From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
Economic democracy (sometimes called a
democratic economy[) is a
socioeconomic philosophy that proposes to shift ownership and decision-making power from
corporate shareholders and
corporate managers (such as a
board of directors) to a larger group of
public stakeholders
that includes workers, consumers, suppliers, communities and the
broader public. No single definition or approach encompasses economic
democracy, but most proponents claim that modern property relations
externalize
costs, subordinate the general well-being to private profit and deny
the polity a democratic voice in economic policy decisions. In addition to these moral concerns, economic democracy makes practical claims, such as that it can compensate for
capitalism's inherent
effective demand gap.
Proponents of economic democracy generally argue that modern
capitalism periodically results in economic crises, characterized by deficiency of effective demand; as society is unable to earn enough income to purchase its own production output. Corporate monopoly of common resources typically creates artificial scarcity, resulting in socio-economic imbalances that restrict workers from access to economic opportunity and diminish consumer purchasing power.
Economic democracy has been proposed as a component of larger
socioeconomic ideologies, as a stand-alone theory and as a variety of
reform agendas. For example, as a means to securing full economic rights, it opens a path to full political rights, defined as including the former.
Both market and non-market theories of economic democracy have been
proposed. As a reform agenda, supporting theories and real-world
examples can include decentralization, democratic cooperatives, public banking, fair trade and the regionalization of food production and currency.
Deficiency of effective demand
According
to many analysts, deficiency of effective demand is the most
fundamental economic problem. That is, modern society does not earn
enough income to purchase its output. For example, economic geographer David Harvey
claims, "Workers spending their wages is one source of effective
demand, but the total wage bill is always less than the total capital in
circulation (otherwise there would be no profit), so the purchase of
wage goods that sustain daily life (even with a suburban lifestyle) is
never sufficient for the profitable sale of the total output".
In the Georgist view of any economic system, "wealth" includes all material things produced by labor for the satisfaction of human desires and having exchange value. Land, labor
and capital are generally considered the essential factors in producing
wealth. Land includes all natural opportunities and forces. Labor
includes all human exertion. Capital
includes the portion of wealth devoted to producing more wealth. While
the income of any individual might include proceeds from any combination
of these three sources—land, labor and capital are generally considered
mutually exclusive factors in economic models of the production and
distribution of wealth. According to Henry George: "People seek to satisfy their desires with the least exertion". Human beings interact with nature to produce goods and services that other human beings need or desire. The laws and customs that govern the relationships among these entities constitute the economic structure of a given society.
Alternately, David Schweickart asserts in his book, After Capitalism: "The structure of a capitalist society consists of three basic components:
- "The bulk of the means of production are privately owned, either directly by individuals or by corporations that are themselves owned by private individuals.
- "Products are exchanged in a market -- that is to say, goods and
services are bought and sold at prices determined for the most part by
competition and not by some governmental pricing authority. Individual
enterprises compete with one another in providing goods and services to
consumers, each enterprise trying to make a profit. This competition is
the primary determinant of prices.
- "Most of the people who work for pay in this society work for other
people, who own the means of production. Most working people are 'wage labourers'".
Supply and demand are generally accepted as market functions for establishing prices. Organisations typically endeavor to 1) minimize the cost of production;
2) increase sales; in order to 3) maximize profits. But, according to
David Schweickart, if "those who produce the goods and services of
society are paid less than their productive contribution", then as
consumers they cannot buy all the goods produced, and investor
confidence tends to decline, triggering declines in production and
employment. Such economic instability stems from a central
contradiction: Wages are both a cost of production and an essential
source of effective demand (needs or desires backed with purchasing power), resulting in deficiency of effective demand along with a growing interest in economic democracy.
In chapter 3 of his book, "Community Organizing: Theory and Practice", Douglas P. Biklen
discusses a variety of perspectives on "The Making of Social Problems".
One of those views suggests that "writers and organizers who define
social problems in terms of social and economic democracy see problems
not as the experiences of poor people, but as the relationship of
poverty to wealth and exploitation". Biklen states that according to
this viewpoint:
[C]orporate power, upper class
power, uneven distribution of wealth and prejudice cause social
problems... [T]he problem is not one of poverty, but of enormous wealth.
The problem is not one of gaps or cracks in an otherwise fine system
but of a system which perpetuates prejudicial views concerning race,
sex, age, and disability. The problem is not one of incompetence but of
barriers to education, jobs, and power. Accordingly, as long as there is
a deep gulf between social classes, both in terms of wealth, power, and
outlook, traditional social programs will act merely as palliatives to
oppression and not as a way of ending large scale human misery. This
perspective is, above all, eclectic. It embraces Marx's criticism of
social class inequality but is not only a social class analysis. It is
anti-racist, but it is not only a theory of race equality. It favors
democratic distribution of power but is also an economic theory. It can
be called a social and economic democracy perspective.
Savings, investment and unemployment
In his 1879 book Progress and Poverty, Henry George argued that a majority of wealth created in a "free market" economy was appropriated by land owners and monopolists through economic rents, and that concentration of such unearned wealth was the root cause of poverty.
"Behind the abstraction known as 'the market' lurks a set of
institutions designed to maximize the wealth and power of the most
privileged group of people in the world—the creditor-rentier class of the first world and their junior partners in the third".
Schweickart claimed that private savings are not only unnecessary for
economic growth, they are often harmful to the overall economy.
In an advanced industrial society, business credit is necessary
for a healthy economy. A business that wants to expand production needs
to command the labor of others, and money is the default mechanism for
exercising this authority. It is often cheaper for a business to borrow capital from a bank than to stockpile cash.
If private savings are loaned out to entrepreneurs who use them
to buy raw materials and hire workers, then aggregate demand is not
reduced.
However, when private savings are not reinvested, the whole economy
suffers recession, unemployment, and disappearance of savings which characterize deficiency of effective demand.
In this view, unemployment is not an aberration, indicating any
sort of systemic malfunction. Rather, unemployment is a necessary
structural feature of capitalism, intended to discipline the workforce.
If unemployment is too low, workers make wage demands that either cut
into profits to an extent that jeopardizes future investment, or are
passed on to consumers, thus generating inflationary instability.
Schweickart suggested, "Capitalism cannot be a full-employment economy,
except in the very short term. For unemployment is the "invisible hand"—carrying a stick—that keeps the workforce in line." In this view, Adam Smith's "invisible hand" does not seem reliable to guide economic forces on a large scale.
Assuming business credit could come from public sources rather
than from private savers, Schweickart and other analysts consider
interest payments to private savers both undeserved and unnecessary for
economic growth. Moreover, the personal decision to save rather than
consume decreases aggregate demand, increases the likelihood of
unemployment, and exacerbates the tendency toward economic stagnation.
Since wealthy people tend to save more than poor people, the propensity
of an economy to slump because of excess saving becomes ever more acute
as a society becomes more affluent.
Richard Wilkinson and Kate Pickett suggested that health and social
problems are significantly worse in more unequal wealthy nations.
They argue that there are "pernicious effects that inequality has on
societies: eroding trust, increasing anxiety and illness, (and)
encouraging excessive consumption"
Monopoly power versus purchasing power
Regarding a social and economic democracy perspective on social problems, Douglas P. Biklen states:
The theme of profit superseding
individual well-being flows through this antimonopoly view of social
problems. On the one hand, poor and middle income people find their
lives deformed by their meager or nonexistent ability to pay for goods
and services. Wealthy people, on the other hand, find that their
relative position, in terms of wealth and power, grows with their
ability to maintain the gulf between social classes. Thus monopolies or
concentrated wealth plays a large part in creating social problems.
Indeed, one might say, monopolies and policies which promote the former
or concentrations of wealth are the problem.
The discipline of economics is largely a study of scarcity
management; "the science which studies human behavior as a relationship
between ends and scarce means which have alternative uses". Absent scarcity and alternative uses of available resources, many analysts claim there is no economic problem".
While he considers these functions a public wrong, Kellogg also asserted
the responsibility of the public to find and implement a remedy.
Generally considered monopoly power, some view this "public wrong" as the most influential factor in artificial scarcity. For example, Henry George further suggested:
There is in reality no conflict
between labor and capital; the true conflict is between labor and
monopoly... Abolish the monopoly that forbids men to employ themselves
and capital could not possibly oppress labor... [R]emove the cause of
that injustice which deprives the laborer of the capital his toil
creates and the sharp distinction between capitalist and laborer would,
in fact, cease to exist.
For example, many analysts consider invention
a "more or less costless store of knowledge, captured by monopoly
capital and protected in order to make it secret and a 'rare and scarce
commodity', for sale at monopoly prices. So far as invention is
concerned, a price is put on them not because they are scarce but in
order to make them scarce to those who want to use them."
Patent monopolies raise share prices above tangible labor value. The
difference between labor-value and monopoly-value raises goods prices,
and is collected as "profit" by intermediaries who have contributed
nothing to earn it.
Analysts generally agree that such conditions typically result in
a deficiency of effective demand. Labor does not earn enough to buy
what enterprises produce. According to Jack Rasmus, author of The Trillion Dollar Income Shift,
in June 2006, investment bank Goldman Sachs reported: "The most
important contribution to the higher profit margins over the past five
years has been a decline in Labor's share of national income."
Enclosure of the commons
Artificially restricted access of labor to common resources is generally considered monopoly or enclosure of the commons.
Due to the economic imbalance inherently imposed, such monopoly
structures tend to be centrally dictated by law, and must be maintained
by military force, trade agreements, or both.
In 1911, American journalist Ambrose Bierce defined "land" as:
A part of the earth's surface,
considered as property. The theory that land is property subject to
private ownership and control is the foundation of modern society....
Carried to its logical conclusion, it means that some have the right to
prevent others from living; for the right to own implies the right
exclusively to occupy; and in fact laws of trespass are enacted wherever
property in land is recognized. It follows that if the whole area of
terra firma is owned by A, B and C, there will be no place for D, E, F
and G to be born, or, born as trespassers, to exist.
In The Servile State (1912), Hilaire Belloc referred to the Enclosures Movement when he said, "England was already captured by a wealthy oligarchy before the series of great industrial
discoveries began". If you sought the accumulated wealth preliminary to
launching new industry, "you had to turn to the class which had already
monopolized the bulk of the means of production in England. The rich
men alone could furnish you with those supplies".
According to Peter Barnes, author of Capitalism 3.0, when Adam Smith wrote The Wealth of Nations
in 1776, the dominant form of business was partnership, in which
regional groups of co-workers ran co-owned businesses. From this
perspective, many considered the corporate model—stock sold to
strangers—inherently prone to fraud. While numerous scandals
historically support this dim view of corporate policy, small
partnerships could not possibly compete with the aggregate capital
generated by corporate economies of scale.
The greatest advantage of corporations over any other business model is
their ability to raise capital from strangers. The corporate model
benefits from laws that limit stockholders' liability to the amounts
they have invested.
In A Preface To Economic Democracy, Robert A. Dahl suggests that agrarian economy and society in the early United States "underwent a revolutionary transformation into a new system of commercial and industrial capitalism that automatically generated vast inequalities of wealth, income, status, and power." Dahl claims that such inequalities result from the "liberty to accumulate unlimited economic resources and to organize economic activity into hierarchically governed enterprises."
The rise of corporations and ending labor shortage
According
to author Greg MacLeod, the concept of the corporation originated in
Roman times. However, "the modern business corporation evolved radically
from its ancient roots into a form with little relation to the purpose
as understood by historians of law." John Davis, a legal historian,
noted that the precursor of the business corporation was the first monastery,
established in the sixth century, the purpose of which was to serve
society. Most business corporations before 1900 developed in Great
Britain, where they were established by royal charter,
with the expectation of contributions to society. Incorporation was a
privilege granted in return for service to the crown or the nation.
