it about that what
happens to one corresponds to what happens to all the others, without,
however, their acting upon one another directly." (Discourse on Metaphysics,
XIV) A dropped glass shatters because it "knows" it has hit the ground,
and not because the impact with the ground "compels" the glass to
split.
Optimism. "God assuredly always chooses the best."
Plenitude. Leibniz believed that the best of all possible worlds would actualize every genuine possibility, and argued in Théodicée
that this best of all possible worlds will contain all possibilities,
with our finite experience of eternity giving no reason to dispute
nature's perfection.
Leibniz would on occasion give a rational defense of a specific principle, but more often took them for granted.
Monads
A page from Leibniz's manuscript of the Monadology
Leibniz's best known contribution to metaphysics is his theory of monads, as exposited in Monadologie. He proposes his theory that the universe is made of an infinite number of simple substances known as monads. Monads can also be compared to the corpuscles of the Mechanical Philosophy
of René Descartes and others. These simple substances or monads are the
"ultimate units of existence in nature". Monads have no parts but still
exist by the qualities that they have. These qualities are continuously
changing over time, and each monad is unique. They are also not
affected by time and are subject to only creation and annihilation. Monads are centers of force; substance is force, while space, matter, and motion are merely phenomenal.
Leibniz's proof of God can be summarized in the Théodicée. Reason is governed by the principle of contradiction and the principle of sufficient reason. Using the principle of reasoning, Leibniz concluded that the first reason of all things is God.
All that we see and experience is subject to change, and the fact that
this world is contingent can be explained by the possibility of the
world being arranged differently in space and time. The contingent world
must have some necessary reason for its existence. Leibniz uses a
geometry book as an example to explain his reasoning. If this book was
copied from an infinite chain of copies, there must be some reason for
the content of the book. Leibniz concluded that there must be the "monas monadum" or God.
The ontological
essence of a monad is its irreducible simplicity. Unlike atoms, monads
possess no material or spatial character. They also differ from atoms by
their complete mutual independence, so that interactions among monads
are only apparent. Instead, by virtue of the principle of pre-established harmony,
each monad follows a pre-programmed set of "instructions" peculiar to
itself, so that a monad "knows" what to do at each moment. By virtue of
these intrinsic instructions, each monad is like a little mirror of the
universe. Monads need not be "small"; e.g., each human being constitutes
a monad, in which case free will is problematic.
Monads are purported to have gotten rid of the problematic:
interaction between mind and matter arising in the system of Descartes;
lack of individuation inherent to the system of Spinoza, which represents individual creatures as merely accidental.
Theodicy and optimism
The Theodicy tries to justify the apparent imperfections of the world by claiming that it is optimal among all possible worlds.
It must be the best possible and most balanced world, because it was
created by an all powerful and all knowing God, who would not choose to
create an imperfect world if a better world could be known to him or
possible to exist. In effect, apparent flaws that can be identified in
this world must exist in every possible world, because otherwise God
would have chosen to create the world that excluded those flaws.
Leibniz asserted that the truths of theology (religion) and
philosophy cannot contradict each other, since reason and faith are both
"gifts of God" so that their conflict would imply God contending
against himself. The Theodicy is Leibniz's attempt to reconcile his personal philosophical system with his interpretation of the tenets of Christianity. This project was motivated in part by Leibniz's belief, shared by many conservative philosophers and theologians during the Enlightenment,
in the rational and enlightened nature of the Christian religion as
compared against its purportedly less-advanced non-Western counterparts.
It was also shaped by Leibniz's belief in the perfectibility of human
nature (if humanity relied on correct philosophy and religion as a
guide), and by his belief that metaphysical necessity must have a
rational or logical foundation, even if this metaphysical causality
seemed inexplicable in terms of physical necessity (the natural laws
identified by science).
Because reason and faith must be entirely reconciled, any tenet
of faith which could not be defended by reason must be rejected. Leibniz
then approached one of the central criticisms of Christian theism: if God is all good, all wise, and all powerful, then how did evil come into the world?
The answer (according to Leibniz) is that, while God is indeed
unlimited in wisdom and power, his human creations, as creations, are
limited both in their wisdom and in their will (power to act). This
predisposes humans to false beliefs, wrong decisions, and ineffective
actions in the exercise of their free will. God does not arbitrarily inflict pain and suffering on humans; rather he permits both moral evil (sin) and physical evil (pain and suffering) as the necessary consequences of metaphysical evil (imperfection), as a means by which humans can identify and correct their erroneous decisions, and as a contrast to true good.
Further, although human actions flow from prior causes that
ultimately arise in God and therefore are known to God as metaphysical
certainties, an individual's free will is exercised within natural laws,
where choices are merely contingently necessary and to be decided in
the event by a "wonderful spontaneity" that provides individuals with an
escape from rigorous predestination.
Discourse on Metaphysics
For
Leibniz, "God is an absolutely perfect being". He describes this
perfection later in section VI as the simplest form of something with
the most substantial outcome (VI). Along these lines, he declares that
every type of perfection "pertains to him (God) in the highest degree"
(I). Even though his types of perfections are not specifically drawn
out, Leibniz highlights the one thing that, to him, does certify
imperfections and proves that God is perfect: "that one acts imperfectly
if he acts with less perfection than he is capable of", and since God
is a perfect being, he cannot act imperfectly (III). Because God cannot
act imperfectly, the decisions he makes pertaining to the world must be
perfect. Leibniz also comforts readers, stating that because he has done
everything to the most perfect degree; those who love him cannot be
injured. However, to love God is a subject of difficulty as Leibniz
believes that we are "not disposed to wish for that which God desires"
because we have the ability to alter our disposition (IV). In accordance
with this, many act as rebels, but Leibniz says that the only way we
can truly love God is by being content "with all that comes to us
according to his will" (IV).
