Nietzsche in Basel, Switzerland, c. 1875
| |
Born |
Friedrich Wilhelm Nietzsche
15 October 1844 |
---|---|
Died | 25 August 1900 (aged 55) |
Nationality | German |
Alma mater | |
Era | 19th-century philosophy |
Region | Western philosophy |
School | |
Institutions | University of Basel |
Language | German |
Main interests
| |
Signature | |
Friedrich Wilhelm Nietzsche was a German philosopher, cultural critic, composer, poet, and philologist whose work has exerted a profound influence on modern intellectual history. He began his career as a classical philologist before turning to philosophy. He became the youngest ever to hold the Chair of Classical Philology at the University of Basel in 1869 at the age of 24. Nietzsche resigned in 1879 due to health problems that plagued him most of his life; he completed much of his core writing in the following decade. In 1889, at age 44, he suffered a collapse and afterward a complete loss of his mental faculties. He lived his remaining years in the care of his mother until her death in 1897 and then with his sister Elisabeth Förster-Nietzsche. Nietzsche died in 1900.
Nietzsche's writing spans philosophical polemics, poetry, cultural criticism, and fiction while displaying a fondness for aphorism and irony. Prominent elements of his philosophy include his radical critique of truth in favor of perspectivism; his genealogical critique of religion and Christian morality and his related theory of master–slave morality: his aesthetic affirmation of existence in response to the "death of God" and the profound crisis of nihilism; his notion of the Apollonian and Dionysian; and his characterization of the human subject as the expression of competing wills, collectively understood as the will to power. He also developed influential concepts such as the Übermensch and the doctrine of eternal return. In his later work, he became increasingly preoccupied with the creative powers of the individual to overcome social, cultural and moral contexts in pursuit of new values and aesthetic health. His body of work touched a wide range of topics, including art, philology, history, religion, tragedy, culture, and science, and drew early inspiration from figures such as philosopher Arthur Schopenhauer, composer Richard Wagner, and writer Johann Wolfgang von Goethe.
After his death, his sister Elisabeth became the curator and editor of Nietzsche's manuscripts, reworking his unpublished writings to fit her own German nationalist ideology while often contradicting or obfuscating Nietzsche's stated opinions, which were explicitly opposed to antisemitism and nationalism. Through her published editions, Nietzsche's work became associated with fascism and Nazism; 20th-century scholars contested this interpretation of his work and corrected editions of his writings were soon made available. Nietzsche's thought enjoyed renewed popularity in the 1960s and his ideas have since had a profound impact on 20th and early-21st century thinkers across philosophy—especially in schools of continental philosophy such as existentialism, postmodernism and post-structuralism—as well as art, literature, psychology, politics, and popular culture.
Life
Youth (1844–1868)
Born on 15 October 1844, Nietzsche grew up in the town of Röcken (now part of Lützen), near Leipzig, in the Prussian Province of Saxony. He was named after King Friedrich Wilhelm IV of Prussia, who turned 49 on the day of Nietzsche's birth (Nietzsche later dropped his middle name Wilhelm). Nietzsche's parents, Carl Ludwig Nietzsche (1813–1849), a Lutheran pastor and former teacher; and Franziska Nietzsche (née Oehler) (1826–1897), married in 1843, the year before their son's birth. They had two other children: a daughter, Elisabeth Förster-Nietzsche,
born in 1846; and a second son, Ludwig Joseph, born in 1848.
Nietzsche's father died from a brain ailment in 1849; Ludwig Joseph died
six months later at age two. The family then moved to Naumburg,
where they lived with Nietzsche's maternal grandmother and his father's
two unmarried sisters. After the death of Nietzsche's grandmother in
1856, the family moved into their own house, now Nietzsche-Haus, a museum and Nietzsche study centre.
Nietzsche attended a boys' school and then a private school, where he
became friends with Gustav Krug and Wilhelm Pinder, all three of whom
came from highly respected families. Academic records from one of the
schools attended by Nietzsche noted that he excelled in Christian
theology.
In 1854, he began to attend Domgymnasium in Naumburg. Because his
father had worked for the state (as a pastor) the now-fatherless
Nietzsche was offered a scholarship to study at the internationally
recognized Schulpforta
(the claim that Nietzsche was admitted on the strength of his academic
competence has been debunked: his grades were nowhere near the top of
the class). He transferred and studied there from 1858 to 1864, becoming friends with Paul Deussen
and Carl von Gersdorff. He also found time to work on poems and musical
compositions. Nietzsche led "Germania", a music and literature club,
during his summers in Naumburg. At Schulpforta, Nietzsche received an important grounding in languages—Greek, Latin, Hebrew, and French—so as to be able to read important primary sources;
he also experienced for the first time being away from his family life
in a small-town conservative environment. His end-of-semester exams in
March 1864 showed a 1 in Religion and German; a 2a in Greek and Latin; a 2b in French, History, and Physics; and a "lackluster" 3 in Hebrew and Mathematics.
While at Pforta,
Nietzsche had a penchant for pursuing subjects that were considered
unbecoming. He became acquainted with the work of the then
almost-unknown poet Friedrich Hölderlin,
calling him "my favorite poet" and composing an essay in which he said
that the mad poet raised consciousness to "the most sublime ideality".
The teacher who corrected the essay gave it a good mark but commented
that Nietzsche should concern himself in the future with healthier, more
lucid, and more "German" writers. Additionally, he became acquainted
with Ernst Ortlepp,
an eccentric, blasphemous, and often drunken poet who was found dead in
a ditch weeks after meeting the young Nietzsche but who may have
introduced Nietzsche to the music and writing of Richard Wagner.
Perhaps under Ortlepp's influence, he and a student named Richter
returned to school drunk and encountered a teacher, resulting in
Nietzsche's demotion from first in his class and the end of his status
as a prefect.
After graduation in September 1864, Nietzsche commenced studies in theology and classical philology at the University of Bonn with hope of becoming a minister. For a short time he and Deussen became members of the Burschenschaft Frankonia. After one semester (and to the anger of his mother), he stopped his theological studies and lost his faith.
As early as his 1862 essay "Fate and History", Nietzsche had argued
that historical research had discredited the central teachings of
Christianity, but David Strauss's Life of Jesus also seems to have had a profound effect on the young man. In addition, Ludwig Feuerbach's The Essence of Christianity influenced young Nietzsche with its argument that people created God, and not the other way around.
In June 1865, at the age of 20, Nietzsche wrote to his sister
Elisabeth, who was deeply religious, a letter regarding his loss of
faith. This letter contains the following statement:
Hence the ways of men part: if you wish to strive for peace of soul and pleasure, then believe; if you wish to be a devotee of truth, then inquire …
Nietzsche subsequently concentrated on studying philology under Professor Friedrich Wilhelm Ritschl, whom he followed to the University of Leipzig in 1865. There, he became close friends with his fellow student Erwin Rohde. Nietzsche's first philological publications appeared soon after.
In 1865, Nietzsche thoroughly studied the works of Arthur Schopenhauer. He owed the awakening of his philosophical interest to reading Schopenhauer's The World as Will and Representation and later admitted that Schopenhauer was one of the few thinkers whom he respected, dedicating the essay "Schopenhauer as Educator" in the Untimely Meditations to him.
In 1866, he read Friedrich Albert Lange's History of Materialism. Lange's descriptions of Kant's anti-materialistic philosophy, the rise of European Materialism, Europe's increased concern with science, Charles Darwin's theory of evolution,
and the general rebellion against tradition and authority intrigued
Nietzsche greatly. Nietzsche would ultimately argue the impossibility of
an evolutionary explanation of the human aesthetic sense.
In 1867, Nietzsche signed up for one year of voluntary service
with the Prussian artillery division in Naumburg. He was regarded as one
of the finest riders among his fellow recruits, and his officers
predicted that he would soon reach the rank of captain. However, in
March 1868, while jumping into the saddle of his horse, Nietzsche struck
his chest against the pommel and tore two muscles in his left side, leaving him exhausted and unable to walk for months. Consequently, Nietzsche turned his attention to his studies again, completing them in 1868 and meeting with Richard Wagner for the first time later that year.
Professor at Basel (1869–1878)
In part because of Ritschl's support, Nietzsche received a remarkable offer in 1869 to become professor of classical philology at the University of Basel in Switzerland. He was only 24 years old and had neither completed his doctorate nor received a teaching certificate ("habilitation"). He was awarded an honorary doctorate by the University of Leipzig, again with Ritschl's support.
Despite his offer coming at a time when he was considering giving up philology for science, he accepted. To this day, Nietzsche is still among the youngest of the tenured Classics professors on record.