MacLeod goes on to say:
A corporation is considered by the law to exist as a legal person. In the Middle Ages
it was called a "persona ficta". This is a very useful way of looking
at a business corporation, because it suggests correctly that the corporate person
has a certain personality. It has duties and responsibilities vested
unto it by the legitimate government or society that fostered it. The
corporate person receives great benefits from society – and, in return,
it must exercise great responsibilities. One of the most basic
responsibilities is job creation, a fundamental need in any society.
By the mid-nineteenth century, corporations could live forever,
engage in any legal activity, and merge with or acquire other
corporations. In 1886, the U.S. Supreme Court legally recognized corporations as “persons”, entitled under the Fourteenth Amendment to the same protections as living citizens. Unlike average citizens, large corporations had large flows of money at their disposal. With this money they can hire lobbyists, donate copiously to politicians, and sway public opinion.
But, despite Supreme Court rulings, the modern corporation is not a real person. Rather, the publicly traded stock corporation is what Barnes terms an "automaton",
explicitly designed to maximize return to its owners. A corporation
never sleeps or slows down. It externalizes as many costs as possible,
and never reaches an upper limit of profitability, because no such limit
has yet been established. As a result, corporations keep getting
larger. In 1955, sales of the Fortune 500
accounted for one-third of U.S. gross domestic product. By 2004 they
commanded two-thirds. In other words, these few hundred corporations
replaced smaller firms organized as partnerships or proprietorships.
Corporations have established a homogeneous global playing field around
which they can freely move raw materials, labor, capital, finished
products, tax-paying obligations, and profits. Thus, corporate franchise
has become a perpetual grant of sovereignty, including immortality, self-government, and limited liability.
By the end of the twentieth century, corporate power—both economic and
political—stretched worldwide. International agreements not only lowered
tariffs but extended corporate property rights and reduced the ability of sovereign nations to regulate corporations.
David Schweickart submits that such "hypermobility of capital" generates economic and political insecurity.
"If the search for lower wages comes to dominate the movement of
capital, the result will be not only a lowering of worldwide wage
disparities (the good to which some economists point) but also a
lowering of total global income (a straight-out utilitarian bad)." Jack Rasmus, author of The War At Home and The Trillion Dollar Income Shift,
argues that the increasing concentration of corporate power is a cause
of the large-scale debt, unemployment, and poverty characteristic of
economic recession and depression.
According to Rasmus, income inequality in contemporary America
increased as the relative share of income for corporations and the
wealthiest one percent of households rose while income shares declined
for 80-percent of the United States workforce. After rising steadily for
three decades after World War II, the standard of living for most
American workers has sharply declined between the mid-1970s to the
present. Rasmus likens the widening income gap in contemporary American
society to the decade leading up to the Great Depression,
estimating "well over $1 trillion in income is transferred annually
from the roughly 90 million working class families in America to
corporations and the wealthiest non-working-class households. While a
hundred new billionaires were created since 2001, real weekly earnings for 100 million workers are less in 2007 than in 1980 when Ronald Reagan took office".
According to economist Richard D. Wolff, the 1970s brought an end to the labor shortage which had facilitated more than a century of rising average real wages in the United States.
Wolff says Americans responded to the resulting deficiency of effective
demand by working more hours and excessive borrowing; the latter paving
the way for the financial crisis of 2007–08.
Imperialism
According
to David Harvey, "the export of capital and the cultivation of new
markets around the world" is a solution "as old as capitalism itself"
for the deficiency of effective demand. Imperialism, as defined by Dictionary of Human Geography,
is "the creation and/or maintenance of an unequal economic, cultural,
and territorial relationship, usually between states and often in the
form of an empire, based on domination and subordination." "These geographic shifts", according to David Harvey, "are the heart of uneven geographic development".
Vladimir Lenin
viewed imperialism as the highest stage of capitalism. He asserted that
the merging of banks and industrial cartels gave rise to finance
capital, which was then exported (rather than goods) in pursuit of
greater profits than the home market could offer. Political and
financial power became divided among international monopolist firms and
European states, colonizing large parts of the world in support of their
businesses.
According to analyst Michael Parenti, imperialism is "the process
whereby the dominant politico-economic interests of one nation
expropriate for their own enrichment the land, labor, raw materials, and
markets of another people."
Parenti says imperialism is older than capitalism. Given its
expansionist nature, capitalism has little inclination to stay home.
While he conceded imperialism is not typically recognized as a
legitimate allegation about the United States, Parenti argued:
Emperors and conquistadors were
interested mostly in plunder and tribute, gold and glory. Capitalist
imperialism differs from these earlier forms in the way it
systematically accumulates capital through the organized exploitation of
labor and the penetration of overseas markets. Capitalist imperialism
invests in other countries, transforming and dominating their economies,
cultures, and political life, integrating their financial and
productive structures into an international system of capital
accumulation.
In his book, The Political Struggle for the 21st century, J.W. Smith
examines the economic basis for the history of imperial civilization.
On a global scale, he says developed nations tended to impede or
prohibit the economic and technological advancement of weaker developing
countries through the military force, martial law, and inequitable
practices of trade that typically characterize colonialism. Rhetorically termed as "survival of the fittest", or "might makes right", such economic crises stem from the imbalances imposed by corporate imperialism. Just as cities in the Middle Ages monopolized the means of production
by conquering and controlling the sources of raw materials and
countryside markets, Smith claims that contemporary centers of capital
now control our present world through private monopoly of public
resources sometimes known as "the commons". Through inequalities of
trade, developing countries are overcharged for import of manufactured
goods and underpaid for raw material exports, as wealth is siphoned from
the periphery of empire and hoarded at the imperial-centers-of-capital:
Over eight-hundred years ago the
powerful of the city-states of Europe learned to control the resources
and markets of the countryside by raiding and destroying others’
primitive industrial capital, thus openly monopolizing that capital and
establishing and maintaining extreme inequality of pay. This low pay
siphoned the wealth of the countryside to the
imperial-centers-of-capital. The powerful had learned to
plunder-by-trade and have been refining those skills ever since.
Smith goes on to say that, like other financial empires in history,
the contemporary model forms alliances necessary to develop and control
wealth, keeping peripheral nations impoverished providers of cheap
resources for the imperial capital centers. Belloc estimated that,
during the British Enclosures, "perhaps half of the whole population was
proletarian",
while roughly the other "half" owned and controlled the means of
production. Under modern Capitalism, J.W. Smith claimed that fewer than
500 individuals possess more wealth than half of the earth's population.
The wealth of 1/2 of 1-percent of the United States population roughly
equals that of the lower 90-percent.
Alternative models
Advocating for an "alternative economic system free of capitalism's structural flaws",
economist Richard D. Wolff says reform agendas are fundamentally
inadequate, given that capitalist corporations, the dominant
institutions of the existing system, retain the incentives and the
resources to undo any sort of reform policy. For example, Wolff goes on
to say:
The New Deal–era taxes on business and the rich and regulations of enterprise behavior proved vulnerable and unsustainable. The enemies of the New Deal had the incentives (profit maximization) and the resources (their returns on investments) to undo many of its reforms after World War II,
with ever-greater effect in the period since the 1970s. They
systematically evaded, then weakened, the taxes and regulations of the
New Deal, and eventually, when politically possible, eliminated them
altogether. Business profits funded the parties, politicians, public
relations campaigns, and professional think tanks that together shaped
the real social effects and historical decline of government economic
regulation. Examples include the destruction of the Glass-Steagall Act, the current assault on Social Security, the shift in the federal tax burden from business to individuals and from upper- to middle-income individuals, and so on.
According to David Schweickart, a serious critique of any problem
cannot be content to merely note the negative features of the existing model.
Instead, we must specify precisely the structural features of an
alternative: "But if we want to do more than simply denounce the evils
of capitalism, we must confront the claim that 'there is no
alternative'—by proposing one."
Schweickart argued that both full employment and guaranteed basic
income are impossible under the restrictions of the U.S. economic system
for two primary reasons: a) unemployment is an essential feature of
capitalism, not an indication of systemic failure; and b) while capitalism thrives under polyarchy, it is not compatible with genuine democracy. Assuming these "democratic deficits" significantly impact the management of both the workplace and new investment,
many proponents of economic democracy tend to favor the creation and
implementation of a new economic model over reform of the existing one.
For example, Dr. Martin Luther King Jr.
claimed "Communism forgets that life is individual. Capitalism forgets
that life is social, and the Kingdom of Brotherhood is found neither in
the thesis of Communism nor the antithesis of Capitalism but in a higher
synthesis. It is found in a higher synthesis that combines the truths
of both". Regarding the gap between productivity and purchasing power, Dr. King maintained:
The problem indicates that our
emphasis must be two-fold. We must create full employment or we must
create incomes. People must be made consumers by one method or the
other. Once they are placed in this position, we need to be concerned
that the potential of the individual is not wasted. New forms of work
that enhance the social good will have to be devised for those for whom
traditional jobs are not available.
According to historian and political economist, Gar Alperovitz:
"King’s final judgment stands as instructive evidence of his
understanding of the nature of systemic challenge — and also as a
reminder that given the failures of both traditional socialism and
corporate capitalism, it is time to get serious about clarifying not
only the question of strategy, but what, in fact, the meaning of
changing the system in a truly democratic direction might one day
entail."
Trade unionist and social activist Allan Engler argued further
that economic democracy was the working-class alternative to capitalism.
In his book, "Economic Democracy", Engler stated:
When economic democracy – a world
of human equality, democracy and cooperation – is the alternative,
capitalism will no longer be seen as a lesser evil. When the working
class, not a revolutionary party, is the agency of social
transformation, change will be based on workplace organization,
community mobilizations and democratic political action. The goal will
be to transform capitalism into economic democracy through gains and
reforms that improve living conditions while methodically replacing
wealth-holders' entitlement with human entitlement, capitalist ownership
with community ownership and master-servant relations with workplace
democracy.
Assuming that "democracy is not just a political value, but one with
profound economic implications, the problem is not to choose between plan and market, but to integrate these institutions into a democratic framework". Like capitalism, economic democracy can be defined in terms of three basic features:
- Worker self-management: each productive enterprise is controlled democratically by its workers.
- Social control of investment: funds for new investment are returned to the economy through a network of public investment banks.
- The market: enterprises interact with one another and with consumers
in an environment largely free of governmental price controls. Raw
materials, instruments of production and consumer goods are all bought
and sold at prices largely determined by the forces of supply and
demand.
In real-world practice, Schweickart concedes economic democracy will
be more complicated and less "pure" than his model. However, to grasp
the nature of the system and to understand its essential dynamic, it is
important to have a clear picture of the basic structure. Capitalism is
characterized by private ownership of productive resources, the market,
and wage labor. The Soviet economic model subordinated private ownership
of productive resources to public ownership by collectivizing farms and
factories. It further subordinated the market to central planning—but
retained the institution of wage labor.
Most proposed models for economic democracy generally begin with
democratizing the workplace and the ownership of capital. Other
proposals advocate replacing the market with some form of planning, as
well (for example, Parecon).
Worker self-management
In
worker self-management, each productive enterprise is controlled by
those who work there. Workers are responsible for the operation of the
facility, including organization, discipline, production techniques, and
the nature, price, and distribution of products. Decisions concerning
distribution are made democratically. Problems of authority delegation
are solved by democratic representation. Management is chosen by the
worker, not appointed by the State, not elected by the community at
large and not selected by a board of directors elected by stockholders. Ultimate authority rests with the enterprise's workers, following the one-person, one-vote principle.
According to veteran World Bank economic adviser David P. Ellerman it's the employment contract
that needs to be abolished, not private property. In other words, "a
firm can be socialized and yet remain 'private' in the sense of not
being government-owned." In his book, "The Democratic Firm", Ellerman stated:
In the world today, the main form of enterprise is based on renting human beings (privately or publicly).
Our task is to construct the alternative. In the alternative type of
firm, employment by the firm is replaced with membership in the firm.
