From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
Baruch Spinoza's philosophy encompasses nearly every area of philosophical discourse, including metaphysics, epistemology, political philosophy, ethics, philosophy of mind, and philosophy of science. It earned Spinoza an enduring reputation as one of the most important and original thinkers of the seventeenth century.
Samuel Shirley, who translated Spinoza's complete works into
English, summed up the significance of Spinoza's philosophy as follows:
To my mind, although Spinoza lived
and thought long before Darwin, Freud, Einstein, and the startling
implications of quantum theory, he had a vision of truth beyond what is
normally granted to human beings.
Spinoza's philosophy is largely contained in two books: the Theologico-Political Treatise, and the Ethics.
The former was published during his lifetime, but the latter, which
contains the entirety of his philosophical system in its most rigorous
form, was not published until after his death in 1677. The rest of the
writings we have from Spinoza are either earlier, or incomplete, works
expressing thoughts that were crystallized in the two aforementioned
books (e.g., the Short Treatise and the Treatise on the Emendation of the Intellect), or else they are not directly concerned with Spinoza's own philosophy (e.g., The Principles of Cartesian Philosophy and The Hebrew Grammar).
He also left behind many letters that help to illuminate his ideas and
provide some insight into what may have been motivating his views.
Philosophy of religion
Spinoza's philosophy of religion is largely contained in the Theologico-Political Treatise.
In that work he argues for the view that we should interpret scripture
solely on its own terms by carefully studying it, not with any concepts
or doctrines that cannot themselves be derived from the text. If we do
this, he thought, it would turn out that many things we believe or are
told by religious authorities about God and the universe could be shown
to be false (e.g., miracles).
Spinoza's view is exemplified in the following sentence from the Preface to the Theological Political Treatise:
[It] is further evident from the
fact that most of them assume as a basic principle for the understanding
of Scripture and for extracting its true meaning that it is throughout
truthful and divine--a conclusion which ought to be the end result of
study and strict examination; and they lay down at the outset as a
principle of interpretation that which would be far more properly
derived from Scripture itself, which stands in no need of human
fabrications.
Ontological argument
In Spinoza’s Ethics,
he wrote a section titled “Treating of God and What Pertains to Him,”
in which he discusses God’s existence and what God is. He starts off by
saying: “whether there is a God, this, we say, can be proved”.
His proof for God follows a similar structure as Descartes’ ontological
argument. Descartes attempts to prove God’s existence by arguing that
there “must be some one thing that is supremely good, through which all
good things have their goodness”.
Spinoza’s argument differs in that he does not move straight from the
conceivability of the greatest being to the existence of God, but rather
uses a deductive argument from the idea of God. Spinoza says that man’s
ideas do not come from himself, but from some sort of external cause.
Thus the things whose characteristics a man knows must have come from
some prior source. So, if man has the idea of God, then God must exist
before this thought, because man cannot create an idea of his own
imagination.
Substance of God
After stating his proof for God’s existence, Spinoza addresses who
“God” is. Spinoza believed that God is “the sum of the natural and
physical laws of the universe and certainly not an individual entity or
creator”.
Spinoza attempts to prove that God is just the substance of the
universe by first stating that substances do not share attributes or
essences, and then demonstrating that God is a “substance” with an
infinite number of attributes, thus the attributes possessed by any
other substances must also be possessed by God. Therefore, God is just
the sum of all the substances of the universe.
God is the only substance in the universe, and everything is a part of
God. “Whatever is, is in God, and nothing can be or be conceived without
God”. This concept of God is very similar to the Advaita Vedanta of Hinduism. This view was described by Charles Hartshorne as Classical Pantheism. Spinoza has also been described as an "Epicurean materialist",
specifically in reference to his opposition to Cartesian mind-body
dualism. This view was held by Epicureans before him, as they believed
that atoms with their probabilistic paths were the only substance that
existed fundamentally.
