Reason is the capacity of consciously making sense of things, establishing and verifying facts, applying logic, and changing or justifying practices, institutions, and beliefs based on new or existing information. It is closely associated with such characteristically human activities as philosophy, science, language, mathematics and art, and is normally considered to be a distinguishing ability possessed by humans.
Reason, or an aspect of it, is sometimes referred to as rationality.
Reasoning is associated with thinking, cognition, and intellect. The philosophical field of logic studies ways in which humans reason formally through argument. Reasoning may be subdivided into forms of logical reasoning (forms associated with the strict sense): deductive reasoning, inductive reasoning, abductive reasoning; and other modes of reasoning considered more informal, such as intuitive reasoning and verbal reasoning. Along these lines, a distinction is often drawn between logical, discursive reasoning (reason proper), and intuitive reasoning,
in which the reasoning process through intuition—however valid—may tend
toward the personal and the subjectively opaque. In some social and
political settings logical and intuitive modes of reasoning may clash,
while in other contexts intuition and formal reason are seen as
complementary rather than adversarial. For example, in mathematics, intuition is often necessary for the creative processes involved with arriving at a formal proof, arguably the most difficult of formal reasoning tasks.
Reasoning, like habit or intuition, is one of the ways by which thinking moves from one idea to a related idea. For example, reasoning is the means by which rational individuals understand sensory information from their environments, or conceptualize abstract dichotomies such as cause and effect, truth and falsehood, or ideas regarding notions of good or evil. Reasoning, as a part of executive decision making, is also closely identified with the ability to self-consciously change, in terms of goals, beliefs, attitudes, traditions, and institutions, and therefore with the capacity for freedom and self-determination.
In contrast to the use of "reason" as an abstract noun, a reason is a consideration given which either explains or justifies events, phenomena, or behavior. Reasons justify decisions, reasons support explanations of natural phenomena; reasons can be given to explain the actions (conduct) of individuals.
Using reason, or reasoning, can also be described more plainly as providing good, or the best, reasons. For example, when evaluating a moral decision, "morality is, at the very least, the effort to guide one's conduct by reason—that is, doing what there are the best reasons for doing—while giving equal [and impartial] weight to the interests of all those affected by what one does."
Psychologists and cognitive scientists have attempted to study and explain how people reason, e.g. which cognitive and neural processes are engaged, and how cultural factors affect the inferences that people draw. The field of automated reasoning studies how reasoning may or may not be modeled computationally. Animal psychology considers the question of whether animals other than humans can reason.
Reasoning, like habit or intuition, is one of the ways by which thinking moves from one idea to a related idea. For example, reasoning is the means by which rational individuals understand sensory information from their environments, or conceptualize abstract dichotomies such as cause and effect, truth and falsehood, or ideas regarding notions of good or evil. Reasoning, as a part of executive decision making, is also closely identified with the ability to self-consciously change, in terms of goals, beliefs, attitudes, traditions, and institutions, and therefore with the capacity for freedom and self-determination.
In contrast to the use of "reason" as an abstract noun, a reason is a consideration given which either explains or justifies events, phenomena, or behavior. Reasons justify decisions, reasons support explanations of natural phenomena; reasons can be given to explain the actions (conduct) of individuals.
Using reason, or reasoning, can also be described more plainly as providing good, or the best, reasons. For example, when evaluating a moral decision, "morality is, at the very least, the effort to guide one's conduct by reason—that is, doing what there are the best reasons for doing—while giving equal [and impartial] weight to the interests of all those affected by what one does."
Psychologists and cognitive scientists have attempted to study and explain how people reason, e.g. which cognitive and neural processes are engaged, and how cultural factors affect the inferences that people draw. The field of automated reasoning studies how reasoning may or may not be modeled computationally. Animal psychology considers the question of whether animals other than humans can reason.
In the English language and other modern European languages,
"reason", and related words, represent words which have always been
used to translate Latin and classical Greek terms in the sense of their
philosophical usage.
- The original Greek term was "λόγος" logos, the root of the modern English word "logic" but also a word which could mean for example "speech" or "explanation" or an "account" (of money handled).
- As a philosophical term logos was translated in its non-linguistic senses in Latin as ratio. This was originally not just a translation used for philosophy, but was also commonly a translation for logos in the sense of an account of money.
- French raison is derived directly from Latin, and this is the direct source of the English word "reason".
The earliest major philosophers to publish in English, such as Francis Bacon, Thomas Hobbes, and John Locke also routinely wrote in Latin and French, and compared their terms to Greek, treating the words "logos", "ratio", "raison"
and "reason" as interchangeable. The meaning of the word "reason" in
senses such as "human reason" also overlaps to a large extent with "rationality" and the adjective of "reason" in philosophical contexts is normally "rational", rather than "reasoned" or "reasonable". Some philosophers, Thomas Hobbes for example, also used the word ratiocination as a synonym for "reasoning".