Before moving to Basel, Nietzsche renounced his Prussian citizenship: for the rest of his life he remained officially stateless.
Nevertheless, Nietzsche served in the Prussian forces during the Franco-Prussian War (1870–1871) as a medical orderly. In his short time in the military, he experienced much and witnessed the traumatic effects of battle. He also contracted diphtheria and dysentery. Walter Kaufmann speculates that he might also have contracted syphilis at a brothel along with his other infections at this time. On returning to Basel in 1870, Nietzsche observed the establishment of the German Empire and Otto von Bismarck's
subsequent policies as an outsider and with a degree of skepticism
regarding their genuineness. His inaugural lecture at the university was
"Homer and Classical Philology". Nietzsche also met Franz Overbeck, a professor of theology who remained his friend throughout his life. Afrikan Spir, a little-known Russian philosopher responsible for the 1873 Thought and Reality, and Nietzsche's colleague the famed historian Jacob Burckhardt, whose lectures Nietzsche frequently attended, began to exercise significant influence on him during this time.
Nietzsche had already met Richard Wagner in Leipzig in 1868 and later Wagner's wife, Cosima. Nietzsche admired both greatly and during his time at Basel frequently visited Wagner's house in Tribschen in Lucerne. The Wagners brought Nietzsche into their most intimate circle—including Franz Liszt, of whom Nietzsche colloquially described: "Liszt or the art of running after women!" Nietzsche enjoyed the attention he gave to the beginning of the Bayreuth Festival.
In 1870, he gave Cosima Wagner the manuscript of "The Genesis of the
Tragic Idea" as a birthday gift. In 1872, Nietzsche published his first
book, The Birth of Tragedy.
However, his colleagues within his field, including Ritschl, expressed
little enthusiasm for the work in which Nietzsche eschewed the classical
philologic method in favor of a more speculative approach. In his polemic Philology of the Future, Ulrich von Wilamowitz-Moellendorff damped the book's reception and increased its notoriety. In response, Rohde (then a professor in Kiel)
and Wagner came to Nietzsche's defense. Nietzsche remarked freely about
the isolation he felt within the philological community and attempted
unsuccessfully to transfer to a position in philosophy at Basel instead.
In 1873, Nietzsche began to accumulate notes that would be posthumously published as Philosophy in the Tragic Age of the Greeks. Between 1873 and 1876, he published four separate long essays: "David Strauss:
the Confessor and the Writer", "On the Use and Abuse of History for
Life", "Schopenhauer as Educator", and "Richard Wagner in Bayreuth".
These four later appeared in a collected edition under the title Untimely Meditations.
The essays shared the orientation of a cultural critique, challenging
the developing German culture along lines suggested by Schopenhauer and
Wagner. During this time in the circle of the Wagners, he met Malwida von Meysenbug and Hans von Bülow. He also began a friendship with Paul Rée, who in 1876 influenced him into dismissing the pessimism in his early writings. However, he was deeply disappointed by the Bayreuth Festival
of 1876, where the banality of the shows and baseness of the public
repelled him. He was also alienated by Wagner's championing of "German
culture", which Nietzsche felt a contradiction in terms as well as by
Wagner's celebration of his fame among the German public. All this
contributed to his subsequent decision to distance himself from Wagner.
With the publication in 1878 of Human, All Too Human (a book of aphorisms ranging from metaphysics to morality to religion), a new style of Nietzsche's work became clear, highly influenced by Afrikan Spir's Thought and Reality
and reacting against the pessimistic philosophy of Wagner and
Schopenhauer. Nietzsche's friendship with Deussen and Rohde cooled as
well. In 1879, after a significant decline in health, Nietzsche had to
resign his position at Basel. Since his childhood, various disruptive
illnesses had plagued him, including moments of short-sightedness that
left him nearly blind, migraine
headaches, and violent indigestion. The 1868 riding accident and
diseases in 1870 may have aggravated these persistent conditions, which
continued to affect him through his years at Basel, forcing him to take
longer and longer holidays until regular work became impractical.
Independent philosopher (1879–1888)
Living off his pension from Basel and aid from friends, Nietzsche
travelled frequently to find climates more conducive to his health and
lived until 1889 as an independent author in different cities. He spent
many summers in Sils Maria near St. Moritz in Switzerland. He spent his winters in the Italian cities of Genoa, Rapallo, and Turin and the French city of Nice. In 1881, when France occupied Tunisia, he planned to travel to Tunis to view Europe from the outside but later abandoned that idea, probably for health reasons. Nietzsche occasionally returned to Naumburg to visit his family, and, especially during this time, he and his sister had repeated periods of conflict and reconciliation.
While in Genoa, Nietzsche's failing eyesight prompted him to explore the use of typewriters as a means of continuing to write. He is known to have tried using the Hansen Writing Ball, a contemporary typewriter device. In the end, a past student of his, Heinrich Köselitz or Peter Gast,
became a sort of private secretary to Nietzsche. In 1876, Gast
transcribed the crabbed, nearly illegible handwriting of Nietzsche for
the first time with Richard Wagner in Bayreuth.
He subsequently transcribed and proofread the galleys for almost all of
Nietzsche's work from then on. On at least one occasion on 23 February
1880, the usually poor Gast received 200 marks from their mutual friend,
Paul Rée. Gast was one of the very few friends Nietzsche allowed to criticize him. In responding most enthusiastically to Also sprach Zarathustra ('Thus Spoke Zarathustra'),
Gast did feel it necessary to point out that what were described as
"superfluous" people were in fact quite necessary. He went on to list
the number of people Epicurus, for example, had to rely on even to supply his simple diet of goat cheese.
To the end of his life, Gast and Overbeck remained consistently faithful friends. Malwida von Meysenbug
remained like a motherly patron even outside the Wagner circle. Soon
Nietzsche made contact with the music-critic Carl Fuchs. Nietzsche stood
at the beginning of his most productive period. Beginning with Human, All Too Human
in 1878, Nietzsche published one book or major section of a book each
year until 1888, his last year of writing; that year, he completed five.
In 1882, Nietzsche published the first part of The Gay Science. That year he also met Lou Andreas-Salomé, through Malwida von Meysenbug and Paul Rée.
Salomé's mother took her to Rome when Salomé was 21. At a literary salon in the city, Salomé became acquainted with Paul Rée.
Rée proposed marriage to her, but she instead proposed that they should
live and study together as "brother and sister", along with another man
for company, where they would establish an academic commune.
Rée accepted the idea, and suggested that they be joined by his friend
Nietzsche. The two met Nietzsche in Rome in April 1882, and Nietzsche is
believed to have instantly fallen in love with Salome, as Rée had done.
Nietzsche asked Rée to propose marriage to Salome, which she rejected.
She had been interested in Nietzsche as a friend, but not as a husband.
Nietzsche nonetheless was content to join together with Rée and Salome
touring through Switzerland and Italy together, planning their commune.
The three traveled with Salomé's mother through Italy and considered
where they would set up their "Winterplan" commune. This commune was
intended to be set up in an abandoned monastery, but no suitable
location was found. On 13 May, in Lucerne, when Nietzsche was alone with
Salome, he earnestly proposed marriage to her again, which she
rejected. He nonetheless was happy to continue with the plans for an
academic commune. After discovering the situation, Nietzsche's sister Elisabeth became determined to get Nietzsche away from the "immoral woman".
Nietzsche and Salomé spent the summer together in Tautenburg
in Thuringia, often with Nietzsche's sister Elisabeth as a chaperone.
Salomé reports that he asked her to marry him on three separate
occasions and that she refused, though the reliability of her reports of
events has come into question. Arriving in Leipzig,
(Germany) in October, Salomé and Rée separated from Nietzsche after a
falling-out between Nietzsche and Salomé, in which Salomé believed that
Nietzsche was desperately in love with her.
While the three spent a number of weeks together in Leipzig in
October 1882, the following month Rée and Salome ditched Nietzsche,
leaving for Stibbe (today Zdbowo in Poland)
without any plans to meet again. Nietzsche soon fell into a period of
mental anguish, although he continued to write to Rée, stating "We shall
see one another from time to time, won't we?"
In later recriminations, Nietzsche would blame on separate occasions
the failure in his attempts to woo Salome both on Salome, Rée, and on
the intrigues of his sister (who had written letters to the family of
Salome and Rée to disrupt the plans for the commune). Nietzsche wrote of
the affair in 1883, that he now felt "genuine hatred for my sister".
Amidst renewed bouts of illness, living in near-isolation after a
falling out with his mother and sister regarding Salomé, Nietzsche fled
to Rapallo, where he wrote the first part of Also sprach Zarathustra in only ten days.