Economic democracy requires the abolition of the employment relation,
not the abolition of private property. Democracy can be married with private property in the workplace; the result of the union is the democratic worker-owned firm.
Alternately, in Schweickart's model, workers control the workplace,
but they do not "own" the means of production. Productive resources are
regarded as the collective property of the society. Workers run the
enterprise, use its capital assets as they see fit, and distribute the
profits among themselves. Here, societal "ownership" of the enterprise
manifests itself in two ways: 1) All firms pay tax on their capital assets,
which goes into society's investment fund. In effect, workers rent
capital assets from society. 2) Firms are required to preserve the value
of the capital stock entrusted to them. This means that a depreciation
fund must be maintained to repair or replace existing capital stock.
This money may be spent on capital replacements or improvements, but not
to supplement workers' incomes.
Italy's Legacoop and Spain's Mondragon
multi-sectoral worker-cooperatives have both been able to reach
significant scale and demonstrate long-term sustainability. According to
a study conducted by Massachusetts Institute of Technology,
the greatest lesson to be learned from these European experiences is
the importance of developing an economically integrated network of
cooperatives rather than a single cooperative. The report goes on to say:
In a market based economy the
cooperative business form suffers from several strategic challenges when
operating independently. One worker cooperative on its own is most
likely doomed to fail in a highly competitive global economy. However,
an ecosystem of several worker cooperatives and support organizations
can create an infrastructure that leads to sustained growth and
expansion. In Mondragon the cooperative network expanded from a single
cooperative polytechnic school to a network of 256 industrial, retail,
finance, educational, and research and development firms.
Social control of investment
While
there is no single approach or 'blueprint' for social control of
investment, many strategies have been proposed. For example, Gar Alperovitz
claims many real-world strategies have already emerged to democratize
and decentralize the ownership of wealth and capital. In addition to
worker cooperatives, Alperovitz highlights ESOPs, credit unions and other cooperative forms, social enterprises, municipally owned utilities and public banks as starting points for what he has termed a "Pluralist Commonwealth".
Alternately, David Schweickart proposes a flat-rate tax
on capital assets to replace all other business taxes. This "capital
assets tax" is collected and invested by the central government. Funds
are dispersed throughout society, first to regions and communities on a
per capita basis, then to public banks in accordance with past
performance, then to those firms with profitable project
proposals. Profitable projects that promise increased employment are
favored over those that do not. At each level, national, regional and
local, legislatures decide what portion of their funds is to be used for
public capital expenditures, then send the remainder to the next lower
level. Associated with most banks are entrepreneurial divisions, which
promote firm expansion and new firm creation. For large (regional or
national) enterprises, local investment banks are complemented by
regional and national investment banks. These too would be public
institutions that receive their funds from the national investment fund.
Banks are public, not private, institutions that make grants,
not loans, to business enterprises. According to Schweickart, these
grants do not represent "free money", since an investment grant counts
as an addition to the capital assets of the enterprise, upon which the
capital-asset tax must be paid. Thus the capital assets tax functions as
an interest rate. A bank grant is essentially a loan requiring interest payments but no repayment of principal.
While an economy of worker-self-managed enterprises might tend
toward lower unemployment than under capitalism - because banks are
mandated to consistently prioritize investment projects that would
increase employment - Schweickart notes that it does not guarantee full employment.
Social control of investment serves to increase employment. If the
market provides insufficient employment, the public sector becomes the employer of last resort. The original formulation of the U.S. Humphrey-Hawkins Act of 1978
assumed that only in this way could full employment be assured in a
market economy. Economic Democracy adopts this approach. Social control
of investment then blocks the cyclical unemployment typical of
capitalism.
The market
Hungarian historian Karl Polanyi
suggested that market economies should subordinate themselves to larger
societal needs. He states that human-beings, the source of labor, do not reproduce for the sole purpose of providing the market with workers. In The Great Transformation,
Polanyi says that while modern states and market economies tend to grow
under capitalism, both are mutually interdependent for functional
development. In order for market economies to be truly prosperous, he
claims social constructs must play an essential role. Polanyi claimed
that land, labor, and money are all commodified under capitalism, though the inherent purpose of these items was never intended "for sale"—what he labels "fictitious commodities." He says natural resources
are "God-given", money is a bookkeeping entry validated by law, and
labor is a human prerogative, not a personal obligation to market
economies.
Schweickart's economic democracy is a form of market economy, at least insofar as the allocation of consumer and capital goods is concerned. Firms buy raw materials and machinery from other firms and sell their products to other enterprises or consumers. "Prices are largely unregulated
except by supply and demand, although in some cases price controls or
price supports might be in order – as they are deemed in order in most
real-world forms of capitalism."
Without a price mechanism
sensitive to supply and demand, it is extremely difficult for a
producer or planner to know what and how much to produce, and which
production and marketing methods are the most efficient. Otherwise, it
is difficult to motivate producers to be both efficient and innovative. Market competition resolves these problems, to a significant if incomplete degree, in a non-authoritarian, non-bureaucratic fashion.
Enterprises still strive to make a profit. However, "profit" in a
worker-run firm is calculated differently than under capitalism. For a
capitalist firm, labor is counted as a cost. For a worker-run enterprise
it is not. Labor is not another "factor of production" on par with land
and capital. Labor is the residual claimant. Workers get all that
remains, once other costs, including depreciation set asides and the
capital assets tax, have been paid.
Because of the way workplaces and the investment mechanism are structured, Schweickart's model aims to facilitate fair trade, not free trade,
between nations. Under Economic Democracy, there would be virtually no
cross-border capital flows. Enterprises themselves would not relocate
abroad, since they are democratically controlled by their own workers. Finance capital
stays mostly at home, since funds for investment are publicly generated
and are mandated by law to be reinvested domestically. "Capital doesn't
flow into the country, either, since there are no stocks nor corporate bonds nor businesses to buy. The capital assets of the country are collectively owned – and hence not for sale."
According to Michael Howard, "in preserving commodity exchange, a market socialism
has greater continuity with the society it displaces than does
nonmarket socialism, and thus it is more likely to emerge from
capitalism as a result of tendencies generated within it." But Howard
also suggested, "one argument against the market in socialist society
has been that it blocks progress toward full communism or even leads
back to capitalism". From this perspective, nonmarket models of economic democracy have also been proposed.
Economic democracy as part of an inclusive democracy
Economic democracy is described as an integral component of an inclusive democracy in Takis Fotopoulos' Towards An Inclusive Democracy
as a stateless, moneyless and marketless economy that precludes private
accumulation of wealth and the institutionalization of privileges for
some sections of society, without relying on a mythical post-scarcity state of abundance, or sacrificing freedom of choice.
The proposed system aims to meet the basic needs of all citizens (macroeconomic decisions), and secure freedom of choice (microeconomic
decisions). Therefore, the system consists of two basic elements: (1)
democratic planning, which involves a feedback process between workplace
assemblies, demotic assemblies and a confederal assembly, and (2) an
artificial market using personal vouchers, which ensures freedom of choice
but avoids the adverse effects of real markets. Although David Pepper
called this system "a form of money based on the labour theory of
value", it is not a money model since vouchers cannot be used as a general medium of exchange and store of wealth.
Another distinguishing feature of inclusive democracy is its
distinction between basic and non-basic needs. Remuneration is
determined separately according to the cost of basic needs, and
according to degree of effort for non-basic needs. Inclusive democracy
is based on the principle that meeting basic needs is a fundamental
human right which is guaranteed to all who are in a physical condition
to offer a minimal amount of work. By contrast, participatory economics
guarantees that basic needs are satisfied only for public goods or are
covered by compassion and by a guaranteed basic income for the
unemployed and those who cannot work. Many advocates of participatory economics and Participism have contested this.
As part of inclusive democracy, economic democracy is the
authority of demos (community) in the economic sphere—which requires
equal distribution of economic power. Therefore, all macroeconomic
decisions (overall level of production, consumption and investment,
amounts of work and leisure implied, technologies to be used and so on)
are made collectively and without representation. However, microeconomic
decisions are made by the individual production or consumption unit
through a proposed system of vouchers.
As with the case of direct democracy, economic democracy is only feasible if the participants can easily cooperate.
Reform agendas
While reform agendas
tend to critique the existing system and recommend corrective measures,
they do not necessarily suggest alternative models to replace the
fundamental structures of capitalism; private ownership of productive
resources, the market and wage labor.
Social credit
Rather than an economic shortfall, many analysts[who?] consider the gap between production and purchasing power a social dividend. In this view, credit is a public utility rather than debt to financial centers. Once reinvested in human productive potential, the surplus
of societal output could actually increase Gross Domestic Product
rather than throttling it, resulting in a more efficient economy,
overall. Social Credit is an economic reform movement that originates from theories developed by Scottish engineer Major C. H. Douglas.
His aim to make societal improvement the goal of economic systems is
reflected in the term "Social Credit", and published in his book,
entitled Economic Democracy. In this view, the term "economic democracy" does not mean worker control of industry.
A national dividend and a compensated price mechanism are the two
most essential components of the Social Credit program. While these
measures have never been implemented in their purest form, they have
provided a foundation for Social Credit political parties in many
countries and for reform agendas that retain the title, "economic
democracy".
National dividend
In his book, Capitalism 3.0, Peter Barnes likens a "National Dividend" to the game of Monopoly,
where all players start with a fair distribution of financial
opportunity to succeed, and try to privatize as much as they can as they
move around "the commons". Distinguishing the board game from
real-world business, Barnes claims that "the top 5 percent of the
population owns more property
than the remaining 95 percent", providing the smaller minority with an
unfair advantage of approximately "$5-trillion" annually, at the
beginning of the game. Contrasting "redistribution" of income (or
property) with "predistribution", Barnes argues for "propertizing"
(without corporately privatizing) "the commons" to spread ownership
universally, without taking wealth from some and giving it to others.
His suggested mechanism to this end is the establishment of a "Commons
Sector", ensuring payment from the Corporate Sector for "the commons"
they utilize, and equitably distributing the proceeds for the benefit of
contemporary and future generations of society.
One real-world example of such reform is in the U.S. State of Alaska, where each citizen receives an annual share of the part of the state's oil revenues via the "Alaska Permanent Fund Dividend".
Barnes suggests this model could extend to other states and nations
because "we jointly own many valuable assets". As corporate pollution of
common assets increased, the permits for such pollution would become
more scarce, driving prices for those permits up. "Less pollution would
equal more revenue", and over time, "trillions of dollars could flow
into an American Permanent Fund".
However, none of these proposals aspire to the mandates recommended by Dr. Martin Luther King Jr.:
Two conditions are indispensable if
we are to ensure that the guaranteed income operates as a consistently
progressive measure. First, it must be pegged to the median income of
society, not the lowest levels of income. To guarantee an income at the
floor would simply perpetuate welfare standards and freeze into the
society poverty conditions. Second, the guaranteed income must be
dynamic; it must automatically increase as the total social income
grows. Were it permitted to remain static under growth conditions, the
recipients would suffer a relative decline. If periodic reviews disclose
that the whole national income has risen, then the guaranteed income
would have to be adjusted upward by the same percentage. Without these
safeguards a creeping retrogression would occur, nullifying the gains of
security and stability.
Barnes deemed any such reform unlikely. Thomas Paine originally
recommended a National Dividend to compensate for the brutality of
British Enclosures, but his idea was never adopted.
Monopoly power versus public utility
Rather than superficially compensating for legalized inequities,
Smith recommends abolishing or redefining property rights laws with
particular respect for "the commons". According to Smith exclusive title
to natural resources and technologies should be converted to inclusive
conditional titles—the condition being that society should collect
rental values on all natural resources.
Smith suggests the basic principles of monopolization under feudalism
were never abandoned, and residues of exclusive feudal property rights
restrict the potential efficiency of capitalism in Western cultures.