Philosophical history
The proposal that reason gives humanity a special position in nature has been argued to be a defining characteristic of western philosophy and later western modern science,
starting with classical Greece. Philosophy can be described as a way of
life based upon reason, and in the other direction reason has been one
of the major subjects of philosophical discussion since ancient times.
Reason is often said to be reflexive, or "self-correcting", and the critique of reason has been a persistent theme in philosophy. It has been defined in different ways, at different times, by different thinkers about human nature.
Classical philosophy
For many classical philosophers, nature was understood teleologically,
meaning that every type of thing had a definitive purpose which fit
within a natural order that was itself understood to have aims. Perhaps
starting with Pythagoras or Heraclitus, the cosmos is even said to have reason.
Reason, by this account, is not just one characteristic that humans
happen to have, and that influences happiness amongst other
characteristics. Reason was considered of higher stature than other
characteristics of human nature, such as sociability, because it is
something humans share with nature itself, linking an apparently
immortal part of the human mind with the divine order of the cosmos
itself. Within the human mind or soul (psyche), reason was described by Plato as being the natural monarch which should rule over the other parts, such as spiritedness (thumos) and the passions. Aristotle, Plato's student, defined human beings as rational animals, emphasizing reason as a characteristic of human nature. He defined the highest human happiness or well being (eudaimonia) as a life which is lived consistently, excellently and completely in accordance with reason.
The conclusions to be drawn from the discussions of Aristotle and
Plato on this matter are amongst the most debated in the history of
philosophy.
But teleological accounts such as Aristotle's were highly influential
for those who attempt to explain reason in a way which is consistent
with monotheism and the immortality and divinity of the human soul. For example, in the neo-platonist account of Plotinus, the cosmos
has one soul, which is the seat of all reason, and the souls of all
individual humans are part of this soul. Reason is for Plotinus both the
provider of form to material things, and the light which brings
individuals souls back into line with their source.
Such neo-Platonist accounts of the rational part of the human soul were
standard amongst medieval Islamic philosophers, and under this
influence, mainly via Averroes, came to be debated seriously in Europe until well into the renaissance, and they remain important in Iranian philosophy.
Subject-centred reason in early modern philosophy
The early modern era was marked by a number of significant changes in the understanding of reason, starting in Europe. One of the most important of these changes involved a change in the metaphysical understanding of human beings. Scientists and philosophers began to question the teleological understanding of the world.
Nature was no longer assumed to be human-like, with its own aims or
reason, and human nature was no longer assumed to work according to
anything other than the same "laws of nature" which affect inanimate things. This new understanding eventually displaced the previous world view that derived from a spiritual understanding of the universe.
Accordingly, in the 17th century, René Descartes
explicitly rejected the traditional notion of humans as "rational
animals", suggesting instead that they are nothing more than "thinking
things" along the lines of other "things" in nature. Any grounds of
knowledge outside that understanding was, therefore, subject to doubt.
In his search for a foundation of all possible knowledge, Descartes deliberately decided to throw into doubt all knowledge – except that of the mind itself in the process of thinking:
At this time I admit nothing that is not necessarily true. I am therefore precisely nothing but a thinking thing; that is a mind, or intellect, or understanding, or reason – words of whose meanings I was previously ignorant.
This eventually became known as epistemological or "subject-centred" reason, because it is based on the knowing subject,
who perceives the rest of the world and itself as a set of objects to
be studied, and successfully mastered by applying the knowledge
accumulated through such study. Breaking with tradition and many
thinkers after him, Descartes explicitly did not divide the incorporeal
soul into parts, such as reason and intellect, describing them as one
indivisible incorporeal entity.
A contemporary of Descartes, Thomas Hobbes described reason as a broader version of "addition and subtraction" which is not limited to numbers.
This understanding of reason is sometimes termed "calculative" reason.
Similar to Descartes, Hobbes asserted that "No discourse whatsoever, can
end in absolute knowledge of fact, past, or to come" but that "sense
and memory" is absolute knowledge.
In the late 17th century, through the 18th century, John Locke and David Hume developed Descartes' line of thought still further. Hume took it in an especially skeptical direction, proposing that there could be no possibility of deducing relationships of cause and effect, and therefore no knowledge is based on reasoning alone, even if it seems otherwise.
Hume famously remarked that, "We speak not strictly and
philosophically when we talk of the combat of passion and of reason.
Reason is, and ought only to be the slave of the passions, and can never
pretend to any other office than to serve and obey them."
Hume also took his definition of reason to unorthodox extremes by
arguing, unlike his predecessors, that human reason is not qualitatively
different from either simply conceiving individual ideas, or from
judgments associating two ideas,
and that "reason is nothing but a wonderful and unintelligible instinct
in our souls, which carries us along a certain train of ideas, and
endows them with particular qualities, according to their particular
situations and relations." It followed from this that animals have reason, only much less complex than human reason.