Because God is "an absolutely perfect being" (I), Leibniz argues
that God would be acting imperfectly if he acted with any less
perfection than what he is able of (III). His syllogism then ends with
the statement that God has made the world perfectly in all ways. This
also affects how we should view God and his will. Leibniz states that,
in lieu of God’s will, we have to understand that God "is the best of
all masters" and he will know when his good succeeds, so we, therefore,
must act in conformity to his good will—or as much of it as we
understand (IV). In our view of God, Leibniz declares that we cannot
admire the work solely because of the maker, lest we mar the glory and
love God in doing so. Instead, we must admire the maker for the work he
has done (II). Effectively, Leibniz states that if we say the earth is
good because of the will of God, and not good according to some
standards of goodness, then how can we praise God for what he has done
if contrary actions are also praiseworthy by this definition (II).
Leibniz then asserts that different principles and geometry cannot
simply be from the will of God, but must follow from his understanding.
Fundamental question of metaphysics
Leibniz wrote: "Why is there something rather than nothing?
The sufficient reason ... is found in a substance which ... is a
necessary being bearing the reason for its existence within itself." Martin Heidegger called this question "the fundamental question of metaphysics".
Symbolic thought
Leibniz
believed that much of human reasoning could be reduced to calculations
of a sort, and that such calculations could resolve many differences of
opinion:
The only way to rectify our reasonings is to make them as
tangible as those of the Mathematicians, so that we can find our error
at a glance, and when there are disputes among persons, we can simply
say: Let us calculate [calculemus], without further ado, to see who is right.
Leibniz's calculus ratiocinator, which resembles symbolic logic, can be viewed as a way of making such calculations feasible. Leibniz wrote memoranda that can now be read as groping attempts to get symbolic logic—and thus his calculus—off
the ground. These writings remained unpublished until the appearance of
a selection edited by C.I. Gerhardt (1859). L. Couturat published a
selection in 1901; by this time the main developments of modern logic
had been created by Charles Sanders Peirce and by Gottlob Frege.
Leibniz thought symbols
were important for human understanding. He attached so much importance
to the development of good notations that he attributed all his
discoveries in mathematics to this. His notation for calculus is an example of his skill in this regard. Peirce, a 19th-century pioneer of semiotics,
shared Leibniz's passion for symbols and notation, and his belief that
these are essential to a well-running logic and mathematics.
But Leibniz took his speculations much further. Defining a character
as any written sign, he then defined a "real" character as one that
represents an idea directly and not simply as the word embodying the
idea. Some real characters, such as the notation of logic, serve only to
facilitate reasoning. Many characters well known in his day, including Egyptian hieroglyphics, Chinese characters, and the symbols of astronomy and chemistry, he deemed not real. Instead, he proposed the creation of a characteristica universalis or "universal characteristic", built on an alphabet of human thought in which each fundamental concept would be represented by a unique "real" character:
It is obvious that if we could find characters or signs
suited for expressing all our thoughts as clearly and as exactly as
arithmetic expresses numbers or geometry expresses lines, we could do in
all matters insofar as they are subject to reasoning all that we
can do in arithmetic and geometry. For all investigations which depend
on reasoning would be carried out by transposing these characters and by
a species of calculus.
Complex thoughts would be represented by combining characters for simpler thoughts. Leibniz saw that the uniqueness of prime factorization suggests a central role for prime numbers in the universal characteristic, a striking anticipation of Gödel numbering. Granted, there is no intuitive or mnemonic way to number any set of elementary concepts using the prime numbers.
Because Leibniz was a mathematical novice when he first wrote about the characteristic, at first he did not conceive it as an algebra but rather as a universal language
or script. Only in 1676 did he conceive of a kind of "algebra of
thought", modeled on and including conventional algebra and its
notation. The resulting characteristic included a logical calculus, some combinatorics, algebra, his analysis situs (geometry of situation), a universal concept language, and more. What Leibniz actually intended by his characteristica universalis and calculus ratiocinator, and the extent to which modern formal logic does justice to calculus, may never be established.
Leibniz's idea of reasoning through a universal language of symbols and
calculations remarkably foreshadows great 20th-century developments in
formal systems, such as Turing completeness, where computation was used to define equivalent universal languages.
Formal logic
Leibniz has been noted as one of the most important logicians between the times of Aristotle and Gottlob Frege. Leibniz enunciated the principal properties of what we now call conjunction, disjunction, negation, identity, set inclusion, and the empty set. The principles of Leibniz's logic and, arguably, of his whole philosophy, reduce to two:
All our ideas are compounded from a very small number of simple ideas, which form the alphabet of human thought.
Complex ideas proceed from these simple ideas by a uniform and
symmetrical combination, analogous to arithmetical multiplication.
Leibniz published nothing on formal logic in his lifetime; most
of what he wrote on the subject consists of working drafts. In his History of Western Philosophy, Bertrand Russell
went so far as to claim that Leibniz had developed logic in his
unpublished writings to a level which was reached only 200 years later.
