Quantum superposition is a fundamental principle of quantum mechanics that states that linear combinations of solutions to the Schrödinger equation are also solutions of the Schrödinger equation. This follows from the fact that the Schrödinger equation is a linear differential equation in time and position. More precisely, the state of a system is given by a linear combination of all the eigenfunctions of the Schrödinger equation governing that system.
where is the quantum state of the qubit, and , denote particular solutions to the Schrödinger equation in Dirac notation weighted by the two probability amplitudes and that both are complex numbers. Here corresponds to the classical 0 bit, and to the classical 1 bit. The probabilities of measuring the system in the or state are given by and respectively (see the Born rule). Before the measurement occurs the qubit is in a superposition of both states.
The interference fringes in the double-slit experiment provide another example of the superposition principle.
Wave postulate
The theory of quantum mechanics postulates that a wave equation completely determines the state of a quantum system at all times. Furthermore, this differential equation is restricted to be linear and homogeneous. These conditions mean that for any two solutions of the wave equation, and , a linear combination of those solutions also solve the wave equation:
for arbitrary complex coefficients and . If the wave equation has more than two solutions, combinations of all such solutions are again valid solutions.
Transformation
The quantum wave equation can be solved using functions of position, , or using functions of momentum, and consequently the superposition of momentum functions are also solutions:
The position and momentum solutions are related by a linear transformation, a Fourier transformation.
This transformation is itself a quantum superposition and every
position wave function can be represented as a superposition of momentum
wave functions and vice versa. These superpositions involve an infinite
number of component waves.
Generalization to basis states
Other transformations express a quantum solution as a superposition of eigenvectors, each corresponding to a possible result of a measurement on the quantum system. An eigenvector for a mathematical operator, , has the equation
where is one possible measured quantum value for the observable . A superposition of these eigenvectors can represent any solution:
The states like are called basis states.
Compact notation for superpositions
Important
mathematical operations on quantum system solutions can be performed
using only the coefficients of the superposition, suppressing the
details of the superposed functions. This leads to quantum systems
expressed in the Dirac bra-ket notation:
This approach is especially effect for systems like quantum spin with no
classical coordinate analog. Such shorthand notation is very common in
textbooks and papers on quantum mechanics and superposition of basis
states is a fundamental tool in quantum mechanics.
Consequences
Paul Dirac described the superposition principle as follows:
The non-classical nature of the superposition process is brought out clearly if we consider the superposition of two states, A and B, such that there exists an observation which, when made on the system in state A, is certain to lead to one particular result, a say, and when made on the system in state B is certain to lead to some different result, b
say. What will be the result of the observation when made on the system
in the superposed state? The answer is that the result will be
sometimes a and sometimes b, according to a probability law depending on the relative weights of A and B in the superposition process. It will never be different from both a and b [i.e., either a or b]. The
intermediate character of the state formed by superposition thus
expresses itself through the probability of a particular result for an
observation being intermediate between the corresponding probabilities
for the original states, not through the result itself being
intermediate between the corresponding results for the original states.
Anton Zeilinger, referring to the prototypical example of the double-slit experiment, has elaborated regarding the creation and destruction of quantum superposition:
"[T]he superposition of amplitudes ... is only valid if
there is no way to know, even in principle, which path the particle
took. It is important to realize that this does not imply that an
observer actually takes note of what happens. It is sufficient to
destroy the interference pattern, if the path information is accessible
in principle from the experiment or even if it is dispersed in the
environment and beyond any technical possibility to be recovered, but in
principle still ‘‘out there.’’ The absence of any such information is the essential criterion for quantum interference to appear.
Theory
General formalism
Any
quantum state can be expanded as a sum or superposition of the
eigenstates of an Hermitian operator, like the Hamiltonian, because the
eigenstates form a complete basis:
where are the energy eigenstates of the Hamiltonian. For continuous variables like position eigenstates, :
where is the projection of the state into the basis and is called the wave function of the particle. In both instances we notice that can be expanded as a superposition of an infinite number of basis states.
Example
Given the Schrödinger equation
where indexes the set of eigenstates of the Hamiltonian with energy eigenvalues we see immediately that
where
is a solution of the Schrödinger equation but is not generally an eigenstate because and are not generally equal. We say that is made up of a superposition of energy eigenstates. Now consider the more concrete case of an electron that has either spin up or down. We now index the eigenstates with the spinors in the basis:
where and
denote spin-up and spin-down states respectively. As previously
discussed, the magnitudes of the complex coefficients give the
probability of finding the electron in either definite spin state:
where the probability of finding the particle with either spin up or down is normalized to 1. Notice that and are complex numbers, so that
is an example of an allowed state. We now get
If we consider a qubit with both position and spin, the state is a superposition of all possibilities for both:
where we have a general state is the sum of the tensor products of the position space wave functions and spinors.
Experiments
Successful experiments involving superpositions of relatively large (by the standards of quantum physics) objects have been performed.
A berylliumion has been trapped in a superposed state.
A double slit experiment has been performed with molecules as large as buckyballs and functionalized oligoporphyrins with up to 2000 atoms.
Molecules with masses exceeding 10,000 and composed of over 810 atoms have successfully been superposed
Very sensitive magnetometers have been realized using superconducting quantum interference devices (SQUIDS) that operate using quantum interference effects in superconducting circuits.