In the 18th century, Immanuel Kant attempted to show that Hume was wrong by demonstrating that a "transcendental"
self, or "I", was a necessary condition of all experience. Therefore,
suggested Kant, on the basis of such a self, it is in fact possible to
reason both about the conditions and limits of human knowledge. And so
long as these limits are respected, reason can be the vehicle of
morality, justice, aesthetics, theories of knowledge (epistemology), and understanding.
Substantive and formal reason
In
the formulation of Kant, who wrote some of the most influential modern
treatises on the subject, the great achievement of reason (German: Vernunft)
is that it is able to exercise a kind of universal law-making. Kant was
able therefore to reformulate the basis of moral-practical, theoretical
and aesthetic reasoning, on "universal" laws.
Here practical reasoning is the self-legislating or self-governing formulation of universal norms, and theoretical reasoning the way humans posit universal laws of nature.
Under practical reason, the moral autonomy
or freedom of human beings depends on their ability to behave according
to laws that are given to them by the proper exercise of that reason.
This contrasted with earlier forms of morality, which depended on religious understanding and interpretation, or nature for their substance.
According to Kant, in a free society each individual must be able
to pursue their goals however they see fit, so long as their actions
conform to principles given by reason. He formulated such a principle,
called the "categorical imperative", which would justify an action only if it could be universalized:
Act only according to that maxim whereby you can, at the same time, will that it should become a universal law.
In contrast to Hume then, Kant insists that reason itself (German Vernunft)
has natural ends itself, the solution to the metaphysical problems,
especially the discovery of the foundations of morality. Kant claimed
that this problem could be solved with his "transcendental logic"
which unlike normal logic is not just an instrument, which can be used
indifferently, as it was for Aristotle, but a theoretical science in its
own right and the basis of all the others.
According to Jürgen Habermas,
the "substantive unity" of reason has dissolved in modern times, such
that it can no longer answer the question "How should I live?" Instead,
the unity of reason has to be strictly formal, or "procedural." He thus
described reason as a group of three autonomous spheres (on the model of
Kant's three critiques):
- Cognitive–instrumental reason is the kind of reason employed by the sciences. It is used to observe events, to predict and control outcomes, and to intervene in the world on the basis of its hypotheses;
- Moral–practical reason is what we use to deliberate and discuss issues in the moral and political realm, according to universalizable procedures (similar to Kant's categorical imperative); and
- Aesthetic reason is typically found in works of art and literature, and encompasses the novel ways of seeing the world and interpreting things that those practices embody.
For Habermas, these three spheres are the domain of experts, and therefore need to be mediated with the "lifeworld"
by philosophers. In drawing such a picture of reason, Habermas hoped to
demonstrate that the substantive unity of reason, which in pre-modern
societies had been able to answer questions about the good life, could
be made up for by the unity of reason's formalizable procedures.
The critique of reason
Hamann, Herder, Kant, Hegel, Kierkegaard, Nietzsche, Heidegger, Foucault, Rorty,
and many other philosophers have contributed to a debate about what
reason means, or ought to mean. Some, like Kierkegaard, Nietzsche, and
Rorty, are skeptical about subject-centred, universal, or instrumental
reason, and even skeptical toward reason as a whole. Others, including
Hegel, believe that it has obscured the importance of intersubjectivity, or "spirit" in human life, and attempt to reconstruct a model of what reason should be.
Some thinkers, e.g. Foucault, believe there are other forms
of reason, neglected but essential to modern life, and to our
understanding of what it means to live a life according to reason.
In the last several decades, a number of proposals have been made
to "re-orient" this critique of reason, or to recognize the "other
voices" or "new departments" of reason.
For example, in opposition to subject-centred reason, Habermas has proposed a model of communicative reason that sees it as an essentially cooperative activity, based on the fact of linguistic intersubjectivity.
Nikolas Kompridis
has proposed a widely encompassing view of reason as "that ensemble of
practices that contributes to the opening and preserving of openness" in
human affairs, and a focus on reason's possibilities for social change.
The philosopher Charles Taylor, influenced by the 20th century German philosopher Martin Heidegger, has proposed that reason ought to include the faculty of disclosure, which is tied to the way we make sense of things in everyday life, as a new "department" of reason.
In the essay "What is Enlightenment?", Michel Foucault proposed a
concept of critique based on Kant's distinction between "private" and
"public" uses of reason. This distinction, as suggested, has two
dimensions:
- Private reason is the reason that is used when an individual is "a cog in a machine" or when one "has a role to play in society and jobs to do: to be a soldier, to have taxes to pay, to be in charge of a parish, to be a civil servant."
- Public reason is the reason used "when one is reasoning as a reasonable being (and not as a cog in a machine), when one is reasoning as a member of reasonable humanity." In these circumstances, "the use of reason must be free and public."
Compared to logic
The terms "logic" or "logical" are sometimes used as if they were
identical with the term "reason" or with the concept of being
"rational", or sometimes logic is seen as the most pure or the defining
form of reason. For example in modern economics, rational choice is assumed to equate to logically consistent choice.