Russell's principal work on Leibniz found that many of Leibniz's
most startling philosophical ideas and claims (e.g., that each of the
fundamental monads mirrors the whole universe) follow logically from Leibniz's conscious choice to reject relations between things as unreal. He regarded such relations as (real) qualities of things (Leibniz admitted unarypredicates
only): For him, "Mary is the mother of John" describes separate
qualities of Mary and of John. This view contrasts with the relational
logic of De Morgan, Peirce, Schröder and Russell himself, now standard in predicate logic. Notably, Leibniz also declared space and time to be inherently relational.
Mathematician
Although the mathematical notion of function
was implicit in trigonometric and logarithmic tables, which existed in
his day, Leibniz was the first, in 1692 and 1694, to employ it
explicitly, to denote any of several geometric concepts derived from a
curve, such as abscissa, ordinate, tangent, chord, and the perpendicular.
In the 18th century, "function" lost these geometrical associations.
Leibniz also believed that the sum of an infinite number of zeros would
equal to one half using the analogy of the creation of the world from
nothing. Leibniz was also one of the pioneers in actuarial science, calculating the purchase price of life annuities and the liquidation of a state's debt.
Leibniz's discoveries of Boolean algebra and of symbolic logic,
also relevant to mathematics, are discussed in the preceding section.
The best overview of Leibniz's writings on calculus may be found in Bos
(1974).
Linear systems
Leibniz arranged the coefficients of a system of linear equations into an array, now called a matrix, in order to find a solution to the system if it existed. This method was later called Gaussian elimination. Leibniz laid down the foundations and theory of determinants, although Seki Takakazu discovered determinants well before Leibniz. His works show calculating the determinants using cofactors. Calculating the determinant using cofactors is named the Leibniz formula. Finding the determinant of a matrix using this method proves impractical with large n, requiring to calculate n! products and the number of n-permutations. He also solved systems of linear equations using determinants, which is now called Cramer's rule.
This method for solving systems of linear equations based on
determinants was found in 1684 by Leibniz (Cramer published his findings
in 1750). Although Gaussian elimination requires arithmetic operations, linear algebra textbooks still teach cofactor expansion before LU factorization.
Leibniz wrote that circles "can most simply be expressed by this
series, that is, the aggregate of fractions alternately added and
subtracted". However this formula is only accurate with a large number of terms, using 10,000,000 terms to obtain the correct value of π/4 to 8 decimal places. Leibniz attempted to create a definition for a straight line while attempting to prove the parallel postulate.
While most mathematicians defined a straight line as the shortest line
between two points, Leibniz believed that this was merely a property of a
straight line rather than the definition.
Calculus
Leibniz is credited, along with Sir Isaac Newton, with the discovery of calculus
(differential and integral calculus). According to Leibniz's notebooks,
a critical breakthrough occurred on 11 November 1675, when he employed
integral calculus for the first time to find the area under the graph of
a function y = f(x). He introduced several notations used to this day, for instance the integral sign∫, representing an elongated S, from the Latin word summa, and the d used for differentials, from the Latin word differentia. Leibniz did not publish anything about his calculus until 1684. Leibniz expressed the inverse relation of integration and differentiation, later called the fundamental theorem of calculus, by means of a figure in his 1693 paper Supplementum geometriae dimensoriae.... However, James Gregory is credited for the theorem's discovery in geometric form, Isaac Barrow proved a more generalized geometric version, and Newton developed supporting theory. The concept became more transparent as developed through Leibniz's formalism and new notation. The product rule of differential calculus
is still called "Leibniz's law". In addition, the theorem that tells
how and when to differentiate under the integral sign is called the Leibniz integral rule.
Leibniz exploited infinitesimals in developing calculus, manipulating them in ways suggesting that they had paradoxicalalgebraic properties. George Berkeley, in a tract called The Analyst and also in De Motu,
criticized these. A recent study argues that Leibnizian calculus was
free of contradictions, and was better grounded than Berkeley's
empiricist criticisms.
From 1711 until his death, Leibniz was engaged in a dispute with
John Keill, Newton and others, over whether Leibniz had invented
calculus independently of Newton. This subject is treated at length in
the article Leibniz–Newton calculus controversy.
Leibniz was the first to use the term analysis situs, later used in the 19th century to refer to what is now known as topology. There are two takes on this situation. On the one hand, Mates, citing a 1954 paper in German by Jacob Freudenthal, argues:
Although for Leibniz the situs of a sequence of points is
completely determined by the distance between them and is altered if
those distances are altered, his admirer Euler, in the famous 1736 paper solving the Königsberg Bridge Problem and its generalizations, used the term geometria situs
in such a sense that the situs remains unchanged under topological
deformations. He mistakenly credits Leibniz with originating this
concept. ... [It] is sometimes not realized that Leibniz used the term
in an entirely different sense and hence can hardly be considered the
founder of that part of mathematics.
But Hideaki Hirano argues differently, quoting Mandelbrot:
To sample Leibniz' scientific works is a sobering
experience. Next to calculus, and to other thoughts that have been
carried out to completion, the number and variety of premonitory thrusts
is overwhelming. We saw examples in "packing", ... My Leibniz mania is
further reinforced by finding that for one moment its hero attached
importance to geometric scaling. In Euclidis Prota ..., which is
an attempt to tighten Euclid's axioms, he states ...: "I have diverse
definitions for the straight line. The straight line is a curve, any
part of which is similar to the whole, and it alone has this property,
not only among curves but among sets." This claim can be proved today.
Thus the fractal geometry promoted by Mandelbrot drew on Leibniz's notions of self-similarity and the principle of continuity: Natura non facit saltus.