Spinoza, however, deviated significantly from Epicureans by adhering to
strict determinism, much like the Stoics before him, in contrast to the
Epicurean belief in the probabilistic path of atoms, which is more in
line with contemporary thought on quantum mechanics.
Political philosophy
Tractatus Theologico-Politicus was published anonymously.
Spinoza's political philosophy is deeply influenced by both the
turbulent time period in which he lived, and by the fact that he
happened to live in a comparatively liberal place in Europe, which
allowed him freedoms he wished to preserve and defend, as he says in the
Preface to the Theological Political Treatise:
Now since we have the rare good
fortune to live in a commonwealth where freedom of judgment is fully
granted to the individual citizen and he may worship God as he pleases,
and where nothing is esteemed dearer and more precious than freedom, I
think I am undertaking no ungrateful or unprofitable task in
demonstrating that not only can this freedom be granted without
endangering piety and the peace of the commonwealth, but also the peace
of the commonwealth and piety depend on this freedom.
Spinoza's political philosophy is scattered in three books, the Theologico-political Treatise, the Ethics and the Political Treatise.
A first look at its main principles could bring the uninformed reader
to believe that it is the same as Hobbes's. Yet both theories differ in
their conclusions. Spinoza's political philosophy is also a philosophy
of the conatus, the individual tendency to exist, which cannot be
brought to extinction even in the most powerful Leviathan, even in the
worst of authoritarian regimes. Every individual, in Spinoza's opinion,
has a natural right. This right includes everything that he desires and
he is able to obtain. As a result, my own natural right is the
equivalent of my individual strength or power.
Hence, in Spinoza's political philosophy subjective rights (e.g. human
rights) do not exist by nature, they are an institution of society, they
only exist in the civil state. Moreover, according to Spinoza the
notions of right and wrong have no meaning before society, since in the
natural state there are no common norms, only individual desires
(desires which can bring some people to dominate other weaker people).
How can civil society exist if people are only dominated by their
own impulse to live? Through many ways. First, through the action of
affections, the same ones that are described in the Ethics.
Those affections, my feelings, will bring me to cluster, to gather with
people similar to myself: this similarity reinforces the feeling or
representation of my own existence. In a similar fashion, human needs
will also play a role: society, through distribution and specialisation
of each task, can provide more goods than I can generate myself and with
less effort. This is why the sciences and the arts can only develop in
societies, where there is time to attend to things other than one's own
survival.
This fear, the need to constantly look after danger and threats and to
live in constant tension, is the third cause or root phenomenon of
society. Society brings me protection and security. We see hence that
Spinoza, while incorporating in his work Hobbesian arguments (the
argument of fear), develops a distinct analysis that will bring him to
different conclusions: the need of a free society.
Here individuals never entirely renounce their individual right
of nature. If in the Theologico-Political Treatise Spinoza refers to the
notion of a pact that would be at the root of civil society, this
notion disappears in the Political Treatise. People are not brought to
form a society by their free will, but rather by their affections, or
domination (a great number of individuals gathered through the authority
of an unusually strong or charismatic man could also be a way to
explain the birth of civil society). They are not passive subjects under
the power of an absolute sovereign, but rather citizens that bring
their own strength to the State. The power of the state exists in
Spinoza's opinion only through the gathering of individual powers,
powers which the society incorporates and can even develop if its
political institutions are well designed.
"Well designed" means that they must induce political leaders to act
according to the rules, by their own will. In Spinoza's political
philosophy, state is not opposed to the society but it is the apparatus
that gives a certain form or existence to the society, to a gathering of
human beings. It is not transcendent to it, as it is in Hobbes's philosophy.
These affirmations have some political implications. Here,
individual rights exist only because we, as individuals, benefit from
the power of our entire group. Members' rights are guaranteed by the
strength of their political group (=State or imperium). Individual or
subjective rights do not exist outside of a state, out of an organised
society. But that doesn't mean that the government should have absolute
power over us. To understand that well, we have to remember that
according to Spinoza the government or society (there is no difference
between them) are nothing else and do not exist without the individual
conatuses of the individuals that are gathered in social entities.