Reason and logic can however be thought of as distinct, although logic is one important aspect of reason. Author Douglas Hofstadter, in Gödel, Escher, Bach,
characterizes the distinction in this way. Logic is done inside a
system while reason is done outside the system by such methods as
skipping steps, working backward, drawing diagrams, looking at examples,
or seeing what happens if you change the rules of the system.
Reason is a type of thought, and the word "logic"
involves the attempt to describe rules or norms by which reasoning
operates, so that orderly reasoning can be taught. The oldest surviving
writing to explicitly consider the rules by which reason operates are
the works of the Greek philosopher Aristotle, especially Prior Analysis and Posterior Analysis. Although the Ancient Greeks had no separate word for logic as distinct from language and reason, Aristotle's newly coined word "syllogism" (syllogismos) identified logic clearly for the first time as a distinct field of study. When Aristotle referred to "the logical" (hē logikē), he was referring more broadly to rational thought.
Reason compared to cause-and-effect thinking, and symbolic thinking
As pointed out by philosophers such as Hobbes, Locke and Hume, some animals are also clearly capable of a type of "associative thinking",
even to the extent of associating causes and effects. A dog once
kicked, can learn how to recognize the warning signs and avoid being
kicked in the future, but this does not mean the dog has reason in any
strict sense of the word. It also does not mean that humans acting on
the basis of experience or habit are using their reason.
Human reason requires more than being able to associate two
ideas, even if those two ideas might be described by a reasoning human
as a cause and an effect, perceptions of smoke, for example, and
memories of fire. For reason to be involved, the association of smoke
and the fire would have to be thought through in a way which can be
explained, for example as cause and effect. In the explanation of Locke, for example, reason requires the mental use of a third idea in order to make this comparison by use of syllogism.
More generally, reason in the strict sense requires the ability to create and manipulate a system of symbols, as well as indices and icons, according to Charles Sanders Peirce, the symbols having only a nominal, though habitual, connection to either smoke or fire. One example of such a system of artificial symbols and signs is language.
The connection of reason to symbolic thinking has been expressed in different ways by philosophers. Thomas Hobbes described the creation of "Markes, or Notes of remembrance" (Leviathan Ch. 4) as speech. He used the word speech as an English version of the Greek word logos so that speech did not need to be communicated. When communicated, such speech becomes language, and the marks or notes or remembrance are called "Signes" by Hobbes. Going further back, although Aristotle is a source of the idea that only humans have reason (logos),
he does mention that animals with imagination, for whom sense
perceptions can persist, come closest to having something like reasoning
and nous, and even uses the word "logos" in one place to describe the distinctions which animals can perceive in such cases.
Reason, imagination, mimesis, and memory
Reason and imagination rely on similar mental processes. Imagination is not only found in humans. Aristotle, for example, stated that phantasia (imagination: that which can hold images or phantasmata) and phronein (a type of thinking that can judge and understand in some sense) also exist in some animals.
According to him, both are related to the primary perceptive ability of
animals, which gathers the perceptions of different senses and defines
the order of the things that are perceived without distinguishing
universals, and without deliberation or logos. But this is not yet reason, because human imagination is different.
The recent modern writings of Terrence Deacon and Merlin Donald, writing about the origin of language, also connect reason connected to not only language, but also mimesis, More specifically they describe the ability to create language as part of an internal modeling of reality specific to humankind. Other results are consciousness, and imagination or fantasy. In contrast, modern proponents of a genetic predisposition to language itself include Noam Chomsky and Steven Pinker, to whom Donald and Deacon can be contrasted.
As reason is symbolic thinking, and peculiarly human, then this
implies that humans have a special ability to maintain a clear
consciousness of the distinctness of "icons" or images and the real
things they represent. Starting with a modern author, Merlin Donald
writes
A dog might perceive the "meaning" of a fight that was realistically play-acted by humans, but it could not reconstruct the message or distinguish the representation from its referent (a real fight). [...] Trained apes are able to make this distinction; young children make this distinction early – hence, their effortless distinction between play-acting an event and the event itself.
In classical descriptions, an equivalent description of this mental faculty is eikasia, in the philosophy of Plato.
This is the ability to perceive whether a perception is an image of
something else, related somehow but not the same, and therefore allows
humans to perceive that a dream or memory or a reflection in a mirror is
not reality as such. What Klein refers to as dianoetic eikasia is the eikasia concerned specifically with thinking and mental images, such as those mental symbols, icons, signes,
and marks discussed above as definitive of reason. Explaining reason
from this direction: human thinking is special in the way that we often
understand visible things as if they were themselves images of our
intelligible "objects of thought" as "foundations" (hypothēses in Ancient Greek). This thinking (dianoia)
is "...an activity which consists in making the vast and diffuse jungle
of the visible world depend on a plurality of more 'precise' noēta."