He estimated that roughly 60 percent of American capital is little more
than capitalized values of unearned wealth. He proposed that
elimination of these monopoly values would double economic efficiency, maintain quality of life, and reduce working hours
by half. Wasteful monetary flows could be stopped only by eliminating
all methods of monopolization typical in Western economies.
Smith divided "primary (feudal) monopoly" into four general categories: banking; land; technology and communications. He listed three general categories of "secondary (modern) monopoly"; insurance, law, health care. Smith further claimed that converting these exclusive entitlements to inclusive human rights would minimize battles for market share,
thereby eliminating most offices and staff needed to maintain monopoly
structures, and stop the wars generated to protect them. Dissolving
roughly half the economic activity of a monopoly system would reduce the
costs of common resources by roughly half, and significantly minimize
the most influential factors of poverty.
In Smith's view, most taxes should be eliminated, and productive enterprise should be privately owned and managed. Inventors should be paid well and all technology placed in the public domain. Crucial services currently monopolized through licensing should be legislated as human rights.
Smith envisioned a balanced economy under a socially owned banking commons within an inclusive society with full and equal rights for all. Federated regions collect resource rents on land and technology to a social fund to operate governments and care for social needs. Socially owned banks provide finance capital by creating debt-free money for social infrastructure and industry.
Rental values return to society through expenditure on public
infrastructures. Local labor is trained and employed to build and
maintain water systems, sewers, roads, communication systems, railroads,
ports, airports, post offices, and education systems.
Purchasing power circulates regionally, as labor spends wages in
consumption and governments spend resource rent and banking profits to
maintain essential services.
According to Smith, all monetary systems, including money markets, should function within fractional-reserve banking.
Financial capital should be the total savings of all citizens, balanced
by primary-created money to fill any shortfall, or its destruction
through increased reserve requirements to eliminate any surplus.
Adjustments of required reserves should facilitate the balance between
building with socially created money or savings. Any shortage of savings
within a socially owned banking system should be alleviated by simply
printing it.
Cooperatives
A cooperative
is an autonomous association of persons united voluntarily to meet
their common economic, social, and cultural needs and aspirations
through a jointly owned and democratically controlled enterprise. By
various names, cooperatives play an essential role in all forms of
Economic Democracy. Classified as either consumer cooperatives or worker cooperatives, the cooperative business model is fundamental to the interests of economic democracy.
According to the International Cooperative Alliance's Statement on the Cooperative Identity,
"cooperatives are democratic organizations controlled by their members,
who actively participate in setting policies and making decisions. Men
and women serving as elected representatives are accountable to the
membership. In primary cooperatives members have equal voting rights
(one member, one vote) and cooperatives at other levels are also
organized in a democratic manner."
Worker cooperatives
According to the United States Federation of Worker Cooperatives:
"Worker cooperatives are business entities that are owned and
controlled by their members, the people who work in them. The two
central characteristics of worker cooperatives are: 1) workers invest in
and own the business and (2) decision-making is democratic, generally
adhering to the principle of one worker-one vote." Worker cooperatives
occupy multiple sectors and industries in the United States, mostly in
the Northeast, the West Coast and the Upper Midwest, totaling 300
democratic workplaces in the United States, employing over 3,500 people
and generating over $400 million in annual revenues. While a few are
larger enterprises, most are small. Growing steadily between 1990 and
2010, technology and home health care experienced most of the recent
increase.
Worker cooperatives generally employ an industrial model called workplace democracy, which rejects the "master-servant relationship" implicit in the traditional employment contract.
According to Wilkinson and Pickett, neither ownership or participation
alone are sufficient to establish democracy in the workplace. "[M]any
share-ownership schemes amount to little more than incentive schemes,
intended to make employees more compliant with management and sometimes
to provide a nest-egg for retirement... To make a reliable difference to
company performance, share-ownership has to be combined with more
participative management methods." Dahl further argued that self-governing enterprises should not be confused with other systems they might resemble:
Self-governing enterprises only
remotely resemble pseudodemocratic schemes of employee consultation by
management; schemes of limited employee participation that leave all
critical decisions with a management elected by stockholders; or
Employee Stock Ownership Plans (ESOPs) that are created only or
primarily to provide corporations with low-interest loans, lower
corporate income taxes, greater cash flow, employee pension plans, or a
market for their stock, without, however, any significant changes in
control.
In worker cooperatives, net income is called surplus instead of profit
and is distributed among the members based on hours worked, seniority,
or other criteria. In a worker cooperative, workers own their jobs, and
therefore have a direct stake in the local environment and the power to
conduct business in ways that benefit the community rather than
destroying it. Some worker cooperatives maintain what is known as a
“multiple bottom line”, evaluating success not merely in terms of net
income, but also by factors like their sustainability as a business,
their contribution to the community, and the happiness and longevity of
their workers.
Worker-control can take many forms depending on the size and type
of the business. Approaches to decision-making include: an elected
board of directors, elected managers, management job roles, no
management at all, consensus, majority vote, or combinations of the
above. Participation in decision-making becomes the responsibility and privilege of each member. In one variation, workers usually invest money when they begin working.
Each member owns one share, which provides its owner with one vote in
company decision-making. While membership is not a requirement of
employment, only employees can become members.
According to Kenneth W. Stikkers, the Mondragon cooperatives in the Basque region of Spain
have achieved a previously unknown level of economic democracy.
Established in 1956, Mondragon has since become an economic model that
transcends the capitalist-socialist dichotomy and thereby helps us to
imagine creative solutions to current economic problems. Economist Richard D. Wolff argues that Mondragon is an example of "a stunningly successful alternative to the capitalist organization of production."
The idea of economic democracy through worker ownership on a national
scale has been argued by economist Tom Winters, who states that
"building a cooperative economy is one small step on the journey to
reclaiming the wealth we all collectively create."
Consumer cooperatives
A consumers' cooperative is owned by its customers for their mutual benefit.
Oriented towards service rather than profit, consumers often provide
capital to launch or purchase the enterprise. In practice, consumer
cooperatives price goods and services at competitive market rates. The
co-op returns profits to the consumer/owner according to a formula
instead of paying a separate investor group.
In his book, From Mondragon To America, Greg MacLeod
argues that "in consumer cooperatives where the customer-members own the
capital and the employees are subject to capital, the normal dynamic is
the adversarial relationship of labor to capital. Sometimes the result
is strikes of labor against management." In some cooperatives, however,
consumer/owners are workers as well. For example, Mondragon has
developed a large "hybrid" cooperative which sells groceries and
furniture in Spain.
Consumer cooperatives vary in organization and operations, but typically follow the Rochdale Principles. Consumer cooperatives may also form Co-operative Federations. These may take the form of co-operative wholesale societies, through which they collectively purchase goods at wholesale prices and, in some cases, cooperatively own factories. Alternatively, they may be members of Co-operative unions.
Consumer cooperatives are very different from "discount clubs,"
which charge annual fees in exchange for a discount on purchases. The
club is not owned or governed by the members and profits go to
investors, not to members.
Food cooperatives
Most
food co-ops are consumer cooperatives that specialize in grocery
products. Members patronize the store and vote in elections. The members
elect a board of directors to make high-level decisions and recruit
managers. Food cooperatives were originally established to provide fresh, organic produce as a viable alternative to packaged imports. The ideas of local and slow food
production can help local farmers prosper, in addition to providing
consumers with fresher products. But the growing ubiquity of organic
food products in corporate stores testifies to broadening consumer
awareness, and to the dynamics of global marketing.
For example, associated with national and international
cooperative communities, Portland Oregon cooperatives manage to survive
market competition with corporate franchise. As Lee Lancaster, financial
manager for Food Front, states, "cooperatives are potentially one
democratic economic model that could help guide business decisions
toward meeting human needs while honoring the needs of society and
nature". He admits, however, it is difficult to maintain collaboration
among cooperatives while also avoiding integration that typically
results in centralized authority.
Regional trading currencies
According
to Smith, "Currency is only the representation of wealth produced by
combining land (resources), labor, and industrial capital". He claimed
that no country was free when another country has such leverage over its
entire economy. But by combining their resources, Smith claimed that
developing nations have all three of these foundations of wealth:
By peripheral nations using the
currency of an imperial center as its trading currency, the imperial
center can actually print money to own industry within those periphery
countries. By forming regional trading blocs and printing their own
trading currency, the developing world has all four requirements for
production, resources, labor, industrial capital, and finance capital.
The wealth produced provides the value to back the created and
circulating money.
Smith further explained that developed countries need resources from
the developing world as much as developing countries need finance
capital and technology from the developed world. Aside from the superior
military power of the imperial centers, the undeveloped world actually
has superior bargaining leverage. With independent trading currencies,
developing countries could barter their resources to the developed world
for the latest industrial technologies. Barter avoids "hard money
monopolization"
and the unequal trade between weak and strong nations that result.
Smith suggested that barter was how Germany resolved many financial
difficulties "put in place to strangle her", and that "World Wars I and
II settled that trade dispute". He claimed that their intentions of
exclusive entitlement were clearly exposed when the imperial centers
resorted to military force to prevent such barter and maintain monopoly
control of others' resources.
Democratizing workplaces and distributing productive assets
The Workplace as a political entity to be democratized
Workplace
democracy has been cited as a possible solution to the problems that
arise from excluding employees from decision-making such as low-employee
morale, employee alienation, and low employee engagement.
Political theorist Isabelle Ferreras
argues that there exists “a great contradiction between the democratic
nature of our times and the reality of the work experience.”
She argues that the modern corporation's two basic inputs, capital and
labor, are treated in radically different ways. Capital owners of a firm
wield power within a system of shareholder democracy that allocates
voice democratically according to how much capital investment they place
in the firm. Labor, on the other hand, rarely benefits from a system to
voice their concerns within the firm. She argues that firms are more
than just economic organizations especially given the power that they
wield over people's livelihoods, environment, and rights. Rather,
Ferreras holds that firms are best understood as political entities. And
as political entities “it is crucial that firms be made compatible with
the democratic commitments of our nations.”
Germany and to a lesser extent the broader European Union have
experimented with a way of workplace democracy known as
Co-determination, a system that allows workers to elect representatives
that sit on the board of directors of a company. Common criticisms of
workplace democracy include that democratic workplaces are less
efficient than hierarchical workplace, that managers are best equipped
to make company decisions since they are better educated and aware of
the broader business context.
Creating a widespread distribution of productive assets
One of the biggest criticisms against capitalism is that it concentrates economic and, as a result, political power
in a few hands. Theorists of economic democracy have argued that one
solution to this unequal concentration of power is to create mechanisms
that distribute ownership of productive assets across the entire
population. In Justice as Fairness: A Restatement, John Rawls argued that only two systems could embody the main features of his principles of justice: liberal socialism or a property-owning democracy. Within a property-owning democracy, Rawls envisioned widespread use of worker-owned cooperatives,
partial-employee ownership of firms, systems to redistribute one's
assets after death to prevent the accumulation of wealth, as well as a
strong system of asset-based redistribution that encourages workers to
own productive assets.
Operating under the idea that making ownership more widespread
leads to more equitable outcomes various proposals of asset-based
welfare and asset-redistribution have been conceived. Individualistic
and liberal asset-based welfare strategies such as the United Kingdom's Child Trust Fund or the United States Individual Development Account
aimed to help people save money so that it could be invested on
education, home-ownership, or entrepreneurship. More experimental and
left-leaning proposals include worker owned cooperatives, ESOPS, or Roemer's coupon socialism.
Critiques
Ludwig von Mises argued that ownership and control over the
means of production belongs to private firms and can only be sustained by means of
consumer choice, exercised daily in the marketplace. "The capitalistic social order", he claimed, therefore "is an economic democracy in the strictest sense of the word".
Critics of Mises claim that consumers only vote on the value of the
product when they make a purchase—they are not participating in the
management of firms, or voting on how the profits are to be used.