We also see that when Leibniz wrote, in a metaphysical vein, that "the
straight line is a curve, any part of which is similar to the whole", he
was anticipating topology by more than two centuries. As for "packing",
Leibniz told his friend and correspondent Des Bosses to imagine a
circle, then to inscribe within it three congruent circles with maximum
radius; the latter smaller circles could be filled with three even
smaller circles by the same procedure. This process can be continued
infinitely, from which arises a good idea of self-similarity. Leibniz's
improvement of Euclid's axiom contains the same concept.
Scientist and engineer
Leibniz's
writings are currently discussed, not only for their anticipations and
possible discoveries not yet recognized, but as ways of advancing
present knowledge. Much of his writing on physics is included in
Gerhardt's Mathematical Writings.
Physics
Leibniz contributed a fair amount to the statics and dynamics emerging around him, often disagreeing with Descartes and Newton. He devised a new theory of motion (dynamics) based on kinetic energy and potential energy,
which posited space as relative, whereas Newton was thoroughly
convinced that space was absolute. An important example of Leibniz's
mature physical thinking is his Specimen Dynamicum of 1695.
Until the discovery of subatomic particles and the quantum mechanics
governing them, many of Leibniz's speculative ideas about aspects of
nature not reducible to statics and dynamics made little sense. For
instance, he anticipated Albert Einstein by arguing, against Newton, that space,
time and motion are relative, not absolute: "As for my own opinion, I
have said more than once, that I hold space to be something merely
relative, as time is, that I hold it to be an order of coexistences, as
time is an order of successions."
Leibniz held a relationist notion of space and time, against Newton's substantivalist views.
According to Newton's substantivalism, space and time are entities in
their own right, existing independently of things. Leibniz's
relationism, on the other hand, describes space and time as systems of relations that exist between objects. The rise of general relativity and subsequent work in the history of physics has put Leibniz's stance in a more favorable light.
One of Leibniz's projects was to recast Newton's theory as a vortex theory.
However, his project went beyond vortex theory, since at its heart
there was an attempt to explain one of the most difficult problems in
physics, that of the origin of the cohesion of matter.
The principle of sufficient reason has been invoked in recent cosmology, and his identity of indiscernibles in quantum mechanics, a field some even credit him with having anticipated in some sense. Those who advocate digital philosophy,
a recent direction in cosmology, claim Leibniz as a precursor. In
addition to his theories about the nature of reality, Leibniz's
contributions to the development of calculus have also had a major
impact on physics.
The vis viva
Leibniz's vis viva (Latin for "living force") is mv2, twice the modern kinetic energy.
He realized that the total energy would be conserved in certain
mechanical systems, so he considered it an innate motive characteristic
of matter. Here too his thinking gave rise to another regrettable nationalistic dispute. His vis viva was seen as rivaling the conservation of momentum championed by Newton in England and by Descartes in France; hence academics in those countries tended to neglect Leibniz's idea. In reality, both energy and momentum are conserved, so the two approaches are equally valid.
Other natural science
By proposing that the earth has a molten core, he anticipated modern geology. In embryology,
he was a preformationist, but also proposed that organisms are the
outcome of a combination of an infinite number of possible
microstructures and of their powers. In the life sciences and paleontology,
he revealed an amazing transformist intuition, fueled by his study of
comparative anatomy and fossils. One of his principal works on this
subject, Protogaea, unpublished in his lifetime, has recently been published in English for the first time. He worked out a primal organismic theory.
In medicine, he exhorted the physicians of his time—with some
results—to ground their theories in detailed comparative observations
and verified experiments, and to distinguish firmly scientific and
metaphysical points of view.
Psychology
Psychology had been a central interest of Leibniz. He appears to be an "underappreciated pioneer of psychology" He wrote on topics which are now regarded as fields of psychology: attention and consciousness, memory, learning (association), motivation (the act of "striving"), emergent individuality, the general dynamics of development (evolutionary psychology). His discussions in the New Essays and Monadology
often rely on everyday observations such as the behaviour of a dog or
the noise of the sea, and he develops intuitive analogies (the
synchronous running of clocks or the balance spring of a clock). He also
devised postulates and principles that apply to psychology: the
continuum of the unnoticed petite perceptions to the distinct, self-aware apperception, and psychophysical parallelism
from the point of view of causality and of purpose: “Souls act
according to the laws of final causes, through aspirations, ends and
means. Bodies act according to the laws of efficient causes, i.e. the
laws of motion. And these two realms, that of efficient causes and that
of final causes, harmonize with one another.” This idea refers to the mind-body problem, stating that the mind and
brain do not act upon each other, but act alongside each other
separately but in harmony. Leibniz, however, did not use the term psychologia.
Leibniz’ epistemological position—against John Locke and English empiricism (sensualism)—was
made clear: “Nihil est in intellectu quod non fuerit in sensu, nisi
intellectu ipse.” – “Nothing is in the intellect that was not first in
the senses, except the intellect itself.”
Principles that are not present in sensory impressions can be
recognised in human perception and consciousness: logical inferences,
categories of thought, the principle of causality and the principle of purpose (teleology).
Leibniz found his most important interpreter in Wilhelm Wundt, founder of psychology as a discipline. Wundt used the "… nisi intellectu ipse" quotation 1862 on the title page of his Beiträge zur Theorie der Sinneswahrnehmung (Contributions on the Theory of Sensory Perception) and published a detailed and aspiring monograph on Leibniz Wundt shaped the term apperception,
introduced by Leibniz, into an experimental psychologically based
apperception psychology that included neuropsychological modelling – an
excellent example of how a concept created by a great philosopher could
stimulate a psychological research program. One principle in the
thinking of Leibniz played a fundamental role: “the principle of
equality of separate but corresponding viewpoints.” Wundt characterized
this style of thought (perspectivism)
in a way that also applied for him—viewpoints that "supplement one
another, while also being able to appear as opposites that only resolve
themselves when considered more deeply."