Individuals hold a part of their natural right in the civil state. They
cannot restrain themselves from judging about the state of things as
they wish, and any action that would go against this tendency can induce
social unrest. It follows that the state must restrain itself from any
action that could jeopardise its own integrity, as condemning
determinate opinions can.
In a broader perspective, a state that relies on fearsome and inhuman
ways to preserve its power cannot survive for long, since those ways
impede the development of its own strength, and reinforce the tendency
of the multitudo, the masses, to unrest or to disobedience: obedience is necessary to preserve social order and peace.
Thus, we can distinguish Hobbes and Spinoza through the way they
see the normal operation of the state. For Hobbes, the object of the
state is to preserve peace through security and fear if needed.
According to Spinoza, that kind of peace would not be a true peace but
only the absence of unrest. True peace implies a state of things where
individuals can accomplish and realise their potentialities, where there
is a minimum peace of mind. This is why Spinoza favors states that are
organised so that citizens can participate in the elaboration of laws,
as a way to improve their quality, and in the operation of the state.
The vocabulary of Spinoza shows a modification of the way philosophers see politics compared to the Antiquity.
In Plato's and Aristotle's works good politics imply good government
(defined as the way decisions are taken in a certain political
community), in the sense that the different types of government can be
ranked according to their virtues (aristocracy is better than democracy,
which is better than oligarchy and tyranny according to Plato, and so
on). Spinoza goes beyond this way of seeing things. There is not a
better government in this sense: the better government is the government
that the people of a certain country have been accustomed to, and there
is no good in changing it: such a change alters the balance of power
already in place and can bring unrest, conflict between opposed or
entrenched interests. According to him, one should rather aim to design
better institutions: for type of regime or government (Monarchy,
Aristocracy, Democracy) Spinoza implements the outlines of what should
be the good institutions for this regime. For example, in Monarchy there
should be an official Council of the king, whose members are chosen
formally, and whose opinions form a set of possible decisions for the
king.
This is a way of avoiding the issue of the king's secret counselors or
ministers, who have a lot of influence on the king and often are the
true decision takers. This system makes public and transparent through a
formal process a matter of fact, the existence of a circle of advisers
around the king.
For further reference, see Spinoza's Political Philosophy.
Philosophy of mind/psychology
The human mind
Spinoza argues for a distinct conception of the human mind in Part Two of The Ethics. He says the following:
The first thing that constitutes
the actual being of a human Mind is nothing but the idea of a singular
thing which actually exists.(E2P11)
He then argues that it follows that "the human Mind is a part of the infinite intellect of God."(E2P11c)
Further, Spinoza says: "Whatever happens in the object of the idea
constituting the human Mind must be perceived by the human Mind"(E2P12)
From this we get a clear rejection of Descartes' mind/body dualism:
"The object of the idea constituting the human Mind is the Body, or a
certain mode of Extension which actually exists, and nothing
else."(E2P13)
The emotions
One thing which seems, on the surface, to distinguish Spinoza's view of the emotions from both Descartes' and Hume's pictures of them is that he takes the emotions to be cognitive
in some important respect. Jonathan Bennett claims that "Spinoza mainly
saw emotions as caused by cognitions. [However] he did not say this
clearly enough and sometimes lost sight of it entirely."
Spinoza provides several demonstrations which purport to show truths
about how human emotions work. The picture presented is, according to
Bennett, "unflattering, coloured as it is by universal egoism"
Spinoza's treatment of the emotions in Part Three of The Ethics,
"On the Origin and Nature of the Affects", utilizes a broad set of
terminology, clearly intended to cover the whole of human experience. He
tells us in the Preface:
The Affects, therefore, of hate,
anger, envy, etc., considered in themselves, follow from the same
necessity and force of nature as any other singular things. And
therefore they acknowledge certain causes, through which they are
understood, and have certain properties, as worthy of our knowledge as
the properties of any other thing, by the mere contemplation of which we
are pleased.