A piezoelectric "tuning fork"
has been constructed, which can be placed into a superposition of
vibrating and non-vibrating states. The resonator comprises about 10
trillion atoms.
Recent research indicates that chlorophyll within plants
appears to exploit the feature of quantum superposition to achieve
greater efficiency in transporting energy, allowing pigment proteins to
be spaced further apart than would otherwise be possible.
In quantum computers
In quantum computers, a qubit is the analog of the classical information bit and qubits can be superposed. Unlike classical bits, a superposition of qubits represents information about two states in parallel. Controlling the superposition of qubits is a central challenge in quantum computation. Qubit systems like nuclear spins
with small coupling strength are robust to outside disturbances but the
same small coupling makes it difficult to readout results.
Illustration of the Neoplatonic concept of the anima mundi emanating from The Absolute, in some ways a precursor to modern panpsychism
In philosophy of mind, panpsychism (/pænˈsaɪkɪzəm/) is the view that the mind or a mind-like aspect is a fundamental and ubiquitous feature of reality. It is also described as a theory that "the mind is a fundamental feature of the world which exists throughout the universe". It is one of the oldest philosophical theories, and has been ascribed in some form to philosophers including Thales, Plato, Spinoza, Leibniz, Schopenhauer, William James, Alfred North Whitehead, and Bertrand Russell. In the 19th century, panpsychism was the default philosophy of mind in
Western thought, but it saw a decline in the mid-20th century with the
rise of logical positivism. Recent interest in the hard problem of consciousness and developments in the fields of neuroscience, psychology, and quantum mechanics have revived interest in panpsychism in the 21st century because it addresses the hard problem directly.
Overview
Etymology
The term panpsychism comes from the Greekpan (πᾶν: "all, everything, whole") and psyche (ψυχή: "soul, mind").
The use of "psyche" is controversial because it is synonymous with
"soul", a term usually taken to refer to something supernatural; more
common terms now found in the literature include mind, mental properties, mental aspect, and experience.
Concept
Panpsychism holds that mind or a mind-like aspect is a fundamental and ubiquitous feature of reality. It is sometimes defined as a theory in which "the mind is a fundamental
feature of the world which exists throughout the universe". Panpsychists posit that the type of mentality we know through our own
experience is present, in some form, in a wide range of natural bodies. This notion has taken on a wide variety of forms. Some historical and
non-Western panpsychists ascribe attributes such as life or spirits to
all entities (animism). Contemporary academic proponents, however, hold that sentience or subjective experience is ubiquitous, while distinguishing these qualities from more complex human mental attributes. They therefore ascribe a primitive form of mentality to entities at the
fundamental level of physics but may not ascribe mentality to most
aggregate things, such as rocks or buildings.
Terminology
The philosopher David Chalmers, who has explored panpsychism as a viable theory, distinguishes between microphenomenal experiences (the experiences of microphysical entities) and macrophenomenal experiences (the experiences of larger entities, such as humans).
Philip Goff draws a distinction between panexperientialism and pancognitivism.
In the form of panpsychism under discussion in the contemporary
literature, conscious experience is present everywhere at a fundamental
level, hence the term panexperientialism. Pancognitivism, by
contrast, is the view that thought is present everywhere at a
fundamental level—a view that had some historical advocates, but no
present-day academic adherents. Contemporary panpsychists do not believe
microphysical entities have complex mental states such as beliefs,
desires, and fears.
Originally, the term panexperientialism had a narrower meaning, having been coined by David Ray Griffin to refer specifically to the form of panpsychism used in process philosophy (see below).
Two iwakura – a rock where a kami or spirit is said to reside in the religion of Shinto
Panpsychist views are a staple in pre-SocraticGreek philosophy. According to Aristotle, Thales (c. 624 – 545 BCE), the first Greek philosopher, posited a theory which held "that everything is full of gods". Thales believed that magnets demonstrated this. This has been interpreted as a panpsychist doctrine. Other Greek thinkers associated with panpsychism include Anaxagoras (who saw the unifying principle or arche as nous or mind), Anaximenes (who saw the arche as pneuma or spirit) and Heraclitus (who said "The thinking faculty is common to all").
Plato argues for panpsychism in his Sophist, in which he writes that all things participate in the form of Being and that it must have a psychic aspect of mind and soul (psyche). In the Philebus and Timaeus, Plato argues for the idea of a world soul or anima mundi. According to Plato:
This world is indeed a living being endowed with a soul
and intelligence ... a single visible living entity containing all other
living entities, which by their nature are all related.
Stoicism developed a cosmology that held that the natural world is infused with the divine fiery essence pneuma, directed by the universal intelligence logos. The relationship between beings' individual logos and the universal logos was a central concern of the Roman Stoic Marcus Aurelius. The metaphysics of Stoicism finds connections with Hellenistic philosophies such as Neoplatonism. Gnosticism also made use of the Platonic idea of anima mundi.
Renaissance
Illustration of the Cosmic order by Robert Fludd, where the World soul is depicted as a woman
After Emperor Justinian closed Plato's Academy in 529 CE, neoplatonism declined. Though there were mediaeval theologians, such as John Scotus Eriugena, who ventured into what might be called panpsychism, it was not a dominant strain in philosophical theology. But in the Italian Renaissance, it enjoyed something of a revival in the thought of figures such as Gerolamo Cardano, Bernardino Telesio, Francesco Patrizi, Giordano Bruno, and Tommaso Campanella. Cardano argued for the view that soul or anima was a fundamental part of the world, and Patrizi introduced the term panpsychism
into philosophical vocabulary. According to Bruno, "There is nothing
that does not possess a soul and that has no vital principle". Platonist ideas resembling the anima mundi (world soul) also resurfaced in the work of esoteric thinkers such as Paracelsus, Robert Fludd, and Cornelius Agrippa.