Both Merlin Donald and the Socratic authors such as Plato and Aristotle emphasize the importance of mimesis, often translated as imitation or representation. Donald writes
Imitation is found especially in monkeys and apes [... but ...] Mimesis is fundamentally different from imitation and mimicry in that it involves the invention of intentional representations. [...] Mimesis is not absolutely tied to external communication.
Mimēsis is a concept, now popular again in academic
discussion, that was particularly prevalent in Plato's works, and within
Aristotle, it is discussed mainly in the Poetics. In Michael Davis's account of the theory of man in this work.
It is the distinctive feature of human action, that whenever we choose what we do, we imagine an action for ourselves as though we were inspecting it from the outside. Intentions are nothing more than imagined actions, internalizings of the external. All action is therefore imitation of action; it is poetic...
Donald like Plato (and Aristotle, especially in On Memory and Recollection), emphasizes the peculiarity in humans of voluntary initiation of a search through one's mental world. The ancient Greek anamnēsis, normally translated as "recollection" was opposed to mneme or memory. Memory, shared with some animals, requires a consciousness not only of what happened in the past, but also that something happened in the past, which is in other words a kind of eikasia "...but nothing except man is able to recollect."
Recollection is a deliberate effort to search for and recapture
something once known. Klein writes that, "To become aware of our having
forgotten something means to begin recollecting." Donald calls the same thing autocueing, which he explains as follows:
"Mimetic acts are reproducible on the basis of internal, self-generated
cues. This permits voluntary recall of mimetic representations, without
the aid of external cues – probably the earliest form of
representational thinking."
In a celebrated paper in modern times, the fantasy author and philologist J.R.R. Tolkien
wrote in his essay "On Fairy Stories" that the terms "fantasy" and
"enchantment" are connected to not only "....the satisfaction of certain
primordial human desires...." but also "...the origin of language and
of the mind."
Logical reasoning methods and argumentation
Looking at logical categorizations of different types of reasoning the traditional main division made in philosophy is between deductive reasoning and inductive reasoning. Formal logic has been described as the science of deduction. The study of inductive reasoning is generally carried out within the field known as informal logic or critical thinking.
Deductive reasoning
A subdivision of Philosophy is Logic.
Logic is the study of reasoning. Deduction is a form of reasoning in
which a conclusion follows necessarily from the stated premises. A
deduction is also the conclusion reached by a deductive reasoning
process. One classic example of deductive reasoning is that found in syllogisms like the following:
- Premise 1: All humans are mortal.
- Premise 2: Socrates is a human.
- Conclusion: Socrates is mortal.
The reasoning in this argument is valid, because there is no way in
which the premises, 1 and 2, could be true and the conclusion, 3, be
false.
Inductive reasoning
Induction is a form of inference producing propositions about
unobserved objects or types, either specifically or generally, based on
previous observation. It is used to ascribe properties or relations to objects or types based on previous observations or experiences, or to formulate general statements or laws based on limited observations of recurring phenomenal patterns.
Inductive reasoning contrasts strongly with deductive reasoning
in that, even in the best, or strongest, cases of inductive reasoning,
the truth of the premises does not guarantee the truth of the
conclusion. Instead, the conclusion of an inductive argument follows
with some degree of probability.
Relatedly, the conclusion of an inductive argument contains more
information than is already contained in the premises. Thus, this method
of reasoning is ampliative.
A classic example of inductive reasoning comes from the empiricist David Hume:
- Premise: The sun has risen in the east every morning up until now.
- Conclusion: The sun will also rise in the east tomorrow.
Analogical reasoning
Analogical reasoning is a form of inductive reasoning from a particular to a particular. It is often used in case-based reasoning, especially legal reasoning. An example follows:
- Premise 1: Socrates is human and mortal.
- Premise 2: Plato is human.
- Conclusion: Plato is mortal.
Analogical reasoning is a weaker form of inductive reasoning from a
single example, because inductive reasoning typically uses a large
number of examples to reason from the particular to the general. Analogical reasoning often leads to wrong conclusions. For example:
- Premise 1: Socrates is human and male.
- Premise 2: Ada Lovelace is human.
- Conclusion: Therefore Ada Lovelace is male.
Abductive reasoning
Abductive reasoning, or argument to the best explanation, is a form
of reasoning that doesn't fit in deductive or inductive, since it starts
with incomplete set of observations and proceeds with likely possible
explanations so the conclusion in an abductive argument does not follow
with certainty from its premises and concerns something unobserved. What
distinguishes abduction from the other forms of reasoning is an attempt
to favour one conclusion above others, by subjective judgement or
attempting to falsify alternative explanations or by demonstrating the
likelihood of the favoured conclusion, given a set of more or less
disputable assumptions. For example, when a patient displays certain
symptoms, there might be various possible causes, but one of these is
preferred above others as being more probable.
Fallacious reasoning
Flawed reasoning in arguments is known as fallacious reasoning. Bad reasoning within arguments can be because it commits either a formal fallacy or an informal fallacy.