Economic democracy (sometimes called a
democratic economy) is a
socioeconomic philosophy that proposes to shift ownership and decision-making power from
corporate shareholders and
corporate managers (such as a
board of directors) to a larger group of
public stakeholders
that includes workers, consumers, suppliers, communities and the
broader public. No single definition or approach encompasses economic
democracy, but most proponents claim that modern property relations
externalize
costs, subordinate the general well-being to private profit and deny
the polity a democratic voice in economic policy decisions. In addition to these moral concerns, economic democracy makes practical claims, such as that it can compensate for
capitalism's inherent
effective demand gap.
Proponents of economic democracy generally argue that modern
capitalism periodically results in economic crises, characterized by deficiency of effective demand; as society is unable to earn enough income to purchase its own production output. Corporate monopoly of common resources typically creates artificial scarcity, resulting in socio-economic imbalances that restrict workers from access to economic opportunity and diminish consumer purchasing power.
Economic democracy has been proposed as a component of larger
socioeconomic ideologies, as a stand-alone theory and as a variety of
reform agendas. For example, as a means to securing full economic rights, it opens a path to full political rights, defined as including the former.
Both market and non-market theories of economic democracy have been
proposed. As a reform agenda, supporting theories and real-world
examples can include decentralization, democratic cooperatives, public banking, fair trade and the regionalization of food production and currency.
Deficiency of effective demand
According
to many analysts, deficiency of effective demand is the most
fundamental economic problem. That is, modern society does not earn
enough income to purchase its output. For example, economic geographer David Harvey
claims, "Workers spending their wages is one source of effective
demand, but the total wage bill is always less than the total capital in
circulation (otherwise there would be no profit), so the purchase of
wage goods that sustain daily life (even with a suburban lifestyle) is
never sufficient for the profitable sale of the total output".
In the Georgist view of any economic system, "wealth" includes all material things produced by labor for the satisfaction of human desires and having exchange value. Land, labor
and capital are generally considered the essential factors in producing
wealth. Land includes all natural opportunities and forces. Labor
includes all human exertion. Capital
includes the portion of wealth devoted to producing more wealth. While
the income of any individual might include proceeds from any combination
of these three sources—land, labor and capital are generally considered
mutually exclusive factors in economic models of the production and
distribution of wealth. According to Henry George: "People seek to satisfy their desires with the least exertion". Human beings interact with nature to produce goods and services that other human beings need or desire. The laws and customs that govern the relationships among these entities constitute the economic structure of a given society.
Alternately, David Schweickart asserts in his book, After Capitalism: "The structure of a capitalist society consists of three basic components:
- "The bulk of the means of production are privately owned, either directly by individuals or by corporations that are themselves owned by private individuals.
- "Products are exchanged in a market -- that is to say, goods and
services are bought and sold at prices determined for the most part by
competition and not by some governmental pricing authority. Individual
enterprises compete with one another in providing goods and services to
consumers, each enterprise trying to make a profit. This competition is
the primary determinant of prices.
- "Most of the people who work for pay in this society work for other
people, who own the means of production. Most working people are 'wage labourers'".
Supply and demand are generally accepted as market functions for establishing prices. Organisations typically endeavor to 1) minimize the cost of production;
2) increase sales; in order to 3) maximize profits. But, according to
David Schweickart, if "those who produce the goods and services of
society are paid less than their productive contribution", then as
consumers they cannot buy all the goods produced, and investor
confidence tends to decline, triggering declines in production and
employment. Such economic instability stems from a central
contradiction: Wages are both a cost of production and an essential
source of effective demand (needs or desires backed with purchasing power), resulting in deficiency of effective demand along with a growing interest in economic democracy.
In chapter 3 of his book, "Community Organizing: Theory and Practice", Douglas P. Biklen
discusses a variety of perspectives on "The Making of Social Problems".
One of those views suggests that "writers and organizers who define
social problems in terms of social and economic democracy see problems
not as the experiences of poor people, but as the relationship of
poverty to wealth and exploitation". Biklen states that according to
this viewpoint:
[C]orporate power, upper class
power, uneven distribution of wealth and prejudice cause social
problems... [T]he problem is not one of poverty, but of enormous wealth.
The problem is not one of gaps or cracks in an otherwise fine system
but of a system which perpetuates prejudicial views concerning race,
sex, age, and disability. The problem is not one of incompetence but of
barriers to education, jobs, and power. Accordingly, as long as there is
a deep gulf between social classes, both in terms of wealth, power, and
outlook, traditional social programs will act merely as palliatives to
oppression and not as a way of ending large scale human misery. This
perspective is, above all, eclectic. It embraces Marx's criticism of
social class inequality but is not only a social class analysis. It is
anti-racist, but it is not only a theory of race equality. It favors
democratic distribution of power but is also an economic theory. It can
be called a social and economic democracy perspective.
Savings, investment and unemployment
In his 1879 book Progress and Poverty, Henry George argued that a majority of wealth created in a "free market" economy was appropriated by land owners and monopolists through economic rents, and that concentration of such unearned wealth was the root cause of poverty.
"Behind the abstraction known as 'the market' lurks a set of
institutions designed to maximize the wealth and power of the most
privileged group of people in the world—the creditor-rentier class of the first world and their junior partners in the third".
Schweickart claimed that private savings are not only unnecessary for
economic growth, they are often harmful to the overall economy.
In an advanced industrial society, business credit is necessary
for a healthy economy. A business that wants to expand production needs
to command the labor of others, and money is the default mechanism for
exercising this authority. It is often cheaper for a business to borrow capital from a bank than to stockpile cash.
If private savings are loaned out to entrepreneurs who use them
to buy raw materials and hire workers, then aggregate demand is not
reduced.
However, when private savings are not reinvested, the whole economy
suffers recession, unemployment, and disappearance of savings which characterize deficiency of effective demand.
In this view, unemployment is not an aberration, indicating any
sort of systemic malfunction. Rather, unemployment is a necessary
structural feature of capitalism, intended to discipline the workforce.
If unemployment is too low, workers make wage demands that either cut
into profits to an extent that jeopardizes future investment, or are
passed on to consumers, thus generating inflationary instability.
Schweickart suggested, "Capitalism cannot be a full-employment economy,
except in the very short term. For unemployment is the "invisible hand"—carrying a stick—that keeps the workforce in line." In this view, Adam Smith's "invisible hand" does not seem reliable to guide economic forces on a large scale.
Assuming business credit could come from public sources rather
than from private savers, Schweickart and other analysts consider
interest payments to private savers both undeserved and unnecessary for
economic growth. Moreover, the personal decision to save rather than
consume decreases aggregate demand, increases the likelihood of
unemployment, and exacerbates the tendency toward economic stagnation.
Since wealthy people tend to save more than poor people, the propensity
of an economy to slump because of excess saving becomes ever more acute
as a society becomes more affluent.
Richard Wilkinson and Kate Pickett suggested that health and social
problems are significantly worse in more unequal wealthy nations.
They argue that there are "pernicious effects that inequality has on
societies: eroding trust, increasing anxiety and illness, (and)
encouraging excessive consumption"
Monopoly power versus purchasing power
Regarding a social and economic democracy perspective on social problems, Douglas P. Biklen states:
The theme of profit superseding
individual well-being flows through this antimonopoly view of social
problems. On the one hand, poor and middle income people find their
lives deformed by their meager or nonexistent ability to pay for goods
and services. Wealthy people, on the other hand, find that their
relative position, in terms of wealth and power, grows with their
ability to maintain the gulf between social classes. Thus monopolies or
concentrated wealth plays a large part in creating social problems.
Indeed, one might say, monopolies and policies which promote the former
or concentrations of wealth are the problem.
The discipline of economics is largely a study of scarcity
management; "the science which studies human behavior as a relationship
between ends and scarce means which have alternative uses". Absent scarcity and alternative uses of available resources, many analysts claim there is no economic problem".
While he considers these functions a public wrong, Kellogg also asserted
the responsibility of the public to find and implement a remedy.
Generally considered monopoly power, some view this "public wrong" as the most influential factor in artificial scarcity. For example, Henry George further suggested:
There is in reality no conflict
between labor and capital; the true conflict is between labor and
monopoly... Abolish the monopoly that forbids men to employ themselves
and capital could not possibly oppress labor... [R]emove the cause of
that injustice which deprives the laborer of the capital his toil
creates and the sharp distinction between capitalist and laborer would,
in fact, cease to exist.
For example, many analysts consider invention
a "more or less costless store of knowledge, captured by monopoly
capital and protected in order to make it secret and a 'rare and scarce
commodity', for sale at monopoly prices. So far as invention is
concerned, a price is put on them not because they are scarce but in
order to make them scarce to those who want to use them."
Patent monopolies raise share prices above tangible labor value. The
difference between labor-value and monopoly-value raises goods prices,
and is collected as "profit" by intermediaries who have contributed
nothing to earn it.
Analysts generally agree that such conditions typically result in
a deficiency of effective demand. Labor does not earn enough to buy
what enterprises produce. According to Jack Rasmus, author of The Trillion Dollar Income Shift,
in June 2006, investment bank Goldman Sachs reported: "The most
important contribution to the higher profit margins over the past five
years has been a decline in Labor's share of national income."
Enclosure of the commons
Artificially restricted access of labor to common resources is generally considered monopoly or enclosure of the commons.
Due to the economic imbalance inherently imposed, such monopoly
structures tend to be centrally dictated by law, and must be maintained
by military force, trade agreements, or both.
In 1911, American journalist Ambrose Bierce defined "land" as:
A part of the earth's surface,
considered as property. The theory that land is property subject to
private ownership and control is the foundation of modern society....
Carried to its logical conclusion, it means that some have the right to
prevent others from living; for the right to own implies the right
exclusively to occupy; and in fact laws of trespass are enacted wherever
property in land is recognized. It follows that if the whole area of
terra firma is owned by A, B and C, there will be no place for D, E, F
and G to be born, or, born as trespassers, to exist.
In The Servile State (1912), Hilaire Belloc referred to the Enclosures Movement when he said, "England was already captured by a wealthy oligarchy before the series of great industrial
discoveries began". If you sought the accumulated wealth preliminary to
launching new industry, "you had to turn to the class which had already
monopolized the bulk of the means of production in England. The rich
men alone could furnish you with those supplies".
According to Peter Barnes, author of Capitalism 3.0, when Adam Smith wrote The Wealth of Nations
in 1776, the dominant form of business was partnership, in which
regional groups of co-workers ran co-owned businesses. From this
perspective, many considered the corporate model—stock sold to
strangers—inherently prone to fraud. While numerous scandals
historically support this dim view of corporate policy, small
partnerships could not possibly compete with the aggregate capital
generated by corporate economies of scale.
The greatest advantage of corporations over any other business model is
their ability to raise capital from strangers. The corporate model
benefits from laws that limit stockholders' liability to the amounts
they have invested.
In A Preface To Economic Democracy, Robert A. Dahl suggests that agrarian economy and society in the early United States "underwent a revolutionary transformation into a new system of commercial and industrial capitalism that automatically generated vast inequalities of wealth, income, status, and power." Dahl claims that such inequalities result from the "liberty to accumulate unlimited economic resources and to organize economic activity into hierarchically governed enterprises."
The rise of corporations and ending labor shortage
According
to author Greg MacLeod, the concept of the corporation originated in
Roman times. However, "the modern business corporation evolved radically
from its ancient roots into a form with little relation to the purpose
as understood by historians of law." John Davis, a legal historian,
noted that the precursor of the business corporation was the first monastery,
established in the sixth century, the purpose of which was to serve
society. Most business corporations before 1900 developed in Great
Britain, where they were established by royal charter,
with the expectation of contributions to society. Incorporation was a
privilege granted in return for service to the crown or the nation.