Early modern
In the 17th century, two rationalists, Baruch Spinoza and Gottfried Leibniz, can be said to be panpsychists. In Spinoza's monism, the one single infinite and eternal substance is "God, or Nature" (Deus sive Natura),
which has the aspects of mind (thought) and matter (extension).
Leibniz's view is that there are infinitely many absolutely simple
mental substances called monads that make up the universe's fundamental structure. While it has been said that George Berkeley's idealist philosophy is also a form of panpsychism, Berkeley rejected panpsychism and posited that the physical world
exists only in the experiences minds have of it, while restricting minds
to humans and certain other specific agents.
Arthur Schopenhauer argued for a two-sided view of reality as both Will and Representation (Vorstellung).
According to Schopenhauer, "All ostensible mind can be attributed to
matter, but all matter can likewise be attributed to mind".
Josiah Royce,
the leading American absolute idealist, held that reality is a "world
self", a conscious being that comprises everything, though he did not
necessarily attribute mental properties to the smallest constituents of
mentalistic "systems". The American pragmatist philosopher Charles Sanders Peirce espoused a sort of psycho-physical monism in which the universe is suffused with mind, which he associated with spontaneity and freedom. Following Pierce, William James also espoused a form of panpsychism. In his lecture notes, James wrote:
Our only intelligible notion of an object in itself is that it should be an object for itself, and this lands us in panpsychism and a belief that our physical perceptions are effects on us of 'psychical' realities
English philosopher Alfred Barratt, the author of Physical Metempiric (1883), has been described as advocating panpsychism.
In 1893, Paul Carus
proposed a philosophy similar to panpsychism, "panbiotism", according
to which "everything is fraught with life; it contains life; it has the
ability to live".
In 1990, the physicist David Bohm published "A new theory of the relationship of mind and matter," a paper based on his interpretation of quantum mechanics. The philosopher Paavo Pylkkänen has described Bohm's view as a version of panprotopsychism.
One widespread misconception is that the arguably greatest systematic metaphysician of the 20th century, Alfred North Whitehead, was also panpsychism's most significant 20th century proponent. This misreading attributes to Whitehead an ontology according to which the basic nature of the world is made up of atomic mental events, termed "actual occasions". But rather than signifying such exotic metaphysical objects—which would in fact exemplify the fallacy of misplaced concreteness
Whitehead criticizes—Whitehead's concept of "actual occasion" refers to
the "immediate experienced occasion" of any possible perceiver, having
in mind only himself as perceiver at the outset, in accordance with his
strong commitment to radical empiricism.
Contemporary
Panpsychism has recently seen a resurgence in the philosophy of mind, set into motion by Thomas Nagel's 1979 article "Panpsychism" and further spurred by Galen Strawson's 2006 realistic monist article "Realistic Monism: Why Physicalism Entails Panpsychism". Other recent proponents include American philosophers David Ray Griffin and David Skrbina, British philosophers Gregg Rosenberg, Timothy Sprigge, and Philip Goff, and Canadian philosopher William Seager. The British philosopher David Papineau,
while distancing himself from orthodox panpsychists, has written that
his view is "not unlike panpsychism" in that he rejects a line in nature
between "events lit up by phenomenology [and] those that are mere
darkness".
The integrated information theory of consciousness (IIT), proposed by the neuroscientist and psychiatrist Giulio Tononi in 2004 and since adopted by other neuroscientists such as Christof Koch, postulates that consciousness is widespread and can be found even in some simple systems.
In 2019, cognitive scientist Donald Hoffman published The Case Against Reality: How evolution hid the truth from our eyes. Hoffman argues that consensus reality lacks concrete existence, and is nothing more than an evolved user-interface. He argues that the true nature of reality is abstract "conscious agents". Science editor Annaka Harris argues that panpsychism is a viable theory in her 2019 book Conscious, though she stops short of fully endorsing it.
Panpsychism has been postulated by psychoanalyst Robin S. Brown as a means to theorizing relations between "inner" and "outer" tropes in the context of psychotherapy. Panpsychism has also been applied in environmental philosophy by Australian philosopher Freya Mathews, who has put forward the notion of ontopoetics as a version of panpsychism.
The geneticist Sewall Wright
endorsed a version of panpsychism. He believed that consciousness is
not a mysterious property emerging at a certain level of the hierarchy
of increasing material complexity, but rather an inherent property,
implying the most elementary particles have these properties.
Varieties
Panpsychism encompasses many theories, united only by the notion that mind in some form is ubiquitous.
Philosophical frameworks
Cosmopsychism
Cosmopsychism hypothesizes that the cosmos is a unified object that is ontologically prior to its parts. It has been described as an alternative to panpsychism, or as a form of panpsychism. Proponents of cosmopsychism claim that the cosmos as a whole is the
fundamental level of reality and that it instantiates consciousness.
They differ on that point from panpsychists, who usually claim that the
smallest level of reality is fundamental and instantiates consciousness.