Formal fallacies occur when there is a problem with the form, or
structure, of the argument. The word "formal" refers to this link to the
form of the argument. An argument that contains a formal fallacy will always be invalid.
An informal fallacy is an error in reasoning that occurs due to a problem with the content, rather than mere structure, of the argument.
Traditional problems raised concerning reason
Philosophy
is sometimes described as a life of reason, with normal human reason
pursued in a more consistent and dedicated way than usual. Two
categories of problem concerning reason have long been discussed by
philosophers concerning reason, essentially being reasonings about
reasoning itself as a human aim, or philosophizing about philosophizing.
The first question is concerning whether we can be confident that
reason can achieve knowledge of truth
better than other ways of trying to achieve such knowledge. The other
question is whether a life of reason, a life that aims to be guided by
reason, can be expected to achieve a happy life more so than other ways of life (whether such a life of reason results in knowledge or not).
Reason versus truth, and "first principles"
Since classical times a question has remained constant in philosophical debate (which is sometimes seen as a conflict between movements called Platonism and Aristotelianism) concerning the role of reason in confirming truth. People use logic, deduction, and induction,
to reach conclusions they think are true. Conclusions reached in this
way are considered, according to Aristotle, more certain than sense
perceptions on their own.
On the other hand, if such reasoned conclusions are only built
originally upon a foundation of sense perceptions, then, our most
logical conclusions can never be said to be certain because they are
built upon the very same fallible perceptions they seek to better.
This leads to the question of what types of first principles, or starting points of reasoning, are available for someone seeking to come to true conclusions. In Greek, "first principles" are archai, "starting points", and the faculty used to perceive them is sometimes referred to in Aristotle and Plato as nous which was close in meaning to awareness or consciousness.
Empiricism (sometimes associated with Aristotle but more correctly associated with British philosophers such as John Locke and David Hume, as well as their ancient equivalents such as Democritus)
asserts that sensory impressions are the only available starting points
for reasoning and attempting to attain truth. This approach always
leads to the controversial conclusion that absolute knowledge is not attainable. Idealism,
(associated with Plato and his school), claims that there is a "higher"
reality, from which certain people can directly arrive at truth without
needing to rely only upon the senses, and that this higher reality is
therefore the primary source of truth.
Philosophers such as Plato, Aristotle, Al-Farabi, Avicenna, Averroes, Maimonides, Aquinas and Hegel
are sometimes said to have argued that reason must be fixed and
discoverable—perhaps by dialectic, analysis, or study. In the vision of
these thinkers, reason is divine or at least has divine attributes. Such
an approach allowed religious philosophers such as Thomas Aquinas and Étienne Gilson to try to show that reason and revelation are compatible. According to Hegel, "...the only thought which Philosophy brings with it to the contemplation of History,
is the simple conception of reason; that reason is the Sovereign of the
World; that the history of the world, therefore, presents us with a
rational process."
Since the 17th century rationalists, reason has often been taken to be a subjective faculty, or rather the unaided ability (pure reason) to form concepts. For Descartes, Spinoza and Leibniz, this was associated with mathematics. Kant attempted to show that pure reason could form concepts (time and space)
that are the conditions of experience. Kant made his argument in
opposition to Hume, who denied that reason had any role to play in
experience.
Reason versus emotion or passion
After Plato and Aristotle, western literature often treated reason as being the faculty that trained the passions and appetites. Stoic philosophy by contrast considered all passions undesirable. After the critiques of reason in the early Enlightenment the appetites were rarely discussed or conflated with the passions.
Some Enlightenment camps took after the Stoics to say Reason should
oppose Passion rather than order it, while others like the Romantics
believed that Passion displaces Reason, as in the maxim "follow your
heart".
Reason has been seen as a slave, or judge, of the passions, notably in the work of David Hume, and more recently of Freud. Reasoning which claims that the object of a desire is demanded by logic alone is called rationalization.
Rousseau first proposed, in his second Discourse, that reason and political life is not natural and possibly harmful to mankind.
He asked what really can be said about what is natural to mankind.
What, other than reason and civil society, "best suits his
constitution"? Rousseau saw "two principles prior to reason" in human
nature. First we hold an intense interest in our own well-being.
Secondly we object to the suffering or death of any sentient being,
especially one like ourselves.
These two passions lead us to desire more than we could achieve. We
become dependent upon each other, and on relationships of authority and
obedience. This effectively puts the human race into slavery. Rousseau
says that he almost dares to assert that nature does not destine men to
be healthy. According to Velkley, "Rousseau outlines certain programs of
rational self-correction, most notably the political legislation of the
Contrat Social and the moral education in Émile.
All the same, Rousseau understands such corrections to be only
ameliorations of an essentially unsatisfactory condition, that of
socially and intellectually corrupted humanity."