Much of Leibniz's work went on to have a great impact on the field of psychology.
Leibniz thought that there are many petites perceptions, or small
perceptions of which we perceive but of which we are unaware. He
believed that by the principle that phenomena found in nature were
continuous by default, it was likely that the transition between
conscious and unconscious states had intermediary steps.
For this to be true, there must also be a portion of the mind of which
we are unaware at any given time. His theory regarding consciousness in
relation to the principle of continuity can be seen as an early theory
regarding the stages of sleep. In this way, Leibniz's theory of perception can be viewed as one of many theories leading up to the idea of the unconscious. Leibniz was a direct influence on Ernst Platner, who is credited with originally coining the term Unbewußtseyn (unconscious). Additionally, the idea of subliminal stimuli can be traced back to his theory of small perceptions. Leibniz's ideas regarding music and tonal perception went on to influence the laboratory studies of Wilhelm Wundt.
Social science
In public health, he advocated establishing a medical administrative authority, with powers over epidemiology and veterinary medicine.
He worked to set up a coherent medical training program, oriented
towards public health and preventive measures. In economic policy, he
proposed tax reforms and a national insurance program, and discussed the
balance of trade. He even proposed something akin to what much later emerged as game theory. In sociology he laid the ground for communication theory.
Technology
In
1906, Garland published a volume of Leibniz's writings bearing on his
many practical inventions and engineering work. To date, few of these
writings have been translated into English. Nevertheless, it is well
understood that Leibniz was a serious inventor, engineer, and applied
scientist, with great respect for practical life. Following the motto theoria cum praxi, he urged that theory be combined with practical application, and thus has been claimed as the father of applied science.
He designed wind-driven propellers and water pumps, mining machines to
extract ore, hydraulic presses, lamps, submarines, clocks, etc. With Denis Papin, he created a steam engine.
He even proposed a method for desalinating water. From 1680 to 1685, he
struggled to overcome the chronic flooding that afflicted the ducal
silver mines in the Harz Mountains, but did not succeed.
Computation
Leibniz may have been the first computer scientist and information theorist. Early in life, he documented the binary numeral system (base 2), then revisited that system throughout his career. While Leibniz was examining other cultures to compare his metaphysical views, he encountered an ancient Chinese book I Ching. Leibniz interpreted a diagram which showed yin and yang and corresponded it to a zero and one. More information can be found in the Sinophile section. Leibniz may have plagiarized Juan Caramuel y Lobkowitz and Thomas Harriot, who independently developed the binary system, as he was familiar with their works on the binary system. Juan Caramuel y Lobkowitz worked extensively on logarithms including logarithms with base 2.
Thomas Harriot's manuscripts contained a table of binary numbers and
their notation, which demonstrated that any number could be written on a
base 2 system.
Regardless, Leibniz simplified the binary system and articulated
logical properties such as conjunction, disjunction, negation, identity,
inclusion, and the empty set. He anticipated Lagrangian interpolation and algorithmic information theory. His calculus ratiocinator anticipated aspects of the universal Turing machine. In 1961, Norbert Wiener suggested that Leibniz should be considered the patron saint of cybernetics.
In 1671, Leibniz began to invent a machine that could execute all
four arithmetic operations, gradually improving it over a number of
years. This "stepped reckoner" attracted fair attention and was the basis of his election to the Royal Society in 1673. A number of such machines were made during his years in Hanover by a craftsman working under his supervision. They were not an unambiguous success because they did not fully mechanize the carry operation.
Couturat reported finding an unpublished note by Leibniz, dated 1674,
describing a machine capable of performing some algebraic operations. Leibniz also devised a (now reproduced) cipher machine, recovered by Nicholas Rescher in 2010.
In 1693, Leibniz described a design of a machine which could, in
theory, integrate differential equations, which he called "integraph".
Leibniz was groping towards hardware and software concepts worked out much later by Charles Babbage and Ada Lovelace.
In 1679, while mulling over his binary arithmetic, Leibniz imagined a
machine in which binary numbers were represented by marbles, governed by
a rudimentary sort of punched cards.
Modern electronic digital computers replace Leibniz's marbles moving by
gravity with shift registers, voltage gradients, and pulses of
electrons, but otherwise they run roughly as Leibniz envisioned in 1679.
Librarian
Later
in Leibniz’s career (after the death of von Boyneburg), Leibniz moved
to Paris and accepted a position as a librarian in the Hanoverian court
of Johann Friedrich, Duke of Brunswick-Luneburg.
Leibniz’s predecessor, Tobias Fleischer, had already created a
cataloging system for the Duke’s library but it was a clumsy attempt. At
this library, Leibniz focused more on advancing the library than on the
cataloging. For instance, within a month of taking the new position, he
developed a comprehensive plan to expand the library. He was one of the
first to consider developing a core collection for a library and felt
“that a library for display and ostentation is a luxury and indeed
superfluous, but a well-stocked and organized library is important and
useful for all areas of human endeavor and is to be regarded on the same
level as schools and churches”.
Unfortunately, Leibniz lacked the funds to develop the library in this
manner. After working at this library, by the end of 1690 Leibniz was
appointed as privy-councilor and librarian of the Bibliotheca Augusta at
Wolfenbuettel. It was an extensive library with at least 25,946 printed
volumes.