Accordingly, human consciousness, for example, merely derives from a
larger cosmic consciousness.
Panexperientialism
Panexperientialism is associated with the philosophies of, among others, Charles Hartshorne and Alfred North Whitehead, although the term itself was invented by David Ray Griffin to distinguish the process philosophical view from other varieties of panpsychism. Whitehead's process philosophy
argues that the fundamental elements of the universe are "occasions of
experience", which can together create something as complex as a human
being. Building on Whitehead's work, process philosopher Michel Weber argues for a pancreativism. Goff has used the term panexperientialism more generally to refer to forms of panpsychism in which experience rather than thought is ubiquitous.
Panprotopsychism
Panprotopsychists believe that higher-order phenomenal properties (such as qualia) are logically entailed by protophenomenal properties, at least in principle. This is similar to how facts about H2O
molecules logically entail facts about water: the lower-level facts are
sufficient to explain the higher-order facts, since the former
logically entail the latter. It also makes sense of questions about the
unity of consciousness relating to the diversity of phenomenal
experiences and the deflation of the self. Adherents of panprotopsychism believe that "protophenomenal" facts
logically entail consciousness. Protophenomenal properties are usually
picked out through a combination of functional and negative definitions:
panphenomenal properties are those that logically entail phenomenal
properties (a functional definition), which are themselves neither
physical nor phenomenal (a negative definition).
Panprotopsychism is advertised as a solution to the combination problem:
the problem of explaining how the consciousness of microscopic physical
things might combine to give rise to the macroscopic consciousness of
the whole brain. Because protophenomenal properties are by definition
the constituent parts of consciousness, it is speculated that their
existence would make the emergence of macroscopic minds less mysterious. The philosopher David Chalmers
argues that the view faces difficulty with the combination problem. He
considers it "ad hoc", and believes it diminishes the parsimony that
made the theory initially interesting.
Russellian monism
Russellian monism is a type of neutral monism. The theory is attributed to Bertrand Russell, and may also be called Russell's panpsychism, or Russell's neutral monism. Russell believed that all causal properties are extrinsic manifestations of identical intrinsic properties. Russell called these identical internal properties quiddities.
Just as the extrinsic properties of matter can form higher-order
structure, so can their corresponding and identical quiddities. Russell
believed the conscious mind was one such structure.
Animism maintains that all things have a soul, and hylozoism maintains that all things are alive. Both could reasonably be interpreted as panpsychist, but both have fallen out of favour in contemporary academia. Modern panpsychists have tried to distance themselves from theories of
this sort, careful to carve out the distinction between the ubiquity of
experience and the ubiquity of mind and cognition.
Panpsychism and metempsychosis
Between 1840 and 1864, the Austrian mystic Jakob Lorber
claimed to have received a 26-volume revelation. Various books of the
Lorber Revelations say that specifica, closely resembling Leibniz's monads, form the most basic, irreducible substance of all physical and metaphysical creation. According to the Lorber Revelations, specifica grow in complexity and
intelligence to form ever higher level clusters of intelligence until a
fully intelligent human soul is reached. In this scenario panpsychism and metempsychosis are used to overcome the combination problem.
In the art of the Japanese rock garden, the artist must be aware of the "ishigokoro" ('heart', or 'mind') of the rocks.
Buddha-nature is an important and multifaceted doctrine in Mahayana Buddhism that is related to the capacity to attain Buddhahood. In numerous Indian sources, the idea is connected to the mind, especially the Buddhist concept of the luminous mind. In some Buddhist traditions, the Buddha-nature doctrine may be
interpreted as implying a form of panpsychism. Graham Parks argues that
most "traditional Chinese, Japanese and Korean philosophy would qualify
as panpsychist in nature".
The Huayan, Tiantai, and Tendai schools of Buddhism explicitly attribute Buddha-nature to inanimate objects such as lotus flowers and mountains. This idea was defended by figures such as the Tiantai patriarch Zhanran, who spoke of the Buddha-nature of grasses and trees. Similarly, Soto Zen master Dogen argued that "insentient beings expound" the teachings of the Buddha, and wrote about the "mind" (心, shin) of "fences, walls, tiles, and pebbles". The 9th-century Shingon figure Kukai
went so far as to argue that natural objects such as rocks and stones
are part of the supreme embodiment of the Buddha. According to Parks,
Buddha-nature is best described "in western terms" as something "psychophysical".
Scientific theories
Conscious realism
It
is a natural and near-universal assumption that the world has the
properties and causal structures that we perceive it to have; to
paraphrase Einstein's famous remark, we naturally assume that the moon
is there whether anyone looks or not. Both theoretical and empirical
considerations, however, increasingly indicate that this is not correct.
— Donald Hoffman, Conscious agent networks: Formal analysis and applications to cognition
Conscious realism is a theory proposed by Donald Hoffman, a cognitive scientist specialising in perception. He has written numerous papers on the topic which he summarised in his 2019 book The Case Against Reality: How evolution hid the truth from our eyes. Conscious realism builds upon Hoffman's former User-Interface Theory. In combination they argue that (1) consensus reality
and spacetime are illusory, and are merely a "species specific evolved
user interface"; (2) Reality is made of a complex, dimensionless, and
timeless network of "conscious agents".