By 1882, Nietzsche was taking huge doses of opium, but he was still having trouble sleeping. In 1883, while staying in Nice, he was writing out his own prescriptions for the sedative chloral hydrate, signing them "Dr. Nietzsche".
After severing his philosophical ties with Schopenhauer
(who was long dead and never met Nietzsche) and his social ties with
Wagner, Nietzsche had few remaining friends. Now, with the new style of Zarathustra,
his work became even more alienating, and the market received it only
to the degree required by politeness. Nietzsche recognized this and
maintained his solitude, though he often complained about it. His books
remained largely unsold. In 1885, he printed only 40 copies of the
fourth part of Zarathustra and distributed only a fraction of these among close friends, including Helene von Druskowitz.
In 1883, he tried and failed to obtain a lecturing post at the University of Leipzig.
It was made clear to him that, in view of his attitude towards
Christianity and his concept of God, he had become effectively
unemployable by any German university. The subsequent "feelings of
revenge and resentment" embittered him:
And hence my rage since I have grasped in the broadest possible sense what wretched means (the depreciation of my good name, my character, and my aims) suffice to take from me the trust of, and therewith the possibility of obtaining, pupils.
In
1886, Nietzsche broke with his publisher Ernst Schmeitzner, disgusted
by his antisemitic opinions. Nietzsche saw his own writings as
"completely buried and unexhumeable in this anti-Semitic dump" of
Schmeitzner—associating the publisher with a movement that should be
"utterly rejected with cold contempt by every sensible mind." He then printed Beyond Good and Evil
at his own expense. He also acquired the publication rights for his
earlier works and over the next year issued second editions of The Birth of Tragedy, Human, All Too Human, Daybreak, and of The Gay Science
with new prefaces placing the body of his work in a more coherent
perspective. Thereafter, he saw his work as completed for a time and
hoped that soon a readership would develop. In fact, interest in
Nietzsche's thought did increase at this time, if rather slowly and
hardly perceptibly to him. During these years Nietzsche met Meta von Salis, Carl Spitteler, and Gottfried Keller.
In 1886, his sister Elisabeth married the antisemite Bernhard Förster and travelled to Paraguay to found Nueva Germania, a "Germanic" colony—a plan Nietzsche responded to with mocking laughter.
Through correspondence, Nietzsche's relationship with Elisabeth
continued through cycles of conflict and reconciliation, but they met
again only after his collapse. He continued to have frequent and painful
attacks of illness, which made prolonged work impossible.
In 1887, Nietzsche wrote the polemic On the Genealogy of Morality. During the same year, he encountered the work of Fyodor Dostoyevsky, to whom he felt an immediate kinship.[79] He also exchanged letters with Hippolyte Taine and Georg Brandes. Brandes, who had started to teach the philosophy of Søren Kierkegaard in the 1870s, wrote to Nietzsche asking him to read Kierkegaard, to which Nietzsche replied that he would come to Copenhagen
and read Kierkegaard with him. However, before fulfilling this promise,
he slipped too far into illness. In the beginning of 1888, Brandes
delivered in Copenhagen one of the first lectures on Nietzsche's
philosophy.
Although Nietzsche had previously announced at the end of On the Genealogy of Morality a new work with the title The Will to Power: Attempt at a Revaluation of All Values, he eventually seems to have abandoned this idea and instead used some of the draft passages to compose Twilight of the Idols and The Antichrist in 1888.
His health seemed to improve and he spent the summer in high
spirits. In the fall of 1888, his writings and letters began to reveal a
higher estimation of his own status and "fate". He overestimated the
increasing response to his writings, however, especially to the recent
polemic, The Case of Wagner. On his 44th birthday, after completing Twilight of the Idols and The Antichrist, he decided to write the autobiography Ecce Homo.
In its preface—which suggests Nietzsche was well aware of the
interpretive difficulties his work would generate—he declares, "Hear me!
For I am such and such a person. Above all, do not mistake me for
someone else." In December, Nietzsche began a correspondence with August Strindberg
and thought that, short of an international breakthrough, he would
attempt to buy back his older writings from the publisher and have them
translated into other European languages. Moreover, he planned the
publication of the compilation Nietzsche contra Wagner and of the poems that made up his collection Dionysian-Dithyrambs.
Mental illness and death (1889–1900)
On 3 January 1889, Nietzsche suffered a mental breakdown. Two policemen approached him after he caused a public disturbance in the streets of .
What happened remains unknown, but an often-repeated tale from shortly
after his death states that Nietzsche witnessed the flogging of a horse
at the other end of the Piazza Carlo Alberto, ran to the horse, threw
his arms around its neck to protect it, then collapsed to the ground.
In the following few days, Nietzsche sent short writings—known as the Wahnzettel ("Madness Letters")—to a number of friends including Cosima Wagner and Jacob Burckhardt. Most of them were signed "Dionysus",
though some were also signed "der Gekreuzigte" meaning "the crucified
one". To his former colleague Burckhardt, Nietzsche wrote:
I have had Caiaphas put in fetters. Also, last year I was crucified by the German doctors in a very drawn-out manner. Wilhelm, Bismarck, and all anti-Semites abolished.
Additionally,
he commanded the German emperor to go to Rome to be shot and summoned
the European powers to take military action against Germany,
that the pope should be put in jail and that he, Nietzsche, created the
world and was in the process of having all anti-Semites shot dead.
On 6 January 1889, Burckhardt showed the letter he had received
from Nietzsche to Overbeck. The following day, Overbeck received a
similar letter and decided that Nietzsche's friends had to bring him
back to Basel. Overbeck traveled to Turin and brought Nietzsche to a
psychiatric clinic in Basel. By that time Nietzsche appeared fully in
the grip of a serious mental illness, and his mother Franziska decided to transfer him to a clinic in Jena under the direction of Otto Binswanger. In January 1889, they proceeded with the planned release of Twilight of the Idols, by that time already printed and bound. From November 1889 to February 1890, the art historian Julius Langbehn
attempted to cure Nietzsche, claiming that the methods of the medical
doctors were ineffective in treating Nietzsche's condition.
Langbehn assumed progressively greater control of Nietzsche until his
secretiveness discredited him. In March 1890, Franziska removed
Nietzsche from the clinic and, in May 1890, brought him to her home in
Naumburg.
During this process Overbeck and Gast contemplated what to do with
Nietzsche's unpublished works. In February, they ordered a fifty-copy
private edition of Nietzsche contra Wagner, but the publisher C. G. Naumann secretly printed one hundred. Overbeck and Gast decided to withhold publishing The Antichrist and Ecce Homo because of their more radical content. Nietzsche's reception and recognition enjoyed their first surge.
In 1893, Nietzsche's sister Elisabeth returned from Nueva Germania
in Paraguay following the suicide of her husband. She read and studied
Nietzsche's works and, piece by piece, took control of them and their
publication. Overbeck eventually suffered dismissal and Gast finally
co-operated. After the death of Franziska in 1897, Nietzsche lived in Weimar, where Elisabeth cared for him and allowed visitors, including Rudolf Steiner (who in 1895 had written Friedrich Nietzsche: a Fighter Against His Time, one of the first books praising Nietzsche),
to meet her uncommunicative brother. Elisabeth at one point went so far
as to employ Steiner as a tutor to help her to understand her brother's
philosophy. Steiner abandoned the attempt after only a few months,
declaring that it was impossible to teach her anything about philosophy.
Nietzsche's mental illness was originally diagnosed as tertiary syphilis,
in accordance with a prevailing medical paradigm of the time. Although
most commentators regard his breakdown as unrelated to his philosophy, Georges Bataille dropped dark hints ("'Man incarnate' must also go mad") and René Girard's postmortem psychoanalysis posits a worshipful rivalry with Richard Wagner.
Nietzsche had previously written, "All superior men who were
irresistibly drawn to throw off the yoke of any kind of morality and to
frame new laws had, if they were not actually mad, no alternative but to
make themselves or pretend to be mad." (Daybreak, 14) The diagnosis of
syphilis has since been challenged and a diagnosis of "manic-depressive illness with periodic psychosis followed by vascular dementia" was put forward by Cybulska prior to Schain's study. Leonard Sax suggested the slow growth of a right-sided retro-orbital meningioma as an explanation of Nietzsche's dementia; Orth and Trimble postulated frontotemporal dementia while other researchers have proposed a hereditary stroke disorder called CADASIL. Poisoning by mercury, a treatment for syphilis at the time of Nietzsche's death, has also been suggested.