MacLeod goes on to say:
A corporation is considered by the law to exist as a legal person. In the Middle Ages
it was called a "persona ficta". This is a very useful way of looking
at a business corporation, because it suggests correctly that the corporate person
has a certain personality. It has duties and responsibilities vested
unto it by the legitimate government or society that fostered it. The
corporate person receives great benefits from society – and, in return,
it must exercise great responsibilities. One of the most basic
responsibilities is job creation, a fundamental need in any society.
By the mid-nineteenth century, corporations could live forever,
engage in any legal activity, and merge with or acquire other
corporations. In 1886, the U.S. Supreme Court legally recognized corporations as “persons”, entitled under the Fourteenth Amendment to the same protections as living citizens. Unlike average citizens, large corporations had large flows of money at their disposal. With this money they can hire lobbyists, donate copiously to politicians, and sway public opinion.
But, despite Supreme Court rulings, the modern corporation is not a real person. Rather, the publicly traded stock corporation is what Barnes terms an "automaton",
explicitly designed to maximize return to its owners. A corporation
never sleeps or slows down. It externalizes as many costs as possible,
and never reaches an upper limit of profitability, because no such limit
has yet been established. As a result, corporations keep getting
larger. In 1955, sales of the Fortune 500
accounted for one-third of U.S. gross domestic product. By 2004 they
commanded two-thirds. In other words, these few hundred corporations
replaced smaller firms organized as partnerships or proprietorships.
Corporations have established a homogeneous global playing field around
which they can freely move raw materials, labor, capital, finished
products, tax-paying obligations, and profits. Thus, corporate franchise
has become a perpetual grant of sovereignty, including immortality, self-government, and limited liability.
By the end of the twentieth century, corporate power—both economic and
political—stretched worldwide. International agreements not only lowered
tariffs but extended corporate property rights and reduced the ability of sovereign nations to regulate corporations.
David Schweickart submits that such "hypermobility of capital" generates economic and political insecurity.
"If the search for lower wages comes to dominate the movement of
capital, the result will be not only a lowering of worldwide wage
disparities (the good to which some economists point) but also a
lowering of total global income (a straight-out utilitarian bad)." Jack Rasmus, author of The War At Home and The Trillion Dollar Income Shift,
argues that the increasing concentration of corporate power is a cause
of the large-scale debt, unemployment, and poverty characteristic of
economic recession and depression.
According to Rasmus, income inequality in contemporary America
increased as the relative share of income for corporations and the
wealthiest one percent of households rose while income shares declined
for 80-percent of the United States workforce. After rising steadily for
three decades after World War II, the standard of living for most
American workers has sharply declined between the mid-1970s to the
present. Rasmus likens the widening income gap in contemporary American
society to the decade leading up to the Great Depression,
estimating "well over $1 trillion in income is transferred annually
from the roughly 90 million working class families in America to
corporations and the wealthiest non-working-class households. While a
hundred new billionaires were created since 2001, real weekly earnings for 100 million workers are less in 2007 than in 1980 when Ronald Reagan took office".
According to economist Richard D. Wolff, the 1970s brought an end to the labor shortage which had facilitated more than a century of rising average real wages in the United States.
Wolff says Americans responded to the resulting deficiency of effective
demand by working more hours and excessive borrowing; the latter paving
the way for the financial crisis of 2007–08.
Imperialism
According
to David Harvey, "the export of capital and the cultivation of new
markets around the world" is a solution "as old as capitalism itself"
for the deficiency of effective demand. Imperialism, as defined by Dictionary of Human Geography,
is "the creation and/or maintenance of an unequal economic, cultural,
and territorial relationship, usually between states and often in the
form of an empire, based on domination and subordination." "These geographic shifts", according to David Harvey, "are the heart of uneven geographic development".
Vladimir Lenin
viewed imperialism as the highest stage of capitalism. He asserted that
the merging of banks and industrial cartels gave rise to finance
capital, which was then exported (rather than goods) in pursuit of
greater profits than the home market could offer. Political and
financial power became divided among international monopolist firms and
European states, colonizing large parts of the world in support of their
businesses.
According to analyst Michael Parenti, imperialism is "the process
whereby the dominant politico-economic interests of one nation
expropriate for their own enrichment the land, labor, raw materials, and
markets of another people."
Parenti says imperialism is older than capitalism. Given its
expansionist nature, capitalism has little inclination to stay home.
While he conceded imperialism is not typically recognized as a
legitimate allegation about the United States, Parenti argued:
Emperors and conquistadors were
interested mostly in plunder and tribute, gold and glory. Capitalist
imperialism differs from these earlier forms in the way it
systematically accumulates capital through the organized exploitation of
labor and the penetration of overseas markets. Capitalist imperialism
invests in other countries, transforming and dominating their economies,
cultures, and political life, integrating their financial and
productive structures into an international system of capital
accumulation.
In his book, The Political Struggle for the 21st century, J.W. Smith
examines the economic basis for the history of imperial civilization.
On a global scale, he says developed nations tended to impede or
prohibit the economic and technological advancement of weaker developing
countries through the military force, martial law, and inequitable
practices of trade that typically characterize colonialism. Rhetorically termed as "survival of the fittest", or "might makes right", such economic crises stem from the imbalances imposed by corporate imperialism. Just as cities in the Middle Ages monopolized the means of production
by conquering and controlling the sources of raw materials and
countryside markets, Smith claims that contemporary centers of capital
now control our present world through private monopoly of public
resources sometimes known as "the commons". Through inequalities of
trade, developing countries are overcharged for import of manufactured
goods and underpaid for raw material exports, as wealth is siphoned from
the periphery of empire and hoarded at the imperial-centers-of-capital:
Over eight-hundred years ago the
powerful of the city-states of Europe learned to control the resources
and markets of the countryside by raiding and destroying others’
primitive industrial capital, thus openly monopolizing that capital and
establishing and maintaining extreme inequality of pay. This low pay
siphoned the wealth of the countryside to the
imperial-centers-of-capital. The powerful had learned to
plunder-by-trade and have been refining those skills ever since.
Smith goes on to say that, like other financial empires in history,
the contemporary model forms alliances necessary to develop and control
wealth, keeping peripheral nations impoverished providers of cheap
resources for the imperial capital centers. Belloc estimated that,
during the British Enclosures, "perhaps half of the whole population was
proletarian",
while roughly the other "half" owned and controlled the means of
production. Under modern Capitalism, J.W. Smith claimed that fewer than
500 individuals possess more wealth than half of the earth's population.
The wealth of 1/2 of 1-percent of the United States population roughly
equals that of the lower 90-percent.
Alternative models
Advocating for an "alternative economic system free of capitalism's structural flaws",
economist Richard D. Wolff says reform agendas are fundamentally
inadequate, given that capitalist corporations, the dominant
institutions of the existing system, retain the incentives and the
resources to undo any sort of reform policy. For example, Wolff goes on
to say:
The New Deal–era taxes on business and the rich and regulations of enterprise behavior proved vulnerable and unsustainable. The enemies of the New Deal had the incentives (profit maximization) and the resources (their returns on investments) to undo many of its reforms after World War II,
with ever-greater effect in the period since the 1970s. They
systematically evaded, then weakened, the taxes and regulations of the
New Deal, and eventually, when politically possible, eliminated them
altogether. Business profits funded the parties, politicians, public
relations campaigns, and professional think tanks that together shaped
the real social effects and historical decline of government economic
regulation. Examples include the destruction of the Glass-Steagall Act, the current assault on Social Security, the shift in the federal tax burden from business to individuals and from upper- to middle-income individuals, and so on.
According to David Schweickart, a serious critique of any problem
cannot be content to merely note the negative features of the existing model.
Instead, we must specify precisely the structural features of an
alternative: "But if we want to do more than simply denounce the evils
of capitalism, we must confront the claim that 'there is no
alternative'—by proposing one."
Schweickart argued that both full employment and guaranteed basic
income are impossible under the restrictions of the U.S. economic system
for two primary reasons: a) unemployment is an essential feature of
capitalism, not an indication of systemic failure; and b) while capitalism thrives under polyarchy, it is not compatible with genuine democracy. Assuming these "democratic deficits" significantly impact the management of both the workplace and new investment,
many proponents of economic democracy tend to favor the creation and
implementation of a new economic model over reform of the existing one.
For example, Dr. Martin Luther King Jr.
claimed "Communism forgets that life is individual. Capitalism forgets
that life is social, and the Kingdom of Brotherhood is found neither in
the thesis of Communism nor the antithesis of Capitalism but in a higher
synthesis. It is found in a higher synthesis that combines the truths
of both". Regarding the gap between productivity and purchasing power, Dr. King maintained:
The problem indicates that our
emphasis must be two-fold. We must create full employment or we must
create incomes. People must be made consumers by one method or the
other. Once they are placed in this position, we need to be concerned
that the potential of the individual is not wasted. New forms of work
that enhance the social good will have to be devised for those for whom
traditional jobs are not available.
According to historian and political economist, Gar Alperovitz:
"King’s final judgment stands as instructive evidence of his
understanding of the nature of systemic challenge — and also as a
reminder that given the failures of both traditional socialism and
corporate capitalism, it is time to get serious about clarifying not
only the question of strategy, but what, in fact, the meaning of
changing the system in a truly democratic direction might one day
entail."
Trade unionist and social activist Allan Engler argued further
that economic democracy was the working-class alternative to capitalism.
In his book, "Economic Democracy", Engler stated:
When economic democracy – a world
of human equality, democracy and cooperation – is the alternative,
capitalism will no longer be seen as a lesser evil. When the working
class, not a revolutionary party, is the agency of social
transformation, change will be based on workplace organization,
community mobilizations and democratic political action. The goal will
be to transform capitalism into economic democracy through gains and
reforms that improve living conditions while methodically replacing
wealth-holders' entitlement with human entitlement, capitalist ownership
with community ownership and master-servant relations with workplace
democracy.
Assuming that "democracy is not just a political value, but one with
profound economic implications, the problem is not to choose between plan and market, but to integrate these institutions into a democratic framework". Like capitalism, economic democracy can be defined in terms of three basic features:
- Worker self-management: each productive enterprise is controlled democratically by its workers.
- Social control of investment: funds for new investment are returned to the economy through a network of public investment banks.
- The market: enterprises interact with one another and with consumers
in an environment largely free of governmental price controls. Raw
materials, instruments of production and consumer goods are all bought
and sold at prices largely determined by the forces of supply and
demand.
In real-world practice, Schweickart concedes economic democracy will
be more complicated and less "pure" than his model. However, to grasp
the nature of the system and to understand its essential dynamic, it is
important to have a clear picture of the basic structure. Capitalism is
characterized by private ownership of productive resources, the market,
and wage labor. The Soviet economic model subordinated private ownership
of productive resources to public ownership by collectivizing farms and
factories. It further subordinated the market to central planning—but
retained the institution of wage labor.
Most proposed models for economic democracy generally begin with
democratizing the workplace and the ownership of capital. Other
proposals advocate replacing the market with some form of planning, as
well (for example, Parecon).
Worker self-management
In
worker self-management, each productive enterprise is controlled by
those who work there. Workers are responsible for the operation of the
facility, including organization, discipline, production techniques, and
the nature, price, and distribution of products. Decisions concerning
distribution are made democratically. Problems of authority delegation
are solved by democratic representation. Management is chosen by the
worker, not appointed by the State, not elected by the community at
large and not selected by a board of directors elected by stockholders. Ultimate authority rests with the enterprise's workers, following the one-person, one-vote principle.
According to veteran World Bank economic adviser David P. Ellerman it's the employment contract
that needs to be abolished, not private property. In other words, "a
firm can be socialized and yet remain 'private' in the sense of not
being government-owned." In his book, "The Democratic Firm", Ellerman stated:
In the world today, the main form of enterprise is based on renting human beings (privately or publicly).
Our task is to construct the alternative. In the alternative type of
firm, employment by the firm is replaced with membership in the firm.