Human freedom
Whether
there is any meaningful kind of freedom which humans may genuinely have
is, in Spinoza's picture, at least contentious. He certainly claims
that there is a kind of freedom, namely, that which is arrived at
through adequate knowledge of God, or, what is the same: the universe.
But in the last two propositions of Part Two of The Ethics, P48 and P49, he explicitly rejects the traditional notion of free will. In E2P48, he claims:
In the Mind there is no absolute,
or free, will, but the Mind is determined to will this or that by a
cause which is also determined by another, and this again by another,
and so to infinity.
So from this we get a strong sense of Spinoza's metaphysical naturalism,
that is, that the natural and human orders are contiguous. With that
being the case, human freedom of a kind which would extricate us from
the order of physical causes is impossible. However, Spinoza argues, we
still ought to strive to understand the world around us, and in doing
so, gain a greater degree of power, which will allow us to be more active than passive, and there is a sense in which this is a kind of freedom.
For more, see: Stanford.edu
Metaphysics
Spinoza's metaphysics consists of one thing, substance, and its modifications (modes). Early in The Ethics Spinoza argues that there is only one substance, which is absolutely infinite, self-caused, and eternal. He calls this substance "God", or "Nature". In fact, he takes these two terms to be synonymous (in the Latin the phrase he uses is "Deus sive Natura"). For Spinoza the whole of the natural universe is made of one substance, God, or, what's the same, Nature, and its modifications (modes).
It cannot be overemphasized how the
rest of Spinoza's philosophy—his philosophy of mind, his epistemology,
his psychology, his moral philosophy, his political philosophy, and his
philosophy of religion—flows more or less directly from the metaphysical
underpinnings in Part I of the Ethics.
Substance
Spinoza defines "substance" as follows:
By substance I understand what is in itself and is conceived through itself, i.e., that whose concept does not require the concept of another thing, from which it must be formed.(E1D3)
This means, essentially, that substance is just whatever can be
thought of without relating it to any other idea or thing. For example,
if one thinks of a particular object, one thinks of it as a kind of thing, e.g., x
is a cat. Substance, on the other hand, is to be conceived of by
itself, without understanding it as a particular kind of thing (because
it isn't a particular thing at all).
Attributes
Spinoza defines "attribute" as follows:
By attribute I understand what the intellect perceives of a substance, as constituting its essence.(E1D4)
From this it can be seen that attributes are related to substance in
some way. It is not clear, however, even from Spinoza's direct
definition, whether, a) attributes are really the way(s) substance is,
or b) attributes are simply ways to understand substance, but not
necessarily the ways it really is.
Spinoza thinks that there are an infinite number of attributes, but there are two attributes for which Spinoza thinks we can have knowledge. Namely, thought and extension.
Thought
The
attribute of thought is how substance can be understood to give rise to
thoughts, or thinking things. When we understand a particular thing in
the universe through the attribute of thought, we are understanding the
mode as an idea of something (either another idea, or an object).
Extension
The
attribute of extension is how substance can be understood to be
physically extended in space. Particular things which have breadth and
depth (that is, occupy space) are what is meant by extended. It follows from
this that if substance and God are identical, on Spinoza's view, and
contrary to the traditional conception, God has extension as one of His
attributes.
Modes
Modes are particular modifications of substance, i.e., particular things in the world. Spinoza gives the following definition:
By mode I understand the affections of a substance, or that which is in another through which it is also conceived.(E1D5)
Substance monism
The argument for there only being one substance in the universe occurs in the first fourteen propositions of The Ethics. The following proposition expresses Spinoza's commitment to substance monism:
Except God, no substance can be or be conceived.(E1P14)
Spinoza takes this proposition to follow directly from everything he says prior to it. Spinoza's monism is contrasted with Descartes' dualism and Leibniz's pluralism. It allows Spinoza to avoid the problem of interaction between mind and body, which troubled Descartes in his Meditations on First Philosophy.