In 1898 and 1899, Nietzsche suffered at least two strokes. This
partially paralyzed him, leaving him unable to speak or walk. He likely
suffered from clinical hemiparesis/hemiplegia on the left side of his body by 1899. After contracting pneumonia in mid-August 1900, he had another stroke during the night of 24–25 August and died at about noon on 25 August. Elisabeth had him buried beside his father at the church in Röcken bei Lützen. His friend and secretary Gast gave his funeral oration, proclaiming: "Holy be your name to all future generations!"
Elisabeth Förster-Nietzsche compiled The Will to Power
from Nietzsche's unpublished notebooks and published it posthumously.
Because his sister arranged the book based on her own conflation of
several of Nietzsche's early outlines and took great liberties with the
material, the scholarly consensus has been that it does not reflect
Nietzsche's intent. (For example, Elisabeth removed aphorism 35 of The Antichrist, where Nietzsche rewrote a passage of the Bible.) Indeed, Mazzino Montinari, the editor of Nietzsche's Nachlass, called it a forgery.
Citizenship, nationality and ethnicity
General
commentators and Nietzsche scholars, whether emphasizing this cultural
baground or his language, overwhelmingly label Nietzsche as a "German
philosopher. "Others do not assign him a national category. Germany had not yet been unified into a nation-state, but Nietzsche was born a citizen of Prussia, which was then part of the German Confederation. His birthplace, Röcken, is in the modern German state of Saxony-Anhalt. When he accepted his post at Basel, Nietzsche applied for the annulment of his Prussian citizenship. The official response confirming the revocation of his citizenship came in a document dated 17 April 1869, and for the rest of his life he remained officially stateless.
Nietzsche believed his ancestors were Polish, at least toward the end of his life. He wore a signet ring bearing the Radwan coat of arms, traceable back to Polish nobility of medieval times and the surname "Nicki" of the Polish noble (szlachta) family bearing that coat of arms. Gotard Nietzsche, a member of the Nicki family, left Poland for Prussia. His descendants later settled in the Electorate of Saxony circa the year 1700.
Nietzsche wrote in 1888, "My ancestors were Polish noblemen (Nietzky);
the type seems to have been well preserved despite three generations of
German mothers."
At one point, Nietzsche becomes even more adamant about his Polish
identity. "I am a pure-blooded Polish nobleman, without a single drop of
bad blood, certainly not German blood."
On yet another occasion, Nietzsche stated, "Germany is a great nation
only because its people have so much Polish blood in their veins… I am
proud of my Polish descent." Nietzsche believed his name might have been Germanized,
in one letter claiming, "I was taught to ascribe the origin of my blood
and name to Polish noblemen who were called Niëtzky and left their home
and nobleness about a hundred years ago, finally yielding to unbearable
suppression: they were Protestants."
Most scholars dispute Nietzsche's account of his family's
origins. Hans von Müller debunked the genealogy put forward by
Nietzsche's sister in favor of a Polish noble heritage. Max Oehler, Nietzsche's cousin and curator of the Nietzsche Archive at Weimar, argued that all of Nietzsche's ancestors bore German names, including the wives' families. Oehler claims that Nietzsche came from a long line of German Lutheran
clergymen on both sides of his family, and modern scholars regard the
claim of Nietzsche's Polish ancestry as a "pure invention."
Colli and Montinari, the editors of Nietzsche's assembled letters,
gloss Nietzsche's claims as a "mistaken belief" and "without
foundation." The name Nietzsche itself is not a Polish name, but an exceptionally common one throughout central Germany, in this and cognate forms (such as Nitsche and Nitzke). The name derives from the forename Nikolaus, abbreviated to Nick; assimilated with the Slavic Nitz, it first became Nitsche and then Nietzsche.
Relationships and sexuality
Nietzsche never married. He proposed to Lou Salomé three times and each time was rejected.
One theory blames Salomé's view on sexuality as one of the reasons for
her alienation from Nietzsche. As articulated in the 1898 novella Fenitschka, she viewed the idea of sexual intercourse as prohibitive and marriage as a violation, with some suggesting that they indicated sexual repression and neurosis . Reflecting on unrequited love,
Nietzsche considered that "indispensable…to the lover is his unrequited
love, which he would at no price relinquish for a state of
indifference."
Deussen cited the episode of Cologne's
brothel in February 1865 as instrumental to understand the
philosopher's way of thinking, mostly about women. Nietzsche was
surreptitiously accompanied to a "call house" from which he clumsily
escaped upon seeing "a half dozen apparitions dressed with sequins and
veils." According to Deussen, Nietzsche "never decided to remain
unmarried all his life. For him women had to sacrifice themselves to the
care and benefit of men." Nietzsche scholar Joachim Köhler
has attempted to explain Nietzsche's life history and philosophy by
claiming that he was homosexual. Köhler argues that Nietzsche's
syphilis, which is "... usually considered to be the product of his encounter with a prostitute in a brothel in Cologne or Leipzig, is equally likely. Some maintain that Nietzsche contracted it in a male brothel in Genoa." The acquisition of the infection from a homosexual brothel was confirmed by Sigmund Freud, who cited Otto Binswanger as his source. Köhler also suggests Nietzsche may have had a romantic relationship, as well as a friendship, with Paul Rée. There is the claim that Nietzsche's homosexuality was widely known in the Vienna Psychoanalytic Society, with Nietzsche's friend Paul Deussen claiming that "he was a man who had never touched a woman."
Köhler's views have not found wide acceptance among Nietzsche
scholars and commentators. Allan Megill argues that, while Köhler's
claim that Nietzsche was conflicted about his homosexual desire cannot
simply be dismissed, "the evidence is very weak," and Köhler may be
projecting twentieth-century understandings of sexuality on
nineteenth-century notions of friendship.It is also known that Nietzsche frequented heterosexual brothels. Nigel Rodgers and Mel Thompson
have argued that continuous sickness and headaches hindered Nietzsche
from engaging much with women. Yet they offer other examples in which
Nietzsche expressed his affections to women, including Wagner's wife Cosima Wagner.
Other scholars have, However. Tthere are also those who stress that, if Nietzsche preferred men—with this preference constituting his psycho-sexual make-up—but could not admit his desires to himself, it meant he acted in conflict with his philosophy.
Composer
Nietzsche
composed several works for voice, piano, and violin beginning in 1858
at the Schulpforta in Naumburg, when he started to work on musical
compositions. Richard Wagner
was dismissive of Nietzsche's music, allegedly mocking a birthday gift
of a piano composition sent by Nietzsche in 1871 to his wife Cosima. German conductor and pianist Hans von Bülow
also described another of Nietzsche's pieces as "the most undelightful
and the most antimusical draft on musical paper that I have faced in a
long time."
In a letter of 1887, Nietzsche claimed, "There has never been a
philosopher who has been in essence a musician to such an extent as I
am," although he also admitted that he "might be a thoroughly
unsuccessful musician."
Philosophy
Because of Nietzsche's evocative
style and provocative ideas, his philosophy generates passionate
reactions. His works remain controversial, due to their varying
interpretations and misinterpretations. In the Western philosophy
tradition, Nietzsche's writings have been described as the unique case
of free revolutionary thought, that is, revolutionary in its structure
and problems, although not tied to any revolutionary project.
His writings have also been described as a revolutionary project in
which his philosophy serves as the foundation of a European cultural
rebirth.
Apollonian and Dionysian
The Apollonian and Dionysian is a two-fold philosophical concept, based on certain features of ancient Greek mythology: Apollo and Dionysus. Even though the concept is famously related to The Birth of Tragedy, the poet Hölderlin had already spoken of it, and Winckelmann had talked of Bacchus. One year before the publication of The Birth of Tragedy, Nietzsche wrote a fragment titled "On Music and Words". In it, he asserted the Schopenhauerian judgment that music is a primary expression of the essence of everything. Secondarily derivative are lyrical poetry and drama, which represent mere phenomenal appearances of objects. In this way, tragedy is born from music.
Nietzsche found in classical Athenian tragedy an art form that transcended the pessimism found in the so-called wisdom of Silenus.
The Greek spectators, by looking into the abyss of human suffering
depicted by characters on stage, passionately and joyously affirmed
life, finding it worth living. A main theme in The Birth of Tragedy was that the fusion of Dionysian and Apollonian Kunsttrieben
("artistic impulses") forms dramatic arts, or tragedies. He goes on to
argue that this fusion has not been achieved since the ancient Greek tragedians.
Apollo represents harmony, progress, clarity, and logic, whereas
Dionysus represents disorder, intoxication, emotion, and ecstasy.