The consensus view is that perception is a reconstruction of
one's environment. Hoffman views perception as a construction rather
than a reconstruction. He argues that perceptual systems are analogous
to information channels, and thus subject to data compression and reconstruction. The set of possible reconstructions for any given data set is quite large. Of that set, the subset that is homomorphic
in relation to the original is minuscule, and does not necessarily—or,
seemingly, even often—overlap with the subset that is efficient or
easiest to use.
For example, consider a graph, such as a pie chart. A pie chart
is easy to understand and use not because it is perfectly homomorphic
with the data it represents, but because it is not. If a graph of, for
example, the chemical composition of the human body were to look exactly
like a human body, then we could not understand it. It is only because
the graph abstracts away from the structure of its subject matter that
it can be visualized. Alternatively, consider a graphical user interface
on a computer. The reason graphical user interfaces are useful is that
they abstract away from lower-level computational processes, such as
machine code, or the physical state of a circuit-board. In general, it
seems that data is most useful to us when it is abstracted from its
original structure and repackaged in a way that is easier to understand,
even if this comes at the cost of accuracy. Hoffman offers the "fitness
beats truth theorem" as mathematical proof that perceptions of reality bear little resemblance to reality's true nature. From this he concludes that our senses do not faithfully represent the external world.
Even if reality is an illusion, Hoffman takes consciousness as an
indisputable fact. He represents rudimentary units of consciousness
(which he calls "conscious agents") as Markovian kernels.
Though the theory was not initially panpsychist, he reports that he and
his colleague Chetan Prakash found the math to be more parsimonious if it were. They hypothesize that reality is composed of these conscious agents, who interact to form "larger, more complex" networks.
Axioms and postulates of integrated information theory
Giulio Tononi first articulated Integrated information theory (IIT) in 2004, and it has undergone two major revisions since then. Tononi approaches consciousness from a scientific perspective, and has
expressed frustration with philosophical theories of consciousness for
lacking predictive power. Though integral to his theory, he refrains from philosophical terminology such as qualia or the unity of consciousness, instead opting for mathematically precise alternatives like entropy function and information integration. This has allowed Tononi to create a measurement for integrated information, which he calls phi (Φ). He believes consciousness is nothing but integrated information, so Φ measures consciousness. As it turns out, even basic objects or substances have a nonzero degree
of Φ. This would mean that consciousness is ubiquitous, albeit to a
minimal degree.
The philosopher Hedda Hassel Mørch's views IIT as similar to Russellian monism, while other philosophers, such as Chalmers and John Searle, consider it a form of panpsychism. IIT does not hold that all systems are conscious, leading Tononi and
Koch to state that IIT incorporates some elements of panpsychism but not
others. Koch has called IIT a "scientifically refined version" of panpsychism.
In relation to other theories
A diagram depicting four positions on the mind-body problem. Versions of panpsychism have been likened to each of these positions as well as contrasted to them.
Because panpsychism encompasses a wide range of theories, it can in principle be compatible with reductive materialism, dualism, functionalism, or other perspectives depending on the details of a given formulation.
David Chalmers and Philip Goff have each described panpsychism as an alternative to both materialism and dualism. Chalmers says panpsychism respects the conclusions of both the causal argument against dualism and the conceivability argument for dualism. Goff has argued that panpsychism avoids the disunity of dualism, under which mind and matter are ontologically separate, as well as dualism's problems explaining how mind and matter interact. By contrast, Uwe Meixner argues that panpsychism has dualist forms, which he contrasts to idealist forms.
Panpsychism is incompatible with emergentism. In general, theories of consciousness fall under one or the other
umbrella; they hold either that consciousness is present at a
fundamental level of reality (panpsychism) or that it emerges higher up
(emergentism).
There is disagreement over whether idealism is a form of panpsychism
or a separate view. Both views hold that everything that exists has some
form of experience. According to the philosophers William Seager and Sean Allen-Hermanson, "idealists are panpsychists by default". Charles Hartshorne
contrasted panpsychism and idealism, saying that while idealists
rejected the existence of the world observed with the senses or
understood it as ideas within the mind of God, panpsychists accepted the
reality of the world but saw it as composed of minds. Chalmers also contrasts panpsychism with idealism (as well as materialism and dualism). Meixner writes that formulations of panpsychism can be divided into dualist and idealist versions. He further divides the latter into "atomistic idealistic panpsychism", which he ascribes to David Hume, and "holistic idealistic panpsychism", which he favors.
Neutral monism rejects the dichotomy of mind and matter, instead
taking a third substance as fundamental that is neither mental nor
physical. Proposals for the nature of the third substance have varied,
with some theorists choosing to leave it undefined. This has led to a
variety of formulations of neutral monism, which may overlap with other
philosophies. In versions of neutral monism in which the world's
fundamental constituents are neither mental nor physical, it is quite
distinct from panpsychism. In versions where the fundamental
constituents are both mental and physical, neutral monism may lead to
panpsychism, panprotopsychism, or dual aspect theory.
In The Conscious Mind, David Chalmers writes that, in some instances, the differences between "Russell's neutral monism" and his property dualism are merely semantic. Philip Goff believes that neutral monism can reasonably be regarded as a
form of panpsychism "in so far as it is a dual aspect view". Neutral monism, panpsychism, and dual aspect theory are grouped together or used interchangeably in some contexts.