At this library, Leibniz sought to improve the catalog. He was not
allowed to make complete changes to the existing closed catalog, but was
allowed to improve upon it so he started on that task immediately. He
created an alphabetical author catalog and had also created other
cataloging methods that were not implemented. While serving as librarian
of the ducal libraries in Hanover and Wolfenbuettel, Leibniz effectively became one of the founders of library science. He also designed a book indexing system in ignorance of the only other such system then extant, that of the Bodleian Library at Oxford University.
He also called on publishers to distribute abstracts of all new titles
they produced each year, in a standard form that would facilitate
indexing. He hoped that this abstracting project would eventually
include everything printed from his day back to Gutenberg.
Neither proposal met with success at the time, but something like them
became standard practice among English language publishers during the
20th century, under the aegis of the Library of Congress and the British Library.
Leibniz
emphasized that research was a collaborative endeavor. Hence he warmly
advocated the formation of national scientific societies along the lines
of the British Royal Society
and the French Académie Royale des Sciences. More specifically, in his
correspondence and travels he urged the creation of such societies in
Dresden, Saint Petersburg, Vienna, and Berlin. Only one such project came to fruition; in 1700, the Berlin Academy of Sciences
was created. Leibniz drew up its first statutes, and served as its
first President for the remainder of his life. That Academy evolved into
the German Academy of Sciences, the publisher of the ongoing critical
edition of his works.
Lawyer and moralist
With the possible exception of Marcus Aurelius,
no philosopher has ever had as much experience with practical affairs
of state as Leibniz. Leibniz's writings on law, ethics, and politics were long overlooked by English-speaking scholars, but this has changed of late.
While Leibniz was no apologist for absolute monarchy like Hobbes, or for tyranny in any form, neither did he echo the political and constitutional views of his contemporary John Locke,
views invoked in support of liberalism, in 18th-century America and
later elsewhere. The following excerpt from a 1695 letter to Baron J. C.
Boyneburg's son Philipp is very revealing of Leibniz's political
sentiments:
As for ... the great question of the power of sovereigns
and the obedience their peoples owe them, I usually say that it would be
good for princes to be persuaded that their people have the right to
resist them, and for the people, on the other hand, to be persuaded to
obey them passively. I am, however, quite of the opinion of Grotius,
that one ought to obey as a rule, the evil of revolution being greater
beyond comparison than the evils causing it. Yet I recognize that a
prince can go to such excess, and place the well-being of the state in
such danger, that the obligation to endure ceases. This is most rare,
however, and the theologian who authorizes violence under this pretext
should take care against excess; excess being infinitely more dangerous
than deficiency.
In 1677, Leibniz called for a European confederation, governed by a
council or senate, whose members would represent entire nations and
would be free to vote their consciences; this is sometimes considered an anticipation of the European Union. He believed that Europe would adopt a uniform religion. He reiterated these proposals in 1715.
But at the same time, he arrived to propose an interreligious and
multicultural project to create a universal system of justice, which
required from him a broad interdisciplinary perspective. In order to
propose it, he combined linguistics (especially sinology), moral and
legal philosophy, management, economics, and politics.
Ecumenism
Leibniz devoted considerable intellectual and diplomatic effort to what would now be called ecumenical endeavor, seeking to reconcile first the Roman Catholic and Lutheran churches, and later the Lutheran and Reformed churches. In this respect, he followed the example of his early patrons, Baron von Boyneburg and the Duke John Frederick—both
cradle Lutherans who converted to Catholicism as adults—who did what
they could to encourage the reunion of the two faiths, and who warmly
welcomed such endeavors by others. (The House of Brunswick
remained Lutheran, because the Duke's children did not follow their
father.) These efforts included corresponding with French bishop Jacques-Bénigne Bossuet,
and involved Leibniz in some theological controversy. He evidently
thought that the thoroughgoing application of reason would suffice to
heal the breach caused by the Reformation.
Philologist
Leibniz the philologist
was an avid student of languages, eagerly latching on to any
information about vocabulary and grammar that came his way. He refuted
the belief, widely held by Christian scholars in his day, that Hebrew
was the primeval language of the human race. He also refuted the
argument, advanced by Swedish scholars in his day, that a form of proto-Swedish was the ancestor of the Germanic languages. He puzzled over the origins of the Slavic languages and was fascinated by classical Chinese. Leibniz was also an expert in the Sanskrit language.
A diagram of I Ching hexagrams sent to Leibniz from Joachim Bouvet. The Arabic numerals were added by Leibniz.
Leibniz was perhaps the first major European intellectual to take a
close interest in Chinese civilization, which he knew by corresponding
with, and reading other works by, European Christian missionaries posted in China. He apparently read Confucius Sinarum Philosophus in the first year of its publication. He came to the conclusion that Europeans could learn much from the Confucian ethical tradition. He mulled over the possibility that the Chinese characters were an unwitting form of his universal characteristic. He noted with fascination how the I Ching hexagrams correspond to the binary numbers
from 000000 to 111111, and concluded that this mapping was evidence of
major Chinese accomplishments in the sort of philosophical mathematics
he admired.
Leibniz communicated his ideas of the binary system representing
Christianity to the Emperor of China, hoping it would convert him.
Leibniz was the only major Western philosopher of the time who
attempted to accommodate Confucian ideas to prevailing European beliefs.
Leibniz's attraction to Chinese philosophy originates from his perception that Chinese philosophy was similar to his own.