This quandary presented by Rousseau led to Kant's
new way of justifying reason as freedom to create good and evil. These
therefore are not to be blamed on nature or God. In various ways, German Idealism after Kant, and major later figures such Nietzsche, Bergson, Husserl, Scheler, and Heidegger, remain preoccupied with problems coming from the metaphysical demands or urges of reason. The influence of Rousseau and these later writers is also large upon art and politics. Many writers (such as Nikos Kazantzakis) extol passion and disparage reason. In politics modern nationalism comes from Rousseau's argument that rationalist cosmopolitanism brings man ever further from his natural state.
Another view on reason and emotion was proposed in the 1994 book titled Descartes' Error by Antonio Damasio. In it, Damasio presents the "Somatic Marker Hypothesis"
which states that emotions guide behavior and decision-making. Damasio
argues that these somatic markers (known collectively as "gut feelings")
are "intuitive signals" that direct our decision making processes in a
certain way that cannot be solved with rationality alone. Damasio
further argues that rationality requires emotional input in order to
function.
Reason versus faith or tradition
There are many religious traditions, some of which are explicitly fideist and others of which claim varying degrees of rationalism.
Secular critics sometimes accuse all religious adherents of
irrationality, since they claim such adherents are guilty of ignoring,
suppressing, or forbidding some kinds of reasoning concerning some
subjects (such as religious dogmas, moral taboos, etc.). Though the theologies and religions such as classical monotheism typically do not claim to be irrational, there is often a perceived conflict or tension between faith and tradition on the one hand, and reason on the other, as potentially competing sources of wisdom, law and truth.
Religious adherents sometimes respond by arguing that faith and
reason can be reconciled, or have different non-overlapping domains, or
that critics engage in a similar kind of irrationalism:
- Reconciliation: Philosopher Alvin Plantinga argues that there is no real conflict between reason and classical theism because classical theism explains (among other things) why the universe is intelligible and why reason can successfully grasp it.
- Non-overlapping magisteria: Evolutionary biologist Stephen Jay Gould argues that there need not be conflict between reason and religious belief because they are each authoritative in their own domain (or "magisterium"). For example, perhaps reason alone is not enough to explain such big questions as the origins of the universe, the origin of life, the origin of consciousness, the foundation of morality, or the destiny of the human race. If so, reason can work on those problems over which it has authority while other sources of knowledge or opinion can have authority on the big questions.
- Tu quoque: Philosophers Alasdair MacIntyre and Charles Taylor argue that those critics of traditional religion who are adherents of secular liberalism are also sometimes guilty of ignoring, suppressing, and forbidding some kinds of reasoning about subjects. Similarly, philosophers of science such as Paul Feyaraband argue that scientists sometimes ignore or suppress evidence contrary to the dominant paradigm.
- Unification: Theologian Joseph Ratzinger, later Benedict XVI, asserted that "Christianity has understood itself as the religion of the Logos, as the religion according to reason," referring to John 1:Ἐν ἀρχῇ ἦν ὁ λόγος, usually translated as "In the beginning was the Word (Logos)." Thus, he said that the Christian faith is "open to all that is truly rational", and that the rationality of Western Enlightenment "is of Christian origin".
Some commentators have claimed that Western civilization can be almost defined by its serious testing of the limits of tension between "unaided" reason and faith in "revealed" truths—figuratively summarized as Athens and Jerusalem, respectively. Leo Strauss spoke of a "Greater West" that included all areas under the influence of the tension between Greek rationalism and Abrahamic revelation, including the Muslim lands. He was particularly influenced by the great Muslim philosopher Al-Farabi. To consider to what extent Eastern philosophy might have partaken of these important tensions, Strauss thought it best to consider whether dharma or tao may be equivalent to Nature (by which we mean physis
in Greek). According to Strauss the beginning of philosophy involved
the "discovery or invention of nature" and the "pre-philosophical
equivalent of nature" was supplied by "such notions as 'custom' or 'ways'", which appear to be really universal in all times and places. The philosophical concept of nature or natures as a way of understanding archai
(first principles of knowledge) brought about a peculiar tension
between reasoning on the one hand, and tradition or faith on the other.
Although there is this special history of debate concerning
reason and faith in the Islamic, Christian and Jewish traditions, the
pursuit of reason is sometimes argued to be compatible with the other
practice of other religions of a different nature, such as Hinduism, because they do not define their tenets in such an absolute way.
Reason in particular fields of study
Reason in political philosophy and ethics
Aristotle famously described reason (with language) as a part of human nature, which means that it is best for humans to live "politically" meaning in communities of about the size and type of a small city state (polis in Greek). For example...