Economic democracy requires the abolition of the employment relation,
not the abolition of private property. Democracy can be married with private property in the workplace; the result of the union is the democratic worker-owned firm.
Alternately, in Schweickart's model, workers control the workplace,
but they do not "own" the means of production. Productive resources are
regarded as the collective property of the society. Workers run the
enterprise, use its capital assets as they see fit, and distribute the
profits among themselves. Here, societal "ownership" of the enterprise
manifests itself in two ways: 1) All firms pay tax on their capital assets,
which goes into society's investment fund. In effect, workers rent
capital assets from society. 2) Firms are required to preserve the value
of the capital stock entrusted to them. This means that a depreciation
fund must be maintained to repair or replace existing capital stock.
This money may be spent on capital replacements or improvements, but not
to supplement workers' incomes.
Italy's Legacoop and Spain's Mondragon
multi-sectoral worker-cooperatives have both been able to reach
significant scale and demonstrate long-term sustainability. According to
a study conducted by Massachusetts Institute of Technology,
the greatest lesson to be learned from these European experiences is
the importance of developing an economically integrated network of
cooperatives rather than a single cooperative. The report goes on to say:
In a market based economy the
cooperative business form suffers from several strategic challenges when
operating independently. One worker cooperative on its own is most
likely doomed to fail in a highly competitive global economy. However,
an ecosystem of several worker cooperatives and support organizations
can create an infrastructure that leads to sustained growth and
expansion. In Mondragon the cooperative network expanded from a single
cooperative polytechnic school to a network of 256 industrial, retail,
finance, educational, and research and development firms.
Social control of investment
While
there is no single approach or 'blueprint' for social control of
investment, many strategies have been proposed. For example, Gar Alperovitz
claims many real-world strategies have already emerged to democratize
and decentralize the ownership of wealth and capital. In addition to
worker cooperatives, Alperovitz highlights ESOPs, credit unions and other cooperative forms, social enterprises, municipally owned utilities and public banks as starting points for what he has termed a "Pluralist Commonwealth".
Alternately, David Schweickart proposes a flat-rate tax
on capital assets to replace all other business taxes. This "capital
assets tax" is collected and invested by the central government. Funds
are dispersed throughout society, first to regions and communities on a
per capita basis, then to public banks in accordance with past
performance, then to those firms with profitable project
proposals. Profitable projects that promise increased employment are
favored over those that do not. At each level, national, regional and
local, legislatures decide what portion of their funds is to be used for
public capital expenditures, then send the remainder to the next lower
level. Associated with most banks are entrepreneurial divisions, which
promote firm expansion and new firm creation. For large (regional or
national) enterprises, local investment banks are complemented by
regional and national investment banks. These too would be public
institutions that receive their funds from the national investment fund.
Banks are public, not private, institutions that make grants,
not loans, to business enterprises. According to Schweickart, these
grants do not represent "free money", since an investment grant counts
as an addition to the capital assets of the enterprise, upon which the
capital-asset tax must be paid. Thus the capital assets tax functions as
an interest rate. A bank grant is essentially a loan requiring interest payments but no repayment of principal.
While an economy of worker-self-managed enterprises might tend
toward lower unemployment than under capitalism - because banks are
mandated to consistently prioritize investment projects that would
increase employment - Schweickart notes that it does not guarantee full employment.
Social control of investment serves to increase employment. If the
market provides insufficient employment, the public sector becomes the employer of last resort. The original formulation of the U.S. Humphrey-Hawkins Act of 1978
assumed that only in this way could full employment be assured in a
market economy. Economic Democracy adopts this approach. Social control
of investment then blocks the cyclical unemployment typical of
capitalism.
The market
Hungarian historian Karl Polanyi
suggested that market economies should subordinate themselves to larger
societal needs. He states that human-beings, the source of labor, do not reproduce for the sole purpose of providing the market with workers. In The Great Transformation,
Polanyi says that while modern states and market economies tend to grow
under capitalism, both are mutually interdependent for functional
development. In order for market economies to be truly prosperous, he
claims social constructs must play an essential role. Polanyi claimed
that land, labor, and money are all commodified under capitalism, though the inherent purpose of these items was never intended "for sale"—what he labels "fictitious commodities." He says natural resources
are "God-given", money is a bookkeeping entry validated by law, and
labor is a human prerogative, not a personal obligation to market
economies.
Schweickart's economic democracy is a form of market economy, at least insofar as the allocation of consumer and capital goods is concerned. Firms buy raw materials and machinery from other firms and sell their products to other enterprises or consumers. "Prices are largely unregulated
except by supply and demand, although in some cases price controls or
price supports might be in order – as they are deemed in order in most
real-world forms of capitalism."
Without a price mechanism
sensitive to supply and demand, it is extremely difficult for a
producer or planner to know what and how much to produce, and which
production and marketing methods are the most efficient. Otherwise, it
is difficult to motivate producers to be both efficient and innovative. Market competition resolves these problems, to a significant if incomplete degree, in a non-authoritarian, non-bureaucratic fashion.
Enterprises still strive to make a profit. However, "profit" in a
worker-run firm is calculated differently than under capitalism. For a
capitalist firm, labor is counted as a cost. For a worker-run enterprise
it is not. Labor is not another "factor of production" on par with land
and capital. Labor is the residual claimant. Workers get all that
remains, once other costs, including depreciation set asides and the
capital assets tax, have been paid.
Because of the way workplaces and the investment mechanism are structured, Schweickart's model aims to facilitate fair trade, not free trade,
between nations. Under Economic Democracy, there would be virtually no
cross-border capital flows. Enterprises themselves would not relocate
abroad, since they are democratically controlled by their own workers. Finance capital
stays mostly at home, since funds for investment are publicly generated
and are mandated by law to be reinvested domestically. "Capital doesn't
flow into the country, either, since there are no stocks nor corporate bonds nor businesses to buy. The capital assets of the country are collectively owned – and hence not for sale."
According to Michael Howard, "in preserving commodity exchange, a market socialism
has greater continuity with the society it displaces than does
nonmarket socialism, and thus it is more likely to emerge from
capitalism as a result of tendencies generated within it." But Howard
also suggested, "one argument against the market in socialist society
has been that it blocks progress toward full communism or even leads
back to capitalism". From this perspective, nonmarket models of economic democracy have also been proposed.
Economic democracy as part of an inclusive democracy
Economic democracy is described as an integral component of an inclusive democracy in Takis Fotopoulos' Towards An Inclusive Democracy
as a stateless, moneyless and marketless economy that precludes private
accumulation of wealth and the institutionalization of privileges for
some sections of society, without relying on a mythical post-scarcity state of abundance, or sacrificing freedom of choice.
The proposed system aims to meet the basic needs of all citizens (macroeconomic decisions), and secure freedom of choice (microeconomic
decisions). Therefore, the system consists of two basic elements: (1)
democratic planning, which involves a feedback process between workplace
assemblies, demotic assemblies and a confederal assembly, and (2) an
artificial market using personal vouchers, which ensures freedom of choice
but avoids the adverse effects of real markets. Although David Pepper
called this system "a form of money based on the labour theory of
value", it is not a money model since vouchers cannot be used as a general medium of exchange and store of wealth.
Another distinguishing feature of inclusive democracy is its
distinction between basic and non-basic needs. Remuneration is
determined separately according to the cost of basic needs, and
according to degree of effort for non-basic needs. Inclusive democracy
is based on the principle that meeting basic needs is a fundamental
human right which is guaranteed to all who are in a physical condition
to offer a minimal amount of work. By contrast, participatory economics
guarantees that basic needs are satisfied only for public goods or are
covered by compassion and by a guaranteed basic income for the
unemployed and those who cannot work. Many advocates of participatory economics and Participism have contested this.
As part of inclusive democracy, economic democracy is the
authority of demos (community) in the economic sphere—which requires
equal distribution of economic power. Therefore, all macroeconomic
decisions (overall level of production, consumption and investment,
amounts of work and leisure implied, technologies to be used and so on)
are made collectively and without representation. However, microeconomic
decisions are made by the individual production or consumption unit
through a proposed system of vouchers.
As with the case of direct democracy, economic democracy is only feasible if the participants can easily cooperate.
Reform agendas
While reform agendas
tend to critique the existing system and recommend corrective measures,
they do not necessarily suggest alternative models to replace the
fundamental structures of capitalism; private ownership of productive
resources, the market and wage labor.
Social credit
Rather than an economic shortfall, many analysts[who?] consider the gap between production and purchasing power a social dividend. In this view, credit is a public utility rather than debt to financial centers. Once reinvested in human productive potential, the surplus
of societal output could actually increase Gross Domestic Product
rather than throttling it, resulting in a more efficient economy,
overall. Social Credit is an economic reform movement that originates from theories developed by Scottish engineer Major C. H. Douglas.
His aim to make societal improvement the goal of economic systems is
reflected in the term "Social Credit", and published in his book,
entitled Economic Democracy. In this view, the term "economic democracy" does not mean worker control of industry.
A national dividend and a compensated price mechanism are the two
most essential components of the Social Credit program. While these
measures have never been implemented in their purest form, they have
provided a foundation for Social Credit political parties in many
countries and for reform agendas that retain the title, "economic
democracy".
National dividend
In his book, Capitalism 3.0, Peter Barnes likens a "National Dividend" to the game of Monopoly,
where all players start with a fair distribution of financial
opportunity to succeed, and try to privatize as much as they can as they
move around "the commons". Distinguishing the board game from
real-world business, Barnes claims that "the top 5 percent of the
population owns more property
than the remaining 95 percent", providing the smaller minority with an
unfair advantage of approximately "$5-trillion" annually, at the
beginning of the game. Contrasting "redistribution" of income (or
property) with "predistribution", Barnes argues for "propertizing"
(without corporately privatizing) "the commons" to spread ownership
universally, without taking wealth from some and giving it to others.
His suggested mechanism to this end is the establishment of a "Commons
Sector", ensuring payment from the Corporate Sector for "the commons"
they utilize, and equitably distributing the proceeds for the benefit of
contemporary and future generations of society.
One real-world example of such reform is in the U.S. State of Alaska, where each citizen receives an annual share of the part of the state's oil revenues via the "Alaska Permanent Fund Dividend".
Barnes suggests this model could extend to other states and nations
because "we jointly own many valuable assets". As corporate pollution of
common assets increased, the permits for such pollution would become
more scarce, driving prices for those permits up. "Less pollution would
equal more revenue", and over time, "trillions of dollars could flow
into an American Permanent Fund".
However, none of these proposals aspire to the mandates recommended by Dr. Martin Luther King Jr.:
Two conditions are indispensable if
we are to ensure that the guaranteed income operates as a consistently
progressive measure. First, it must be pegged to the median income of
society, not the lowest levels of income. To guarantee an income at the
floor would simply perpetuate welfare standards and freeze into the
society poverty conditions. Second, the guaranteed income must be
dynamic; it must automatically increase as the total social income
grows. Were it permitted to remain static under growth conditions, the
recipients would suffer a relative decline. If periodic reviews disclose
that the whole national income has risen, then the guaranteed income
would have to be adjusted upward by the same percentage. Without these
safeguards a creeping retrogression would occur, nullifying the gains of
security and stability.
Barnes deemed any such reform unlikely. Thomas Paine originally
recommended a National Dividend to compensate for the brutality of
British Enclosures, but his idea was never adopted.
Monopoly power versus public utility
Rather than superficially compensating for legalized inequities,
Smith recommends abolishing or redefining property rights laws with
particular respect for "the commons".cording to Smith exclusive title
to natural resources and technologies should be converted to inclusive
conditional titles—the condition being that society should collect
rental values on all natural resources.
Smith suggests the basic principles of monopolization under feudalism
were never abandoned, and residues of exclusive feudal property rights
restrict the potential efficiency of capitalism in Western cultures.