Nietzsche used these two forces because, for him, the world of mind and
order on one side, and passion and chaos on the other, formed principles
that were fundamental to the Greek culture:
the Apollonian side being a dreaming state, full of illusions; and
Dionysian being the state of intoxication, representing the liberations
of instinct and dissolution of boundaries. In this mold, man appears as
the satyr. He is the horror of the annihilation of the principle of individuality and at the same time someone who delights in its destruction. Both of these principles are meant to represent cognitive states that appear through art as the power of nature in man.
Apollonian and Dionysian juxtapositions appear in the interplay
of tragedy: the tragic hero of the drama, the main protagonist,
struggles to make (Apollonian) order of his unjust and chaotic
(Dionysian) fate, though he dies unfulfilled. Elaborating on the
conception of Hamlet as an intellectual who cannot make up his mind, and therefore is a living antithesis
to the man of action, Nietzsche argues that a Dionysian figure
possesses knowledge to realize that his actions cannot change the
eternal balance of things, and it disgusts him enough not to be able to
act at all. Hamlet falls under this category—he has glimpsed the
supernatural reality through the Ghost, he has gained true knowledge and
knows that no action of his has the power to change this. For the audience of such drama, this tragedy allows them to sense what Nietzsche called the Primordial Unity,
which revives Dionysian nature. He describes primordial unity as the
increase of strength, experience of fullness and plenitude bestowed by frenzy. Frenzy acts as an intoxication, and is crucial for the physiological condition that enables the creation of any art. Stimulated by this state, a person's artistic will is enhanced:
In this state one enriches everything out of one's own fullness: whatever one sees, whatever wills is seen swelled, taut, strong, overloaded with strength. A man in this state transforms things until they mirror his power—until they are reflections of his perfection. This having to transform into perfection is—art.
Nietzsche is adamant that the works of Aeschylus and Sophocles represent the apex of artistic creation, the true realization of tragedy; it is with Euripides, he states, that tragedy begins its Untergang
(literally 'going under' or 'downward-way;' meaning decline,
deterioration, downfall, death, etc.). Nietzsche objects to Euripides'
use of Socratic rationalism and morality in his tragedies, claiming that the infusion of ethics and reason robs tragedy of its foundation, namely the fragile balance of the Dionysian and Apollonian. Socrates emphasized reason to such a degree that he diffused the value of myth and suffering to human knowledge. Plato
continued along this path in his dialogues, and the modern world
eventually inherited reason at the expense of artistic impulses that
could be found only in the Apollonian and Dionysus dichotomy. This leads
to his conclusion that European culture from the time of Socrates had
always been only Apollonian, thus decadent and unhealthy.
He notes that whenever Apollonian culture dominates, the Dionysian
lacks the structure to make a coherent art, and when Dionysian
dominates, the Apollonian lacks the necessary passion. Only the fertile
interplay of these two forces, brought together as an art, represented
the best of Greek tragedy.
An example of the impact of this idea can be seen in the book Patterns of Culture, where anthropologist Ruth Benedict acknowledges Nietzschean opposites of "Apollonian" and "Dionysian" as the stimulus for her thoughts about Native American cultures. Carl Jung has written extensively on the dichotomy in Psychological Types. Michel Foucault has commented that his own book Madness and Civilization
should be read "under the sun of the great Nietzschean inquiry". Here
Foucault references Nietzsche's description of the birth and death of
tragedy and his explanation that the subsequent tragedy of the Western
world was the refusal of the tragic and, with that, refusal of the
sacred. Painter Mark Rothko was influenced by Nietzsche's view of tragedy, which were presented in The Birth of Tragedy.
Perspectivism
Nietzsche claimed the death of God would eventually lead to the loss
of any universal perspective on things, and along with it any coherent
sense of objective truth. Nietzsche himself rejected the idea of objective reality, arguing that knowledge is contingent and conditional, relative to various fluid perspectives or interests.
This leads to constant reassessment of rules (i.e., those of
philosophy, the scientific method, etc.) according to the circumstances
of individual perspectives. This view has acquired the name perspectivism.
In Also sprach Zarathustra,
Nietzsche proclaims that a table of values hangs above every great
person. He points out that what is common among different peoples is the
act of esteeming, of creating values, even if the values are different
from one people to the next. Nietzsche asserts that what made people
great was not the content of their beliefs, but the act of valuing. Thus
the values a community strives to articulate are not as important as
the collective will to see those values come to pass. The willing is
more essential than the merit of the goal itself, according to
Nietzsche. "A thousand goals have there been so far", says Zarathustra,
"for there are a thousand peoples. Only the yoke for the thousand necks
is still lacking: the one goal is lacking. Humanity still has no goal."
Hence, the title of the aphorism, "On The Thousand And One Goals". The
idea that one value-system is no more worthy than the next, although it
may not be directly ascribed to Nietzsche, has become a common premise
in modern social science. Max Weber and Martin Heidegger
absorbed it and made it their own. It shaped their philosophical and
cultural endeavor, as well as their political understanding. Weber, for
example, relies on Nietzsche's perspectivism by maintaining that
objectivity is still possible—but only after a particular perspective,
value, or end has been established.
Among his critique of traditional philosophy of Kant, Descartes and Plato in Beyond Good and Evil, Nietzsche attacked thing in itself and cogito ergo sum ("I think, therefore I am") as unfalsifiable beliefs based on naive acceptance of previous notions and fallacies. Philosopher Alasdair MacIntyre
puts Nietzsche in a high place in the history of philosophy. While
criticizing nihilism and Nietzsche together as a sign of general decay, he still commends him for recognizing psychological motives behind Kant and Hume's moral philosophy:
For it was Nietzsche's historic achievement to understand more clearly than any other philosopher…not only that what purported to be appeals of objectivity were in fact expressions of subjective will, but also the nature of the problems that this posed for philosophy.
The "slave revolt" in morals
In Beyond Good and Evil and On the Genealogy of Morality, Nietzsche's genealogical
account of the development of modern moral systems occupies a central
place. For Nietzsche, a fundamental shift took place during human
history from thinking in terms of "good and bad" toward "good and evil."
The initial form of morality was set by a warrior aristocracy
and other ruling castes of ancient civilizations. Aristocratic values
of good and bad coincided with and reflected their relationship to lower
castes such as slaves. Nietzsche presents this "master morality" as the original system of morality—perhaps best associated with Homeric Greece. To be "good" was to be happy and to have the things related to
happiness: wealth, strength, health, power, etc. To be "bad" was to be
like the slaves over whom the aristocracy ruled: poor, weak, sick,
pathetic—objects of pity or disgust rather than hatred.
"Slave morality" developed as a reaction to master morality.
Here, value emerges from the contrast between good and evil: good being
associated with other-worldliness, charity, piety, restraint, meekness,
and submission; while evil is worldly, cruel, selfish, wealthy, and
aggressive. Nietzsche sees slave morality as pessimistic and fearful,
its values emerging to improve the self-perception of slaves. He
associates slave morality with the Jewish and Christian traditions, as
it is born out of the ressentiment
of slaves. Nietzsche argued that the idea of equality allowed slaves to
overcome their own condition without despising themselves. And by
denying the inherent inequality of people—in success, strength, beauty,
and intelligence—slaves acquired a method of escape, namely by
generating new values on the basis of rejecting master morality, which
frustrated them. It was used to overcome the slave's own sense of
inferiority before their (better-off) masters. It does so by making out
slave weakness, for example, to be a matter of choice, by relabeling it
as "meekness". The "good man" of master morality is precisely the "evil
man" of slave morality, while the "bad man" is recast as the "good man".
Nietzsche sees slave morality as a source of the nihilism that
has overtaken Europe. Modern Europe and Christianity exist in a
hypocritical state due to a tension between master and slave morality,
both contradictory values determining, to varying degrees, the values of
most Europeans (who are "motley").
Nietzsche calls for exceptional people to no longer be ashamed in the
face of a supposed morality-for-all, which he deems to be harmful to the
flourishing of exceptional people. He cautions, however, that morality,
per se, is not bad; it is good for the masses, and should be left to
them. Exceptional people, on the other hand, should follow their own
"inner law". A favorite motto of Nietzsche, taken from Pindar, reads: "Become what you are."
A long-standing assumption about Nietzsche is that he preferred master over slave morality. However, eminent Nietzsche scholar Walter Kaufmann rejected this interpretation, writing that Nietzsche's analyses of these two types of morality were used only in a descriptive and historic sense; they were not meant for any kind of acceptance or glorification.
On the other hand, it is clear from his own writings that Nietzsche
hoped for the victory of master morality. He linked the "salvation and
future of the human race with the unconditional dominance"
of master morality and called master morality "a higher order of
values, the noble ones, those that say Yes to life, those that guarantee
the future." Just as "there is an order of rank between man and man", there is also an order of rank "between morality and morality."