Chalmers calls panpsychism an alternative to both materialism and dualism. Similarly, Goff calls panpsychism an alternative to both physicalism and substance dualism. Strawson, on the other hand, describes panpsychism as a form of physicalism, in his view the only viable form. Panpsychism can be combined with reductive materialism but cannot be combined with eliminative materialism because the latter denies the existence of the relevant mental attributes.
Arguments for
Hard problem of consciousness
But
what consciousness is, we know not; and how it is that anything so
remarkable as a state of consciousness comes about as the result of
irritating nervous tissue, is just as unaccountable as the appearance of
the Djin when Aladdin rubbed his lamp in the story, or as any other
ultimate fact of nature.
It evidently feels like something to be a human brain. This means that when things in the world are organised in a particular way, they begin to have an experience. The questions of why and how this material structure has experience, and why it has that particular experience rather than another experience, are known as the hard problem of consciousness. The term is attributed to Chalmers. He argues that even after "all the
perceptual and cognitive functions within the vicinity of consciousness"
are accounted for, "there may still remain a further unanswered
question: Why is the performance of these functions accompanied by experience?"
Though Chalmers gave the hard problem of consciousness its present name, similar views were expressed before. Isaac Newton, John Locke, Gottfried Leibniz, John Stuart Mill, Thomas Henry Huxley, Wilhelm Wundt, all wrote about the seeming incompatibility of third-person functional
descriptions of mind and matter and first-person conscious experience.
Likewise, Asian philosophers like Dharmakirti and Guifeng Zongmi discussed the problem of how consciousness arises from unconscious matter. Similar sentiments have been articulated through philosophical inquiries such as the problem of other minds, solipsism, the explanatory gap, philosophical zombies, and Mary's room. These problems have caused Chalmers to consider panpsychism a viable solution to the hard problem, though he is not committed to any single view.
Brian Jonathan Garrett has compared the hard problem to vitalism,
the now discredited hypothesis that life is inexplicable and can only
be understood if some vital life force exists. He maintains that given
time, consciousness and its evolutionary origins will be understood just
as life is now understood. Daniel Dennett called the hard problem a "hunch", and maintained that
conscious experience, as it is usually understood, is merely a complex
cognitive illusion. Patricia Churchland, also an eliminative materialist,
maintains that philosophers ought to be more patient: neuroscience is
still in its early stages, so Chalmers's hard problem is premature.
Clarity will come from learning more about the brain, not from
metaphysical speculation.
Solutions
In The Conscious Mind (1996), Chalmers attempts to pinpoint why the hard problem is so hard. He concludes that consciousness is irreducible
to lower-level physical facts, just as the fundamental laws of physics
are irreducible to lower-level physical facts. Therefore, consciousness
should be taken as fundamental in its own right and studied as such.
Just as fundamental properties of reality are ubiquitous (even small
objects have mass), consciousness may also be, though he considers that
an open question.
In Mortal Questions (1979), Thomas Nagel argues that panpsychism follows from four premises:
P1: There is no spiritual plane or disembodied soul; everything that exists is material.
P2: Consciousness is irreducible to lower-level physical properties.
P3: Consciousness exists.
P4: Higher-order properties of matter (i.e., emergent properties)
can, at least in principle, be reduced to their lower-level properties.
Before the first premise is accepted, the range of possible
explanations for consciousness is fully open. Each premise, if accepted,
narrows down that range of possibilities. If the argument is sound, then by the last premise panpsychism is the only possibility left.
If (P1) is true, then either consciousness does not exist, or it exists within the physical world.
If (P2) is true, then either consciousness does not exist, or it (a)
exists as distinct property of matter or (b) is fundamentally entailed
by matter.
If (P3) is true, then consciousness exists, and is either (a) its
own property of matter or (b) composed by the matter of the brain but
not logically entailed by it.
If (P4) is true, then (b) is false, and consciousness must be its own unique property of matter.
Therefore, if all four premises are true, consciousness is its own unique property of matter and panpsychism is true.
Mind-body problem
Dualism makes the problem insoluble; materialism denies the existence of any phenomenon to study, and hence of any problem.
— John R. Searle, Consciousness and Language, p. 47
In 2015, Chalmers proposed a possible solution to the mind-body problem through the argumentative format of thesis, antithesis, and synthesis. The goal of such arguments is to argue for sides of a debate (the
thesis and antithesis), weigh their vices and merits, and then reconcile
them (the synthesis). Chalmers's thesis, antithesis, and synthesis are
as follows:
Thesis:materialism is true; everything is fundamentally physical.
Antithesis:dualism is true; not everything is fundamentally physical.
Synthesis: panpsychism is true.
(1) A centerpiece of Chalmers's argument is the physical world's causal closure. Newton's law of motion explains this phenomenon succinctly: for every action there is an equal and opposite reaction.
Cause and effect is a symmetrical process. There is no room for
consciousness to exert any causal power on the physical world unless it
is itself physical.
(2) On one hand, if consciousness is separate from the physical
world then there is no room for it to exert any causal power on the
world (a state of affairs philosophers call epiphenomenalism).
If consciousness plays no causal role, then it is unclear how Chalmers
could even write this paper. On the other hand, consciousness is
irreducible to the physical processes of the brain.
(3) Panpsychism has all the benefits of materialism because it
could mean that consciousness is physical while also escaping the grasp
of epiphenomenalism. After some argumentation Chalmers narrows it down
further to Russellian monism, concluding that thoughts, actions,
intentions and emotions may just be the quiddities of neurotransmitters,
neurons, and glial cells.