He estimated that roughly 60 percent of American capital is little more
than capitalized values of unearned wealth. He proposed that
elimination of these monopoly values would double economic efficiency, maintain quality of life, and reduce working hours
by half. Wasteful monetary flows could be stopped only by eliminating
all methods of monopolization typical in Western economies.
Smith divided "primary (feudal) monopoly" into four general categories: banking; land; technology and communications. He listed three general categories of "secondary (modern) monopoly"; insurance, law, health care. Smith further claimed that converting these exclusive entitlements to inclusive human rights would minimize battles for market share,
thereby eliminating most offices and staff needed to maintain monopoly
structures, and stop the wars generated to protect them. Dissolving
roughly half the economic activity of a monopoly system would reduce the
costs of common resources by roughly half, and significantly minimize
the most influential factors of poverty.
In Smith's view, most taxes should be eliminated, and productive enterprise should be privately owned and managed. Inventors should be paid well and all technology placed in the public domain. Crucial services currently monopolized through licensing should be legislated as human rights.
Smith envisioned a balanced economy under a socially owned banking commons within an inclusive society with full and equal rights for all. Federated regions collect resource rents on land and technology to a social fund to operate governments and care for social needs. Socially owned banks provide finance capital by creating debt-free money for social infrastructure and industry.
Rental values return to society through expenditure on public
infrastructures. Local labor is trained and employed to build and
maintain water systems, sewers, roads, communication systems, railroads,
ports, airports, post offices, and education systems.
Purchasing power circulates regionally, as labor spends wages in
consumption and governments spend resource rent and banking profits to
maintain essential services.
According to Smith, all monetary systems, including money markets, should function within fractional-reserve banking.
Financial capital should be the total savings of all citizens, balanced
by primary-created money to fill any shortfall, or its destruction
through increased reserve requirements to eliminate any surplus.
Adjustments of required reserves should facilitate the balance between
building with socially created money or savings. Any shortage of savings
within a socially owned banking system should be alleviated by simply
printing it.
Cooperatives
A cooperative
is an autonomous association of persons united voluntarily to meet
their common economic, social, and cultural needs and aspirations
through a jointly owned and democratically controlled enterprise. By
various names, cooperatives play an essential role in all forms of
Economic Democracy. Classified as either consumer cooperatives or worker cooperatives, the cooperative business model is fundamental to the interests of economic democracy.
According to the International Cooperative Alliance's Statement on the Cooperative Identity,
"cooperatives are democratic organizations controlled by their members,
who actively participate in setting policies and making decisions. Men
and women serving as elected representatives are accountable to the
membership. In primary cooperatives members have equal voting rights
(one member, one vote) and cooperatives at other levels are also
organized in a democratic manner."
Worker cooperatives
According to the United States Federation of Worker Cooperatives:
"Worker cooperatives are business entities that are owned and
controlled by their members, the people who work in them. The two
central characteristics of worker cooperatives are: 1) workers invest in
and own the business and (2) decision-making is democratic, generally
adhering to the principle of one worker-one vote." Worker cooperatives
occupy multiple sectors and industries in the United States, mostly in
the Northeast, the West Coast and the Upper Midwest, totaling 300
democratic workplaces in the United States, employing over 3,500 people
and generating over $400 million in annual revenues. While a few are
larger enterprises, most are small. Growing steadily between 1990 and
2010, technology and home health care experienced most of the recent
increase.
Worker cooperatives generally employ an industrial model called workplace democracy, which rejects the "master-servant relationship" implicit in the traditional employment contract.
According to Wilkinson and Pickett, neither ownership or participation
alone are sufficient to establish democracy in the workplace. "[M]any
share-ownership schemes amount to little more than incentive schemes,
intended to make employees more compliant with management and sometimes
to provide a nest-egg for retirement... To make a reliable difference to
company performance, share-ownership has to be combined with more
participative management methods." Dahl further argued that self-governing enterprises should not be confused with other systems they might resemble:
Self-governing enterprises only
remotely resemble pseudodemocratic schemes of employee consultation by
management; schemes of limited employee participation that leave all
critical decisions with a management elected by stockholders; or
Employee Stock Ownership Plans (ESOPs) that are created only or
primarily to provide corporations with low-interest loans, lower
corporate income taxes, greater cash flow, employee pension plans, or a
market for their stock, without, however, any significant changes in
control.
In worker cooperatives, net income is called surplus instead of profit
and is distributed among the members based on hours worked, seniority,
or other criteria. In a worker cooperative, workers own their jobs, and
therefore have a direct stake in the local environment and the power to
conduct business in ways that benefit the community rather than
destroying it. Some worker cooperatives maintain what is known as a
“multiple bottom line”, evaluating success not merely in terms of net
income, but also by factors like their sustainability as a business,
their contribution to the community, and the happiness and longevity of
their workers.
Worker-control can take many forms depending on the size and type
of the business. Approaches to decision-making include: an elected
board of directors, elected managers, management job roles, no
management at all, consensus, majority vote, or combinations of the
above. Participation in decision-making becomes the responsibility and privilege of each member. In one variation, workers usually invest money when they begin working.
Each member owns one share, which provides its owner with one vote in
company decision-making. While membership is not a requirement of
employment, only employees can become members.
According to Kenneth W. Stikkers, the Mondragon cooperatives in the Basque region of Spain
have achieved a previously unknown level of economic democracy.
Established in 1956, Mondragon has since become an economic model that
transcends the capitalist-socialist dichotomy and thereby helps us to
imagine creative solutions to current economic problems. Economist Richard D. Wolff argues that Mondragon is an example of "a stunningly successful alternative to the capitalist organization of production."
The idea of economic democracy through worker ownership on a national
scale has been argued by economist Tom Winters, who states that
"building a cooperative economy is one small step on the journey to
reclaiming the wealth we all collectively create."
Consumer cooperatives
A consumers' cooperative is owned by its customers for their mutual benefit.
Oriented towards service rather than profit, consumers often provide
capital to launch or purchase the enterprise. In practice, consumer
cooperatives price goods and services at competitive market rates. The
co-op returns profits to the consumer/owner according to a formula
instead of paying a separate investor group.
In his book, From Mondragon To America, Greg MacLeod
argues that "in consumer cooperatives where the customer-members own the
capital and the employees are subject to capital, the normal dynamic is
the adversarial relationship of labor to capital. Sometimes the result
is strikes of labor against management." In some cooperatives, however,
consumer/owners are workers as well. For example, Mondragon has
developed a large "hybrid" cooperative which sells groceries and
furniture in Spain.
Consumer cooperatives vary in organization and operations, but typically follow the Rochdale Principles. Consumer cooperatives may also form Co-operative Federations. These may take the form of co-operative wholesale societies, through which they collectively purchase goods at wholesale prices and, in some cases, cooperatively own factories. Alternatively, they may be members of Co-operative unions.
Consumer cooperatives are very different from "discount clubs,"
which charge annual fees in exchange for a discount on purchases. The
club is not owned or governed by the members and profits go to
investors, not to members.
Food cooperatives
Most
food co-ops are consumer cooperatives that specialize in grocery
products. Members patronize the store and vote in elections. The members
elect a board of directors to make high-level decisions and recruit
managers. Food cooperatives were originally established to provide fresh, organic produce as a viable alternative to packaged imports. The ideas of local and slow food
production can help local farmers prosper, in addition to providing
consumers with fresher products. But the growing ubiquity of organic
food products in corporate stores testifies to broadening consumer
awareness, and to the dynamics of global marketing.
For example, associated with national and international
cooperative communities, Portland Oregon cooperatives manage to survive
market competition with corporate franchise. As Lee Lancaster, financial
manager for Food Front, states, "cooperatives are potentially one
democratic economic model that could help guide business decisions
toward meeting human needs while honoring the needs of society and
nature". He admits, however, it is difficult to maintain collaboration
among cooperatives while also avoiding integration that typically
results in centralized authority.
Regional trading currencies
According
to Smith, "Currency is only the representation of wealth produced by
combining land (resources), labor, and industrial capital". He claimed
that no country was free when another country has such leverage over its
entire economy. But by combining their resources, Smith claimed that
developing nations have all three of these foundations of wealth:
By peripheral nations using the
currency of an imperial center as its trading currency, the imperial
center can actually print money to own industry within those periphery
countries. By forming regional trading blocs and printing their own
trading currency, the developing world has all four requirements for
production, resources, labor, industrial capital, and finance capital.
The wealth produced provides the value to back the created and
circulating money.
Smith further explained that developed countries need resources from
the developing world as much as developing countries need finance
capital and technology from the developed world. Aside from the superior
military power of the imperial centers, the undeveloped world actually
has superior bargaining leverage. With independent trading currencies,
developing countries could barter their resources to the developed world
for the latest industrial technologies. Barter avoids "hard money
monopolization"
and the unequal trade between weak and strong nations that result.
Smith suggested that barter was how Germany resolved many financial
difficulties "put in place to strangle her", and that "World Wars I and
II settled that trade dispute". He claimed that their intentions of
exclusive entitlement were clearly exposed when the imperial centers
resorted to military force to prevent such barter and maintain monopoly
control of others' resources.
Democratizing workplaces and distributing productive assets
The Workplace as a political entity to be democratized
Workplace
democracy has been cited as a possible solution to the problems that
arise from excluding employees from decision-making such as low-employee
morale, employee alienation, and low employee engagement.
Political theorist Isabelle Ferreras
argues that there exists “a great contradiction between the democratic
nature of our times and the reality of the work experience.”
She argues that the modern corporation's two basic inputs, capital and
labor, are treated in radically different ways. Capital owners of a firm
wield power within a system of shareholder democracy that allocates
voice democratically according to how much capital investment they place
in the firm. Labor, on the other hand, rarely benefits from a system to
voice their concerns within the firm. She argues that firms are more
than just economic organizations especially given the power that they
wield over people's livelihoods, environment, and rights. Rather,
Ferreras holds that firms are best understood as political entities. And
as political entities “it is crucial that firms be made compatible with
the democratic commitments of our nations.”
Germany and to a lesser extent the broader European Union have
experimented with a way of workplace democracy known as
Co-determination, a system that allows workers to elect representatives
that sit on the board of directors of a company. Common criticisms of
workplace democracy include that democratic workplaces are less
efficient than hierarchical workplace, that managers are best equipped
to make company decisions since they are better educated and aware of
the broader business context.
Creating a widespread distribution of productive assets
One of the biggest criticisms against capitalism is that it concentrates economic and, as a result, political power
in a few hands. Theorists of economic democracy have argued that one
solution to this unequal concentration of power is to create mechanisms
that distribute ownership of productive assets across the entire
population. In Justice as Fairness: A Restatement, John Rawls argued that only two systems could embody the main features of his principles of justice: liberal socialism or a property-owning democracy. Within a property-owning democracy, Rawls envisioned widespread use of worker-owned cooperatives,
partial-employee ownership of firms, systems to redistribute one's
assets after death to prevent the accumulation of wealth, as well as a
strong system of asset-based redistribution that encourages workers to
own productive assets.
Operating under the idea that making ownership more widespread
leads to more equitable outcomes various proposals of asset-based
welfare and asset-redistribution have been conceived. Individualistic
and liberal asset-based welfare strategies such as the United Kingdom's Child Trust Fund or the United States Individual Development Account
aimed to help people save money so that it could be invested on
education, home-ownership, or entrepreneurship. More experimental and
left-leaning proposals include worker owned cooperatives, ESOPS, or Roemer's coupon socialism.
Critiques
Ludwig von Mises argued that ownership and control over the
means of production belongs to private firms and can only be sustained by means of
consumer choice, exercised daily in the marketplace. "The capitalistic social order", he claimed, therefore "is an economic democracy in the strictest sense of the word".
Critics of Mises claim that consumers only vote on the value of the
product when they make a purchase—they are not participating in the
management of firms, or voting on how the profits are to be used.