Indeed, Nietzsche waged a philosophic war against the slave morality of
Christianity in his "revaluation of all values" in order to bring about
the victory of a new master morality that he called the "philosophy of
the future" (Beyond Good and Evil is subtitled Prelude to a Philosophy of the Future).
In Daybreak, Nietzsche begins his "Campaign against Morality". He calls himself an "immoralist" and harshly criticizes the prominent moral philosophies of his day: Christianity, Kantianism, and utilitarianism. Nietzsche's concept "God is dead" applies to the doctrines of Christendom, though not to all other faiths: he claimed that Buddhism is a successful religion that he compliments for fostering critical thought. Still, Nietzsche saw his philosophy as a counter-movement to nihilism through appreciation of art:
Art as the single superior counterforce against all will to negation of life, art as the anti-Christian, anti-Buddhist, anti-Nihilist par excellence.
Nietzsche claimed that the Christian faith as practiced was not a
proper representation of Jesus' teachings, as it forced people merely to
believe in the way of Jesus but not to act as Jesus did; in particular,
his example of refusing to judge people, something that Christians had
constantly done. He condemned institutionalized Christianity for emphasizing a morality of pity (Mitleid), which assumes an inherent illness in society:
Christianity is called the religion of pity. Pity stands opposed to the tonic emotions which heighten our vitality: it has a depressing effect. We are deprived of strength when we feel pity. That loss of strength which suffering as such inflicts on life is still further increased and multiplied by pity. Pity makes suffering contagious.
In Ecce Homo Nietzsche called the establishment of moral systems based on a dichotomy of good and evil a "calamitous error", and wished to initiate a re-evaluation of the values of the Judeo-Christian world. He indicates his desire to bring about a new, more naturalistic source of value in the vital impulses of life itself.
While Nietzsche attacked the principles of Judaism, he was not antisemitic: in his work On the Genealogy of Morality,
he explicitly condemns antisemitism, and points out that his attack on
Judaism was not an attack on contemporary Jewish people but specifically
an attack upon the ancient Jewish priesthood who he claims antisemitic Christians paradoxically based their views upon.
An Israeli historian who performed a statistical analysis of everything
Nietzsche wrote about Jews claims that cross-references and context
make clear that almost all (85%) negative comments are actually attacks
on Christian doctrine or, sarcastically, on Richard Wagner.
Nietzsche felt that modern antisemitism was "despicable" and contrary to European ideals. Its cause, in his opinion, was the growth in European nationalism and the endemic "jealousy and hatred" of Jewish success. He wrote that Jews should be thanked for helping uphold a respect for the philosophies of ancient Greece, and for giving rise to "the noblest human being (Christ), the purest philosopher (Baruch Spinoza), the mightiest book, and the most effective moral code in the world."
Death of God and nihilism
The statement "God is dead," occurring in several of Nietzsche's works (notably in The Gay Science), has become one of his best-known remarks. On the basis of it, most commentators regard Nietzsche as an atheist;
others (such as Kaufmann) suggest that this statement reflects a more
subtle understanding of divinity. Recent developments in modern science
and the increasing secularization of European society had effectively 'killed' the Abrahamic
God, who had served as the basis for meaning and value in the West for
more than a thousand years. The death of God may lead beyond bare
perspectivism to outright nihilism,
the belief that nothing has any inherent importance and that life lacks
purpose. Here he states that the Christian moral doctrine provides
people with intrinsic value, belief in God (which justifies the evil in the world) and a basis for objective knowledge.
In this sense, in constructing a world where objective knowledge is
possible, Christianity is an antidote to a primal form of nihilism—the
despair of meaninglessness. As Heidegger
put the problem, "If God as the suprasensory ground and goal of all
reality is dead, if the suprasensory world of the ideas has suffered the
loss of its obligatory and above it its vitalizing and upbuilding
power, then nothing more remains to which man can cling and by which he
can orient himself."
One such reaction to the loss of meaning is what Nietzsche calls passive nihilism, which he recognizes in the pessimistic philosophy of Schopenhauer. Schopenhauer's doctrine—which Nietzsche also refers to as Western Buddhism—advocates separating oneself from will and desires in order to reduce suffering. Nietzsche characterizes this ascetic
attitude as a "will to nothingness", whereby life turns away from
itself, as there is nothing of value to be found in the world. This
moving away of all value in the world is characteristic of the nihilist,
although in this, the nihilist appears to be inconsistent; this "will
to nothingness" is still a (disavowed) form of willing.
A nihilist is a man who judges that the real world ought not to be, and that the world as it ought to be does not exist. According to this view, our existence (action, suffering, willing, feeling) has no meaning: this 'in vain' is the nihilists' pathos—an inconsistency on the part of the nihilists.
— Friedrich Nietzsche, KSA 12:9 [60], taken from The Will to Power, section 585, translated by Walter Kaufmann
Nietzsche approaches the problem of nihilism as a deeply personal
one, stating that this problem of the modern world has "become
conscious" in him.
Furthermore, he emphasizes both the danger of nihilism and the
possibilities it offers, as seen in his statement that "I praise, I do
not reproach, [nihilism's] arrival. I believe it is one of the greatest
crises, a moment of the deepest self-reflection of humanity. Whether man
recovers from it, whether he becomes master of this crisis, is a
question of his strength!" According to Nietzsche, it is only when nihilism is overcome
that a culture can have a true foundation on which to thrive. He wished
to hasten its coming only so that he could also hasten its ultimate
departure. Heidegger interprets the death of God with what he explains
as the death of metaphysics.
He concludes that metaphysics has reached its potential and that the
ultimate fate and downfall of metaphysics was proclaimed with the
statement "God is dead."
Will to power
A basic element in Nietzsche's philosophical outlook is the "will to power" (der Wille zur Macht),
which he maintained provides a basis for understanding human
behavior—more so than competing explanations, such as the ones based on
pressure for adaptation or survival.
As such, according to Nietzsche, the drive for conservation appears as
the major motivator of human or animal behavior only in exceptions, as
the general condition of life is not one of emergency, of 'struggle for
existence.' More often than not, self-conservation is but a consequence of a creature's will to exert its strength on the outside world.
In presenting his theory of human behavior, Nietzsche also
addressed, and attacked, concepts from philosophies popularly embraced
in his days, such as Schopenhauer's notion of an aimless will or that of
utilitarianism.
Utilitarians claim that what moves people is mainly the desire to be
happy, to accumulate pleasure in their lives. But such a conception of
happiness Nietzsche rejected as something limited to, and characteristic
of, the bourgeois lifestyle of the English society, and instead put forth the idea that happiness is not an aim per se—it
is instead a consequence of a successful pursuit of one's aims, of the
overcoming of hurdles to one's actions—in other words, of the
fulfillment of the will.
Related to his theory of the will to power is his speculation, which he did not deem final,
regarding the reality of the physical world, including inorganic
matter—that, like man's affections and impulses, the material world is
also set by the dynamics of a form of the will to power. At the core of
his theory is a rejection of atomism—the idea that matter is composed of stable, indivisible units (atoms). Instead, he seems to have accepted the conclusions of Ruđer Bošković, who explained the qualities of matter as a result of an interplay of forces.
One study of Nietzsche defines his fully developed concept of the will
to power as "the element from which derive both the quantitative
difference of related forces and the quality that devolves into each
force in this relation" revealing the will to power as "the principle of
the synthesis of forces."Of such forces Nietzsche said they could perhaps be viewed as a
primitive form of the will. Likewise he rejected as a mere
interpretation the view that the movement of bodies is ruled by
inexorable laws of nature, positing instead that movement was governed
by the power relations between bodies and forces.
Other scholars disagree that Nietzsche considered the material world to
be a form of the will to power: Nietzsche thoroughly criticized
metaphysics, and by including the will to power in the material world,
he would simply be setting up a new metaphysics. Other than Aphorism 36
in Beyond Good and Evil, where he raised a question regarding
will to power as being in the material world, they argue, it was only in
his notes (unpublished by himself), where he wrote about a metaphysical
will to power. And they also claim that Nietzsche directed his landlord
to burn those notes in 1888 when he left Sils Maria for the last time. According to these scholars, the 'burning' story supports their thesis
that at the end of his lucid life, Nietzsche rejected his project on the
will to power. However, a recent study (Huang 2019) shows that although
it is true that in 1888 Nietzsche wanted some of his notes burned, the
'burning' story indicates little about his project on the will to power,
not only because only 11 'aphorisms' saved from the flames were
ultimately incorporated into The Will to Power (this book
contains 1067 'aphorisms'), but also because these abandoned notes
mainly focus on topics such as critique of morality while touching upon
the 'feeling of power' only once.