Problem of substance
Physics
is mathematical, not because we know so much about the physical world,
but because we know so little: it is only its mathematical properties
that we can discover. For the rest our knowledge is negative.
— Bertrand Russell, An Outline of Philosophy (1927)
Rather than solely trying to solve the problem of consciousness, Russell also attempted to solve the problem of substance, which is arguably a form of the problem of infinite regress.
(1) Like many sciences, physics describes the world through
mathematics. Unlike other sciences, physics cannot describe what
Schopenhauer called the "object that grounds" mathematics. Economics is grounded in resources being allocated, and population
dynamics is grounded in individual people within that population. The
objects that ground physics, however, can be described only through more
mathematics. In Russell's words, physics describes "certain equations giving
abstract properties of their changes". When it comes to describing "what
it is that changes, and what it changes from and to—as to this, physics
is silent". In other words, physics describes matter's extrinsic properties, but not the intrinsic properties that ground them.
(2) Russell argued that physics is mathematical because "it is
only mathematical properties we can discover". This is true almost by
definition: if only extrinsic properties are outwardly observable, then they will be the only ones discovered. This led Alfred North Whitehead to conclude that intrinsic properties are "intrinsically unknowable".
(3) Consciousness has many similarities to these intrinsic
properties of physics. It, too, cannot be directly observed from an
outside perspective. And it, too, seems to ground many observable
extrinsic properties: presumably, music is enjoyable because of the
experience of listening to it, and chronic pain is avoided because of
the experience of pain, etc. Russell concluded that consciousness must
be related to these extrinsic properties of matter. He called these
intrinsic properties quiddities. Just as extrinsic physical
properties can create structures, so can their corresponding and
identical quiddites. The conscious mind, Russell argued, is one such
structure.
Proponents of panpsychism who use this line of reasoning include Chalmers, Annaka Harris, and Galen Strawson.
Chalmers has argued that the extrinsic properties of physics must have
corresponding intrinsic properties; otherwise the universe would be "a
giant causal flux" with nothing for "causation to relate", which he
deems a logical impossibility. He sees consciousness as a promising
candidate for that role. Galen Strawson
calls Russell's panpsychism "realistic physicalism". He argues that
"the experiential considered specifically as such" is what it means for
something to be physical. Just as mass is energy, Strawson believes that consciousness "just is" matter.
Max Tegmark, theoretical physicist and creator of the mathematical universe hypothesis, disagrees with these conclusions. By his account, the universe is not just describable by math but is
math; comparing physics to economics or population dynamics is a
disanalogy. While population dynamics may be grounded in individual
people, those people are grounded in "purely mathematical objects" such
as energy and charge. The universe is, in a fundamental sense, made of
nothing.
Quantum mechanics
In a 2018 interview, Chalmers called quantum mechanics "a magnet for anyone who wants to find room for crazy properties of the mind", but not entirely without warrant. The relationship between observation (and, by extension, consciousness) and the wave-function collapse is known as the measurement problem. It seems that atoms, photons, etc. are in quantum superposition
(which is to say, in many seemingly contradictory states or locations
simultaneously) until measured in some way. This process is known as a wave-function collapse. According to the Copenhagen interpretation of quantum mechanics, one of the oldest interpretations and the most widely taught, it is the act of observation that collapses the wave-function.Erwin Schrödinger famously articulated the Copenhagen interpretation's unusual implications in the thought experiment now known as Schrödinger's cat. He imagines a box that contains a cat, a flask of poison, radioactive material, and a Geiger counter.
The apparatus is configured so that when the Geiger counter detects
radioactive decay, the flask will shatter, poisoning the cat. Unless and
until the Geiger counter detects the radioactive decay of a single
atom, the cat survives. The radioactive decay the Geiger counter detects
is a quantum event; each decay corresponds to a quantum state
transition of a single atom of the radioactive material. According to
Schrödinger's wave equation, until they are observed, quantum particles,
including the atoms of the radioactive material, are in quantum state
superposition; each unmeasured atom in the radioactive material is in a
quantum superposition of decayed and not decayed. This
means that while the box remains sealed and its contents unobserved, the
Geiger counter is also in a superposition of states of decay detected and no decay detected; the vial is in a superposition of both shattered and not shattered and the cat in a superposition of dead and alive.
But when the box is unsealed, the observer finds a cat that is either
dead or alive; there is no superposition of states. Since the cat is no
longer in a superposition of states, then neither is the radioactive
atom (nor the vial or the Geiger counter). Hence Schrödinger's wave
function no longer holds and the wave function that described the
atom—and its superposition of states—is said to have "collapsed": the
atom now has only a single state, corresponding to the cat's observed
state. But until an observer opens the box and thereby causes the wave
function to collapse, the cat is both dead and alive. This has raised
questions about, in John S. Bell's words, "where the observer begins and
ends".
The measurement problem has largely been characterised as the clash of
classical physics and quantum mechanics. Bohm argued that it is rather a
clash of classical physics, quantum mechanics, and phenomenology; all three levels of description seem to be difficult to reconcile, or even contradictory. Though not referring specifically to quantum mechanics, Chalmers has written that if a theory of everything is ever discovered, it will be a set of "psychophysical laws", rather than simply a set of physical laws. With Chalmers as their inspiration, Bohm and Pylkkänen set out to do
just that in their panprotopsychism. Chalmers, who is critical of the
Copenhagen interpretation and most quantum theories of consciousness,
has coined this "the Law of the Minimisation of Mystery".