The historian E.R. Hughes suggests that Leibniz's ideas of "simple
substance" and "pre-established harmony" were directly influenced by
Confucianism, pointing to the fact that they were conceived during the
period when he was reading Confucius Sinarum Philosophus.
As polymath
While
making his grand tour of European archives to research the Brunswick
family history that he never completed, Leibniz stopped in Vienna
between May 1688 and February 1689, where he did much legal and
diplomatic work for the Brunswicks. He visited mines, talked with mine
engineers, and tried to negotiate export contracts for lead from the
ducal mines in the Harz mountains. His proposal that the streets of Vienna be lit with lamps burning rapeseed oil was implemented. During a formal audience with the Austrian Emperor
and in subsequent memoranda, he advocated reorganizing the Austrian
economy, reforming the coinage of much of central Europe, negotiating a Concordat between the Habsburgs and the Vatican,
and creating an imperial research library, official archive, and public
insurance fund. He wrote and published an important paper on mechanics.
Leibniz also wrote a short paper, Primae veritates, first published by Louis Couturat in 1903 (pp. 518–523) summarizing his views on metaphysics.
The paper is undated; that he wrote it while in Vienna in 1689 was
determined only in 1999, when the ongoing critical edition finally
published Leibniz's philosophical writings for the period 1677–90. Couturat's reading of this paper was the launching point for much 20th-century thinking about Leibniz, especially among analytic philosophers.
But after a meticulous study of all of Leibniz's philosophical writings
up to 1688—a study the 1999 additions to the critical edition made
possible—Mercer (2001) begged to differ with Couturat's reading; the
jury is still out.
Posthumous reputation
Leibnizstrasse street sign Berlin
When Leibniz died, his reputation was in decline. He was remembered for only one book, the Théodicée, whose supposed central argument Voltaire lampooned in his popular book Candide, which concludes with the character Candide saying, "Non liquet"
(it is not clear), a term that was applied during the Roman Republic to
a legal verdict of "not proven". Voltaire's depiction of Leibniz's
ideas was so influential that many believed it to be an accurate
description. Thus Voltaire and his Candide bear some of the blame for the lingering failure to appreciate and understand Leibniz's ideas. Leibniz had an ardent disciple, Christian Wolff, whose dogmatic and facile outlook did Leibniz's reputation much harm. He also influenced David Hume, who read his Théodicée and used some of his ideas.
In any event, philosophical fashion was moving away from the
rationalism and system building of the 17th century, of which Leibniz
had been such an ardent proponent. His work on law, diplomacy, and
history was seen as of ephemeral interest. The vastness and richness of
his correspondence went unrecognized.
Much of Europe came to doubt that Leibniz had discovered calculus
independently of Newton, and hence his whole work in mathematics and
physics was neglected. Voltaire, an admirer of Newton, also wrote Candide at least in part to discredit Leibniz's claim to having discovered calculus and Leibniz's charge that Newton's theory of universal gravitation was incorrect.
Leibniz's long march to his present glory began with the 1765 publication of the Nouveaux Essais, which Kant read closely. In 1768, Louis Dutens
edited the first multi-volume edition of Leibniz's writings, followed
in the 19th century by a number of editions, including those edited by
Erdmann, Foucher de Careil, Gerhardt, Gerland, Klopp, and Mollat.
Publication of Leibniz's correspondence with notables such as Antoine Arnauld, Samuel Clarke, Sophia of Hanover, and her daughter Sophia Charlotte of Hanover, began.
In 1900, Bertrand Russell published a critical study of Leibniz's metaphysics. Shortly thereafter, Louis Couturat
published an important study of Leibniz, and edited a volume of
Leibniz's heretofore unpublished writings, mainly on logic. They made
Leibniz somewhat respectable among 20th-century analytical and linguistic philosophers in the English-speaking world (Leibniz had already been of great influence to many Germans such as Bernhard Riemann). For example, Leibniz's phrase salva veritate, meaning interchangeability without loss of or compromising the truth, recurs in Willard Quine's
writings. Nevertheless, the secondary literature on Leibniz did not
really blossom until after World War II. This is especially true of
English speaking countries; in Gregory Brown's bibliography fewer than
30 of the English language entries were published before 1946. American
Leibniz studies owe much to Leroy Loemker (1904–1985) through his translations and his interpretive essays in LeClerc (1973).
Nicholas Jolley has surmised that Leibniz's reputation as a philosopher is now perhaps higher than at any time since he was alive. Analytic and contemporary philosophy continue to invoke his notions of identity, individuation, and possible worlds. Work in the history of 17th- and 18th-century ideas has revealed more clearly the 17th-century "Intellectual Revolution" that preceded the better-known Industrial and commercial revolutions of the 18th and 19th centuries.
In 1985, the German government created the Leibniz Prize, offering an annual award of 1.55 million euros
for experimental results and 770,000 euros for theoretical ones. It was
the worlds largest prize for scientific achievement prior to the Fundamental Physics Prize.
The collection of manuscript papers of Leibniz at the Gottfried
Wilhelm Leibniz Bibliothek – Niedersächische Landesbibliothek was
inscribed on UNESCO's Memory of the World Register in 2007.
Writings and publication
Leibniz mainly wrote in three languages: scholastic Latin,
French and German. During his lifetime, he published many pamphlets and
scholarly articles, but only two "philosophical" books, the Combinatorial Art and the Théodicée. (He published numerous pamphlets, often anonymous, on behalf of the House of Brunswick-Lüneburg, most notably the "De jure suprematum" a major consideration of the nature of sovereignty.) One substantial book appeared posthumously, his Nouveaux essais sur l'entendement humain, which Leibniz had withheld from publication after the death of John Locke.