Eternal return
"Eternal return" (also known as "eternal recurrence") is a
hypothetical concept that posits that the universe has been recurring,
and will continue to recur, in a self-similar form for an infinite
number of times across infinite time or space. It is a purely physical concept, involving no supernatural ,
but the return of beings in the same bodies. Nietzsche first invokes
the idea of eternal return in a parable in Section 341 of , and also in the chapter "Of the Vision and the Riddle" in, among
individual, hence "And thus it will
happen one day that a man will be born again, just like me and a woman
will be born, just like Mary—only that it is hoped to be that the head
of this man may contain a little less foolishness …."
Alexander Nehamas writes in Nietzsche: Life as Literature of three ways of seeing the eternal recurrence:
- "My life will recur in exactly identical fashion:" this expresses a totally fatalistic approach to the idea;
- "My life may recur in exactly identical fashion:" this second view conditionally asserts cosmology, but fails to capture what Nietzsche refers to in The Gay Science, p. 341; and finally,
- "If my life were to recur, then it could recur only in identical fashion." Nehamas shows that this interpretation exists totally independently of physics and does not presuppose the truth of cosmology.
Nehamas draws the conclusion that if individuals constitute
themselves through their actions, then they can only maintain themselves
in their current state by living in a recurrence of past actions
(Nehamas, 153). Nietzsche's thought is the negation of the idea of a
history of salvation.
Übermensch
Another concept important to an understanding of Nietzsche's thought is the Übermensch. Developing the idea of nihilism, Nietzsche wrote Also sprach Zarathustra,
therein introducing the concept of a value-creating Übermensch, not as a
project, but as an anti-project, the absence of any project. According to Laurence Lampert,
"the death of God must be followed by a long twilight of piety and
nihilism (II. 19; III. 8). Zarathustra's gift of the overman is given to
a mankind not aware of the problem to which the overman is the
solution."
Zarathustra presents the overman as the creator of new values, and he
appears as a solution to the problem of the death of God and nihilism.
The overman does not follow the morality of common people since that
favors mediocrity but instead rises above the notion of good and evil and above the "herd".
In this way Zarathustra proclaims his ultimate goal as the journey
towards the state of overman. He wants a kind of spiritual evolution of
self-awareness and overcoming of traditional views on morality and
justice that stem from the superstition beliefs still deeply rooted or related to the notion of God and Christianity.
While interpretations of Nietzsche's overman vary wildly, here is one of his quotations from Thus Spoke Zarathustra (Prologue, §§ 3–4):
I teach you the overman. Man is something that shall be overcome. What have you done to overcome him? ... All beings so far have created something beyond themselves; and do you want to be the ebb of this great flood, and even go back to the beasts rather than overcome man? What is ape to man? A laughing stock or painful embarrassment. And man shall be that to overman: a laughing stock or painful embarrassment. You have made your way from worm to man, and much in you is still worm. Once you were apes, and even now, too, man is more ape than any ape ... The overman is the meaning of the earth. Let your will say: the overman shall be the meaning of the earth ... Man is a rope, tied between beast and overman—a rope over an abyss ... what is great in man is that he is a bridge and not an end.
Zarathustra contrasts the overman with the
of egalitarian modernity (most obvious example being democracy), an
alternative goal humanity might set for itself. The last man is possible
only by mankind's having bred an apathetic
creature who has no great passion or commitment, who is unable to
dream, who merely earns his living and keeps warm. This concept appears
only in Thus Spoke Zarathustra, and is presented as a condition that would render the creation of the overman impossible.
Some have suggested that the notion of eternal return is related
to the overman, since willing the eternal return of the same is a
necessary step if the overman is to create new values, untainted by the
spirit of gravity or asceticism.
Values involve a rank-ordering of things, and so are inseparable from
approval and disapproval; yet it was dissatisfaction that prompted men
to seek refuge in other-worldliness and embrace other-worldly values. It
could seem that the overman, in being devoted to any values at all,
would necessarily fail to create values that did not share some bit of
asceticism. Willing the eternal recurrence is presented as accepting the
existence of the low while still recognizing it as the low, and thus as
overcoming the spirit of gravity or asceticism. One must have the
strength of the overman in order to will the eternal recurrence; that
is, only the overman will have the strength to fully accept all of his
past life, including his failures and misdeeds, and to truly will their
eternal return. This action nearly kills Zarathustra, for example, and
most human beings cannot avoid other-worldliness because they really are
sick, not because of any choice they made.
The Nazis tried to incorporate the concept into their ideology. After his death, Elisabeth Förster-Nietzsche became the curator and editor of her brother's manuscripts. She reworked Nietzsche's unpublished writings to fit her own German nationalist ideology while often contradicting or obfuscating Nietzsche's stated opinions, which were explicitly opposed to antisemitism and nationalism. Through her published editions, Nietzsche's work became associated with fascism and Nazism; 20th century scholars contested this interpretation of his work, and
corrected editions of his writings were soon made available.
Although Nietzsche has famously been misrepresented as a predecessor to Nazism, he criticized anti-Semitism, pan-Germanism and, to a lesser extent, nationalism. Thus, he broke with his editor in 1886 because of his opposition to his editor's anti-Semitic stances, and his rupture with Richard Wagner, expressed in The Case of Wagner and Nietzsche contra Wagner,
both of which he wrote in 1888, had much to do with Wagner's
endorsement of pan-Germanism and anti-Semitism—and also of his rallying
to Christianity. In a 29 March 1887 letter to Theodor Fritsch, Nietzsche mocked anti-Semites, Fritsch, Eugen Dühring, Wagner, Ebrard, Wahrmund, and the leading advocate of pan-Germanism, Paul de Lagarde, who would become, along with Wagner and Houston Chamberlain, the main official influences of Nazism. his 1887 letter to Fritsch ended by: "And finally, how do you think I
feel when the name Zarathustra is mouthed by anti-Semites?"
Critique of mass culture
Friedrich
Nietzsche held a pessimistic view on modern society and culture. His
views stand against the concept of popular culture. He believed the
press and mass culture led to conformity and brought about mediocrity.
Nietzsche saw a lack of intellectual progress, leading to the decline of
the human species. According to Nietzsche, individuals needed to
overcome this form of mass culture. He believed some people were able to
become superior individuals through the use of will power. By rising
above mass culture, society would produce higher, brighter and healthier
human beings.
Reading and influence
Nietzsche's philosophy, while innovative and revolutionary, was
indebted to many predecessors. While at Basel, Nietzsche offered lecture
courses on pre-Platonic philosophers for several years, and the text of
this lecture series has been characterized as a "lost link" in the
development of his thought. "In it concepts such as the will to power,
the eternal return of the same, the overman, gay science,
self-overcoming and so on receive rough, unnamed formulations and are
linked to specific pre-Platonics, especially Heraclitus, who emerges as a
pre-Platonic Nietzsche." The pre-Socratic thinker Heraclitus was known for the rejection of the concept of being
as a constant and eternal principle of universe, and his embrace of
"flux" and incessant change. His symbolism of the world as "child play"
marked by amoral spontaneity and lack of definite rules was appreciated
by Nietzsche. From his Heraclitean sympathy, Nietzsche was also a vociferous detractor of Parmenides, who opposed Heraclitus and believed all world is a single Being with no change at all.
Nietzsche expressed admiration for 17th-century French moralists such as La Rochefoucauld, La Bruyère and Vauvenargues, as well as for Stendhal. The organicism of Paul Bourget influenced Nietzsche, as did that of Rudolf Virchow and Alfred Espinas. Nietzsche wrote in a letter in 1867 that he was trying to improve his German style of writing with the help of Lessing, Lichtenberg and Schopenhauer. It was probably Lichtenberg (along with Paul Rée) whose aphoristic style of writing contributed to Nietzsche's own use of aphorism instead of an essay. Nietzsche early learned of Darwinism through Friedrich Albert Lange. The essays of Ralph Waldo Emerson had a profound influence on Nietzsche, who "loved Emerson from first to last",[236]
wrote "Never have I felt so much at home in a book", and called him
"[the] author who has been richest in ideas in this century so far".[237] Hippolyte Taine influenced Nietzsche's view on Rousseau and Napoleon.[238] Notably, he also read some of the posthumous works of Charles Baudelaire,[239] Tolstoy's My Religion, Ernest Renan's Life of Jesus, and Fyodor Dostoyevsky's Demons.[239][240] Nietzsche called Dostoyevsky "the only psychologist from whom I have anything to learn."[241] While Nietzsche never mentions Max Stirner, the similarities in their ideas have prompted a minority of interpreters to suggest a relationship between the two.[242][243][244][245][246][247][248]
In 1861 Nietzsche wrote an enthusiastic essay on his "favorite poet," Friedrich Hölderlin, mostly forgotten at that time.[249] He also expressed deep appreciation for Stifter's Indian Summer,[250] Byron's Manfred and Twain's Tom Sawyer.[251]
Reception and legacy
Nietzsche's works did not reach a wide readership during his active
writing career. However, in 1888 the influential Danish critic Georg Brandes aroused considerable excitement about Nietzsche through a series of lectures he gave at the University of Copenhagen.