According
to the Copenhagen interpretation of quantum mechanics, Schrödinger's
cat is both dead and alive until observed or measured in some way.
The many-worlds interpretation
of quantum mechanics does not take observation as central to the
wave-function collapse, because it denies that the collapse happens. On
the many-worlds interpretation, just as the cat is both dead and alive,
the observer both sees a dead cat and sees a living cat. Even though
observation does not play a central role in this case, questions about
observation are still relevant to the discussion. In Roger Penrose's words:
I
do not see why a conscious being need be aware of only "one" of the
alternatives in a linear superposition. What is it about consciousnesses
that says that consciousness must not be "aware" of that tantalising
linear combination of both a dead and a live cat? It seems to me that a
theory of consciousness would be needed for one to square the many world
view with what one actually observes.
Chalmers believes that the tentative variant of panpsychism outlined in The Conscious Mind (1996) does just that. Leaning toward the many-worlds interpretation due to its mathematical parsimony, he believes his variety of panpsychist property dualism
may be the theory Penrose is seeking. Chalmers believes that
information will play an integral role in any theory of consciousness
because the mind and brain have corresponding informational structures.
He considers the computational nature of physics further evidence of information's central role, and suggests that information that is physically realised is simultaneously phenomenally realised;
both regularities in nature and conscious experience are expressions of
information's underlying character. The theory implies panpsychism, and
also solves the problem Penrose poses. On Chalmers's formulation,
information in any given position is phenomenally realised, whereas the
informational state of the superposition as a whole is not. Panpsychist interpretations of quantum mechanics have been put forward by such philosophers as Whitehead, Shan Gao, Michael Lockwood, and Hoffman, who is a cognitive scientist. Protopanpsychist interpretations have been put forward by Bohm and Pylkkänen.
Tegmark has formally calculated the "decoherence
rates" of neurons, finding that the brain is a "classical rather than a
quantum system" and that quantum mechanics does not relate "to
consciousness in any fundamental way". Hagan et al. criticize Tegmark's estimate and present a revised
calculation that yields a range of decoherence rates within the realm of
physiological relevance.
In 2007, Steven Pinker
criticized explanations of consciousness invoking quantum physics,
saying: "to my ear, this amounts to the feeling that quantum mechanics
sure is weird, and consciousness sure is weird, so maybe quantum
mechanics can explain consciousness"; a view echoed by physicist Stephen Hawking. In 2017, Penrose rejected these characterizations, stating that disagreements are about the nature of quantum mechanics.
One criticism of panpsychism is that it cannot be empirically tested. A corollary of this criticism is that panpsychism has no predictive power.
Tononi and Koch write: "Besides claiming that matter and mind are one
thing, [panpsychism] has little constructive to say and offers no
positive laws explaining how the mind is organized and works".
John Searle
has alleged that panpsychism's unfalsifiability goes deeper than
run-of-the-mill untestability: it is unfalsifiable because "It does not
get up to the level of being false. It is strictly speaking meaningless
because no clear notion has been given to the claim". The need for coherence and clarification is accepted by David Skrbina, a proponent of panpsychism.
Many proponents of panpsychism base their arguments not on
empirical support but on panpsychism's theoretical virtues. Chalmers
says that while no direct evidence exists for the theory, neither is
there direct evidence against it, and that "there are indirect reasons,
of a broadly theoretical character, for taking the view seriously". Notwithstanding Tononi and Koch's criticism of panpsychism, they state
that it integrates consciousness into the physical world in a way that
is "elegantly unitary".
A related criticism is what seems to many to be the theory's bizarre nature. Goff dismisses this objection: though he admits that panpsychism is counterintuitive, he argues that
Einstein's and Darwin's theories are also counterintuitive. "At the end
of the day," he writes, "you should judge a view not for its cultural
associations but by its explanatory power".
Philosophers such as Chalmers have argued that theories of
consciousness should be capable of providing insight into the brain and
mind to avoid the problem of mental causation. If they fail to do that, the theory will succumb to epiphenomenalism, a view commonly criticised as implausible or even self-contradictory. Proponents of panpsychism (especially those with neutral monist tendencies) hope to bypass this problem by dismissing it as a false dichotomy;
mind and matter are two sides of the same coin, and mental causation is
merely the extrinsic description of intrinsic properties of mind. Robert Howell has argued that all causal functions are still accounted
for dispositionally (i.e., in terms of the behaviors described by
science), leaving phenomenality causally inert. He concludes, "This leaves us once again with epiphenomenal qualia, only in a very surprising place". Neutral monists reject such dichotomous views of mind-body interaction.
Combination problem
The combination problem (which is related to the binding problem) can be traced to William James, but was given its present name by William Seager in 1995. The problem arises from the tension between the seemingly irreducible nature of consciousness and its ubiquity. If consciousness is ubiquitous, then in panpsychism, every atom (or every bit, depending on the version of panpsychism) has a minimal level of it. How then, as Keith Frankish
puts it, do these "tiny consciousnesses combine" to create larger
conscious experiences such as "the twinge of pain" he feels in his knee? This objection has garnered significant attention, and many have attempted to answer it. None of the proposed answers has gained widespread acceptance.