Causality and modality
The issue of causality and modality (possibility and necessity) in Spinoza's philosophy is contentious. Spinoza's philosophy is, in one sense, thoroughly deterministic (or necessitarian). This can be seen directly from Axiom 3 of The Ethics:
From a given determinate cause the
effect follows necessarily; and conversely, if there is no determinate
cause, it is impossible for an effect to follow.(E1A3)
Yet Spinoza seems to make room for a kind of freedom, especially in the fifth and final section of The Ethics, "On the Power of the Intellect, or on Human Freedom":
I pass, finally, to the remaining
Part of the Ethics, which concerns the means or way, leading to Freedom.
Here, then, I shall treat of the power of reason, showing what it can
do against the affects, and what Freedom of Mind, or blessedness,
is.(E5, Preface)
So Spinoza certainly has a use for the word 'freedom', but he equates
"Freedom of Mind" with "blessedness", a notion which is not
traditionally associated with freedom of the will at all.
The principle of sufficient reason (PSR)
Though the PSR is most commonly associated with Gottfried Leibniz, it is arguably found in its strongest form in Spinoza's philosophy.
Within the context of Spinoza's philosophical system, the PSR can be understood to unify causation and explanation. What this means is that for Spinoza, questions regarding the reason
why a given phenomenon is the way it is (or exists) are always
answerable, and are always answerable in terms of the relevant cause(s).
This constitutes a rejection of teleological, or final causation, except possibly in a more restricted sense for human beings. Given this, Spinoza's views regarding causality and modality begin to make much more sense.
Parallelism
Spinoza's
philosophy contains as a key proposition the notion that mental and
physical (thought and extension) phenomena occur in parallel, but
without causal interaction between them. He expresses this proposition
as follows:
The order and connection of ideas is the same as the order and connection of things.(E2P7)
His proof of this proposition is that:
The knowledge of an effect depends on, and involves, the knowledge of its cause.(E1A4)
The reason Spinoza thinks the parallelism
follows from this axiom is that since the idea we have of each thing
requires knowledge of its cause, this cause must be understood under the
same attribute. Further, there is only one substance, so whenever we
understand some chain of ideas of things, we understand that the way the
ideas are causally related must be the same as the way the things
themselves are related, since the ideas and the things are the same
modes understood under different attributes.
Epistemology
Spinoza's epistemology is deeply rationalist. That is, unlike the empiricists
who rejected knowledge of things as they are in themselves (in favour
of knowledge merely of what appears to the senses), to think we can have
a priori knowledge, knowledge of a world external from our sense perceptions, and, further, that this is tantamount to knowledge of God. The majority of Spinoza's epistemological claims come in Part Two of The Ethics.
Truth and falsity
Spinoza's notions of truth and falsity have to do with the relation between ideas and their objects. He thinks that:
Every idea that in us is absolute, or adequate and perfect, is true. (E2P34)
Falsity consists in the privation of knowledge which inadequate, or mutilated and confused, ideas involve.(E2P35)
Adequate and inadequate ideas
From
this it is clear that the notions of adequate and inadequate ideas are
important for understanding how Spinoza's view works. This may be
explained in the following way. Spinoza argues that "All ideas, insofar
as they are related to God, are true."(E2P32)
Since by "God", he means the one substance which exists necessarily and
absolutely infinitely, it follows that an idea as it is with no
reference to knowledge a particular person has, is necessarily true, since it just is a particular instance of God. (E2P32)
On the other hand, Spinoza argues: "All ideas are in God; and,
insofar as they are related to God, are true, and adequate. And so there
are no inadequate or confused ideas except insofar as they are related
to the singular Mind of someone."(E2P36d).
That is, even though ideas considered objectively as elements of the
universe are always adequate (meaning their relation to their object is
total), when a particular individual has an idea of something, such an
idea is necessarily incomplete, and therefore, inadequate. This is the
source of falsehood.