In the years after Nietzsche's death in 1900, his works became better
known, and readers have responded to them in complex and sometimes
controversial ways. Many Germans eventually discovered his appeals for greater individualism and personality development in Thus Spoke Zarathustra,
but responded to them divergently. He had some following among
left-wing Germans in the 1890s; in 1894–1895 German conservatives wanted
to ban his work as subversive. During the late 19th century Nietzsche's ideas were commonly associated with anarchist movements and appear to have had influence within them, particularly in France and the United States. Mencken produced the first book on Nietzsche in English in 1907, The Philosophy of Friedrich Nietzsche, and in 1910 a book of translated paragraphs from Nietzsche, increasing knowledge of his philosophy in the United States. Nietzsche is known today as a precursor to existentialism, post-structuralism and postmodernism.
W.B. Yeats and Arthur Symons described Nietzsche as the intellectual heir to William Blake. Symons went on to compare the ideas of the two thinkers in The Symbolist Movement in Literature, while Yeats tried to raise awareness of Nietzsche in Ireland. A similar notion was espoused by W.H. Auden who wrote of Nietzsche in his New Year Letter (released in 1941 in The Double Man): "O masterly debunker of our liberal fallacies…all your life you stormed, like your English forerunner Blake." Nietzsche made an impact on composers during the 1890s. Writer on music Donald Mitchell notes that Gustav Mahler
was "attracted to the poetic fire of Zarathustra, but repelled by the
intellectual core of its writings." He also quotes Mahler himself, and
adds that he was influenced by Nietzsche's conception and affirmative
approach to nature, which Mahler presented in his Third Symphony using Zarathustra's roundelay. Frederick Delius produced a piece of choral music, A Mass of Life, based on a text of Thus Spoke Zarathustra, while Richard Strauss (who also based his Also sprach Zarathustra on the same book), was only interested in finishing "another chapter of symphonic autobiography." Famous writers and poets influenced by Nietzsche include André Gide, August Strindberg, Robinson Jeffers, Pío Baroja, D.H. Lawrence, Edith Södergran and Yukio Mishima.
Nietzsche was an early influence on the poetry of Rainer Maria Rilke. Knut Hamsun counted Nietzsche, along with Strindberg and Dostoyevsky, as one of his primary influences. Author Jack London wrote that he was more stimulated by Nietzsche than by any other writer. Critics have suggested that the character of David Grief in A Son of the Sun was based on Nietzsche. Nietzsche's influence on is most evidenced in Asrar-i-Khudi (The Secrets of the Self). Wallace Stevens was another reader of Nietzsche, and elements of Nietzsche's philosophy were found throughout Stevens's poetry collection Harmonium. Olaf Stapledon was influenced by the idea of the Übermensch and it is a central theme in his books Odd John and Sirius. In Russia, Nietzsche has influenced Russian symbolism and figures such as Dmitry Merezhkovsky, Andrei Bely, Vyacheslav Ivanov and Alexander Scriabin have all incorporated or discussed parts of Nietzsche philosophy in their works. Thomas Mann's novel Death in Venice shows a use of Apollonian and Dionysian, and in Doctor Faustus Nietzsche was a central source for the character of Adrian Leverkühn. Hermann Hesse, similarly, in his Narcissus and Goldmund presents two main characters in the sense of Apollonian and Dionysian as the two opposite yet intertwined spirits. Painter Giovanni Segantini was fascinated by Thus Spoke Zarathustra, and he drew an illustration for the first Italian translation of the book. The Russian painter Lena Hades created the oil painting cycle Also Sprach Zarathustra dedicated to the book Thus Spoke Zarathustra.
By World War I, Nietzsche had acquired a reputation as an inspiration for both right-wing German militarism and leftist politics. German soldiers received copies of Thus Spoke Zarathustra as gifts during World War I. The Dreyfus affair
provides a contrasting example of his reception: the French antisemitic
Right labelled the Jewish and leftist intellectuals who defended Alfred Dreyfus as "Nietzscheans". Nietzsche had a distinct appeal for many Zionist thinkers around the start of the 20th century, most notable being Ahad Ha'am, Hillel Zeitlin, Micha Josef Berdyczewski, A.D. Gordon and Martin Buber, who went so far as to extoll Nietzsche as a "creator" and "emissary of life". Chaim Weizmann
was a great admirer of Nietzsche; the first president of Israel sent
Nietzsche's books to his wife, adding a comment in a letter that "This
was the best and finest thing I can send to you." Israel Eldad, the ideological chief of the Stern Gang that fought the British in Palestine in the 1940s, wrote about Nietzsche in his underground newspaper and later translated most of Nietzsche's books into Hebrew. Eugene O'Neill remarked that Zarathustra influenced him more than any other book he ever read. He also shared Nietzsche's view of tragedy. Plays The Great God Brown and Lazarus Laughed are an example of Nietzsche's influence on O'Neill. Nietzsche's influence on the works of Frankfurt School philosophers Max Horkheimer and Theodor W. Adorno can be seen in the popular Dialectic of Enlightenment. Adorno summed up Nietzsche's philosophy as expressing the "humane in a world in which humanity has become a sham."
Nietzsche's growing prominence suffered a severe setback when his works became closely associated with Adolf Hitler and Nazi Germany.
Many political leaders of the twentieth century were at least
superficially familiar with Nietzsche's ideas, although it is not always
possible to determine whether they actually read his work. It is
debated among scholars whether Hitler read Nietzsche, although if he did
his reading of him may not have been extensive.
He was a frequent visitor to the Nietzsche museum in Weimar and used
expressions of Nietzsche's, such as "lords of the earth" in Mein Kampf. The Nazis made selective use of Nietzsche's philosophy. Mussolini, Charles de Gaulle and Huey P. Newton read Nietzsche. Richard Nixon read Nietzsche with "curious interest", and his book Beyond Peace might have taken its title from Nietzsche's book Beyond Good and Evil which Nixon read beforehand. Bertrand Russell
wrote that Nietzsche had exerted great influence on philosophers and on
people of literary and artistic culture, but warned that the attempt to
put Nietzsche's philosophy of aristocracy into practice could only be
done by an organization similar to the Fascist or the Nazi party.
A decade after World War II, there was a revival of Nietzsche's
philosophical writings thanks to exhaustive translations and analyses by
Walter Kaufmann and R.J. Hollingdale. Others, well known philosophers in their own right, wrote commentaries on Nietzsche's philosophy, including Martin Heidegger, who produced a four-volume study, and Lev Shestov, who wrote a book called Dostoyevski, Tolstoy and Nietzsche where he portrays Nietzsche and Dostoyevski as the "thinkers of tragedy". Georg Simmel compares Nietzsche's importance to ethics to that of Copernicus for cosmology. Sociologist Ferdinand Tönnies
read Nietzsche avidly from his early life, and later frequently
discussed many of his concepts in his own works. Nietzsche has
influenced philosophers such as Heidegger, Jean-Paul Sartre, Oswald Spengler, George Grant, Emil Cioran, Albert Camus, Ayn Rand, Jacques Derrida, Leo Strauss, Max Scheler, Michel Foucault and Bernard Williams. Camus described Nietzsche as "the only artist to have derived the extreme consequences of an aesthetics of the absurd". Paul Ricœur called Nietzsche one of the masters of the "school of suspicion", alongside Karl Marx and Sigmund Freud. Carl Jung was also influenced by Nietzsche. In Memories, Dreams, Reflections, a biography transcribed by his secretary, he cites Nietzsche as a large influence.
Aspects of Nietzsche's philosophy, especially his ideas of the self and
his relation to society, also run through much of late-twentieth and
early twenty-first century thought.
His deepening of the romantic-heroic tradition of the nineteenth
century, for example, as expressed in the ideal of the "grand striver"
appears in the work of thinkers from Cornelius Castoriadis to Roberto Mangabeira Unger.
For Nietzsche this grand striver overcomes obstacles, engages in epic
struggles, pursues new goals, embraces recurrent novelty, and transcends
existing structures and contexts.