Only in 1895, when Bodemann completed his catalogue of Leibniz's
manuscripts and correspondence, did the enormous extent of Leibniz's Nachlass
become clear: about 15,000 letters to more than 1000 recipients plus
more than 40,000 other items. Moreover, quite a few of these letters are
of essay length. Much of his vast correspondence, especially the
letters dated after 1700, remains unpublished, and much of what is
published has appeared only in recent decades. The amount, variety, and
disorder of Leibniz's writings are a predictable result of a situation
he described in a letter as follows:
I cannot tell you how extraordinarily distracted and
spread out I am. I am trying to find various things in the archives; I
look at old papers and hunt up unpublished documents. From these I hope
to shed some light on the history of the [House of] Brunswick. I receive
and answer a huge number of letters. At the same time, I have so many
mathematical results, philosophical thoughts, and other literary
innovations that should not be allowed to vanish that I often do not
know where to begin.
The extant parts of the critical edition of Leibniz's writings are organized as follows:
Series 1. Political, Historical, and General Correspondence. 25 vols., 1666–1706.
Series 2. Philosophical Correspondence. 3 vols., 1663–1700.
Series 3. Mathematical, Scientific, and Technical Correspondence. 8 vols., 1672–1698.
Series 4. Political Writings. 7 vols., 1667–99.
Series 5. Historical and Linguistic Writings. Inactive.
Series 6. Philosophical Writings. 7 vols., 1663–90, and Nouveaux essais sur l'entendement humain.
Series 7. Mathematical Writings. 6 vols., 1672–76.
Series 8. Scientific, Medical, and Technical Writings. 1 vol., 1668–76.
The systematic cataloguing of all of Leibniz's Nachlass began
in 1901. It was hampered by two world wars and then by decades of German
division into two states with the Cold War's "iron curtain" in between,
separating scholars, and also scattering portions of his literary
estates. The ambitious project has had to deal with writings in seven
languages, contained in some 200,000 written and printed pages. In 1985
it was reorganized and included in a joint program of German federal and
state (Länder) academies. Since then the branches in Potsdam, Münster, Hanover and Berlin have jointly published 57 volumes of the critical edition, with an average of 870 pages, and prepared index and concordance works.
Selected works
The year given is usually that in which the work was completed, not of its eventual publication.
1666 (publ. 1690). De Arte Combinatoria (On the Art of Combination); partially translated in Loemker §1 and Parkinson (1966)
1667. Nova Methodus Discendae Docendaeque Iurisprudentiae (A New Method for Learning and Teaching Jurisprudence).
1667. Dialogus de connexione inter res et verba.
1671. Hypothesis Physica Nova (New Physical Hypothesis); Loemker §8.I (part).
Oct. 1684. "Meditationes de cognitione, veritate et ideis" ("Meditations on Knowledge, Truth, and Ideas")
Nov. 1684. "Nova methodus pro maximis et minimis" ("New method for maximums and minimums"); translated in Struik, D. J., 1969. A Source Book in Mathematics, 1200–1800. Harvard University Press: 271–81.
1686. Discours de métaphysique;
Martin and Brown (1988), Ariew and Garber 35, Loemker §35, Wiener
III.3, Woolhouse and Francks 1. An online translation by Jonathan
Bennett is available.
1686. Generales inquisitiones de analysi notionum et veritatum (General Inquiries About the Analysis of Concepts and of Truths)
1695. Système nouveau de la nature et de la communication des substances (New System of Nature)
1700. Accessiones historicae
1703. Explication de l'Arithmétique Binaire (Explanation of Binary Arithmetic); Gerhardt, Mathematical Writings VII.223. An online translation by Lloyd Strickland is available.
1704 (publ. 1765). Nouveaux essais sur l'entendement humain. Translated in: Remnant, Peter, and Bennett, Jonathan, trans., 1996. New Essays on Human Understanding
Langley translation 1896. Cambridge University Press. Wiener III.6
(part). An online translation of the Preface and Book I by Jonathan
Bennett is available.
1707–1710. Scriptores rerum Brunsvicensium (3 Vols.)
1710. Théodicée; Farrer, A.M., and Huggard, E.M., trans., 1985 (1952). Wiener III.11 (part). An online translation is available at Project Gutenberg.
1714. Principes de la nature et de la Grâce fondés en raison
Six
important collections of English translations are Wiener (1951),
Parkinson (1966), Loemker (1969), Ariew and Garber (1989), Woolhouse and
Francks (1998), and Strickland (2006). The ongoing critical edition of
all of Leibniz's writings is Sämtliche Schriften und Briefe.
Leibniz in popular media
Leibniz is receiving popular attention. The Google Doodle for July 1, 2018 celebrated Leibniz's 372nd birthday. Using a quill, his hand is shown writing "Google" in binary ASCII code.
One of the earliest popular but indirect expositions of Leibniz was Voltaire's satire Candide, published in 1759. Leibniz was lampooned as Professor Pangloss, described as "the greatest philosopher of the Holy Roman Empire".
Leibniz also appears as one of the main historical figures in Neal Stephenson's series of novels The Baroque Cycle. Stephenson credits readings and discussions concerning Leibniz for inspiring him to write the series.
Leibniz also stars in Adam Ehrlich Sach's novel The Organs of Sense.