Three kinds of knowledge
Spinoza discusses the three kinds of knowledge in E2P40s2.
The first kind of knowledge
Spinoza thinks there are two ways we can have the first kind of knowledge:
- From random experience: "from singular things which have
been represented to us through the senses in a way that is mutilated,
confused, and without order for the intellect; for that reasons I have
been accustomed to call such perceptions knowledge from random
experience."
- From imagination: "from signs, e.g., from the fact
that, having heard or read certain words, we recollect things, and form
certain ideas of them, which are like them, and through which we imagine
the things."
He calls these two ways "knowledge of the first kind, opinion or imagination."
The second kind of knowledge
Spinoza argues that the second kind of knowledge arises:
from the fact that we have common notions and adequate ideas of the properties of things."
He goes on to explain what this means in the propositions which immediately follow.
The third kind of knowledge
This can be referred to as Intuition,
but it means something rather technical for Spinoza. The third kind of
knowledge is a particularly important part of Spinoza's philosophy
because it is what he thinks allows us to have adequate knowledge, and
therefore know things absolutely truly. As he says:
there
is (as I shall show in what follows) another, third kind, which we
shall call intuitive knowledge. And this kind of knowing proceeds from
an adequate idea of certain attributes of God to the adequate knowledge
of the essence of things.
Ethics
The opening page of Spinoza's magnum opus, Ethics
Spinoza's ethical views are deeply tied to his metaphysical system. This is evident from the following claim:
As far as good and evil are
concerned, they also indicate nothing positive in things, considered in
themselves, nor are they anything other than modes of thinking, or
notions we form because we compare things to one another.(E4, Preface)
It is also apparent from this that he is a kind of subjectivist about moral values.
That is, he does not take good and evil to be real properties/facts in
the objects we attribute them to, but rather, they are simply thoughts
we have about the comparative value of one thing to another for a
particular person.
"Good" and "Evil"
Spinoza gives the following definitions of "Good", and "Evil":
By good I shall understand what we certainly know to be useful to us.(E4D1)
By evil, however, I shall understand what we certainly know prevents us from being masters of some good.(E4D2)
From this it is clear that Spinoza's view of moral value is in some
sense instrumental. That is, the goodness or badness of a particular
object or action is measured not by some essential property. The
emphasis on "essential knowledge" is important, given Spinoza's view of
what epistemic certainty amounts to, i.e., adequate knowledge of God (a notion which is briefly elaborated on in this article).
Blessedness
Spinoza's notion of blessedness figures centrally in his ethical philosophy.
Blessedness (or salvation or freedom), Spinoza thinks,
consists...in a constant and eternal love of God, or in God's love for men.(E5P36s)
And this means, as Jonathan Bennett explains, that "Spinoza wants
"blessedness" to stand for the most elevated and desirable state one
could possibly be in." Here, understanding what is meant by 'most elevated and desirable state' requires understanding Spinoza's notion of conatus (read: striving, but not necessarily with any teleological
baggage) and that "perfection" refers not to (moral) value, but to
completeness. Given that individuals are identified as mere
modifications of the infinite Substance, it follows that no individual
can ever be fully complete, i.e., perfect, or blessed. Absolute
perfection, is, as noted above, reserved solely for Substance.
Nevertheless, mere modes can attain a lesser form of blessedness,
namely, that of pure understanding of oneself as one really is, i.e., as
a definite modification of Substance in a certain set of relationships
with everything else in the universe. That this is what Spinoza has in
mind can be seen at the end of the Ethics, in E5P24 and E5P25,
wherein Spinoza makes two final key moves, unifying the metaphysical,
epistemological, and ethical propositions he has developed over the
course of the work. In E5P24, he links the understanding of particular
things to the understanding of God, or Substance; in E5P25, the conatus of the mind is linked to the third kind of knowledge (Intuition). From here, it is a short step to the connection of Blessedness with the amor dei intellectualis ("intellectual love of God").