It is clear, then, that a human being is more of a political [politikon = of the polis] animal [zōion] than is any bee or than any of those animals that live in herds. For nature, as we say, makes nothing in vain, and humans are the only animals who possess reasoned speech [logos]. Voice, of course, serves to indicate what is painful and pleasant; that is why it is also found in other animals, because their nature has reached the point where they can perceive what is painful and pleasant and express these to each other. But speech [logos] serves to make plain what is advantageous and harmful and so also what is just and unjust. For it is a peculiarity of humans, in contrast to the other animals, to have perception of good and bad, just and unjust, and the like; and the community in these things makes a household or city [polis]. [...] By nature, then, the drive for such a community exists in everyone, but the first to set one up is responsible for things of very great goodness. For as humans are the best of all animals when perfected, so they are the worst when divorced from law and right. The reason is that injustice is most difficult to deal with when furnished with weapons, and the weapons a human being has are meant by nature to go along with prudence and virtue, but it is only too possible to turn them to contrary uses. Consequently, if a human being lacks virtue, he is the most unholy and savage thing, and when it comes to sex and food, the worst. But justice is something political [to do with the polis], for right is the arrangement of the political community, and right is discrimination of what is just. (Aristotle's Politics 1253a 1.2. Peter Simpson's translation, with Greek terms inserted in square brackets.)
The concept of human nature being fixed in this way, implied, in
other words, that we can define what type of community is always best
for people. This argument has remained a central argument in all
political, ethical and moral thinking since then, and has become
especially controversial since firstly Rousseau's Second Discourse, and secondly, the Theory of Evolution. Already in Aristotle there was an awareness that the polis
had not always existed and had needed to be invented or developed by
humans themselves. The household came first, and the first villages and
cities were just extensions of that, with the first cities being run as
if they were still families with Kings acting like fathers.
Friendship [philia] seems to prevail [in] man and woman according to nature [kata phusin]; for people are by nature [tēi phusei] pairing [sunduastikon] more than political [politikon = of the polis], in as much as the household [oikos] is prior [proteron = earlier] and more necessary than the polis and making children is more common [koinoteron] with the animals. In the other animals, community [koinōnia] goes no further than this, but people live together [sumoikousin] not only for the sake of making children, but also for the things for life; for from the start the functions [erga] are divided, and are different [for] man and woman. Thus they supply each other, putting their own into the common [eis to koinon]. It is for these [reasons] that both utility [chrēsimon] and pleasure [hēdu] seem to be found in this kind of friendship. (Nicomachean Ethics, VIII.12.1162a. Rough literal translation with Greek terms shown in square brackets.)
Rousseau
in his Second Discourse finally took the shocking step of claiming that
this traditional account has things in reverse: with reason, language
and rationally organized communities all having developed over a long
period of time merely as a result of the fact that some habits of
cooperation were found to solve certain types of problems, and that once
such cooperation became more important, it forced people to develop
increasingly complex cooperation—often only to defend themselves from
each other.
In other words, according to Rousseau, reason, language and
rational community did not arise because of any conscious decision or
plan by humans or gods, nor because of any pre-existing human nature. As
a result, he claimed, living together in rationally organized
communities like modern humans is a development with many negative
aspects compared to the original state of man as an ape. If anything is
specifically human in this theory, it is the flexibility and
adaptability of humans. This view of the animal origins of distinctive
human characteristics later received support from Charles Darwin's Theory of Evolution.
The two competing theories concerning the origins of reason are
relevant to political and ethical thought because, according to the
Aristotelian theory, a best way of living together exists independently
of historical circumstances. According to Rousseau, we should even doubt
that reason, language and politics are a good thing, as opposed to
being simply the best option given the particular course of events that
lead to today. Rousseau's theory, that human nature is malleable rather
than fixed, is often taken to imply, for example by Karl Marx, a wider range of possible ways of living together than traditionally known.
However, while Rousseau's initial impact encouraged bloody revolutions against traditional politics, including both the French Revolution and the Russian Revolution, his own conclusions about the best forms of community seem to have been remarkably classical, in favor of city-states such as Geneva, and rural living.
Psychology
Scientific research into reasoning is carried out within the fields of psychology and cognitive science.
Psychologists attempt to determine whether or not people are capable of
rational thought in a number of different circumstances.
Assessing how well someone engages in reasoning is the project of determining the extent to which the person is rational or acts rationally. It is a key research question in the psychology of reasoning. Rationality is often divided into its respective theoretical and practical counterparts.
Behavioral experiments on human reasoning
Experimental
cognitive psychologists carry out research on reasoning behaviour. Such
research may focus, for example, on how people perform on tests of
reasoning such as intelligence or IQ tests, or on how well people's reasoning matches ideals set by logic (see, for example, the Wason test). Experiments examine how people make inferences from conditionals e.g., If A then B and how they make inferences about alternatives, e.g., A or else B. They test whether people can make valid deductions about spatial and temporal relations, e.g., A is to the left of B, or A happens after B, and about quantified assertions, e.g., All the A are B. Experiments investigate how people make inferences about factual situations, hypothetical possibilities, probabilities, and counterfactual situations.
Developmental studies of children's reasoning
Developmental psychologists investigate the development of reasoning from birth to adulthood. Piaget's theory of cognitive development
was the first complete theory of reasoning development. Subsequently,
several alternative theories were proposed, including the neo-Piagetian theories of cognitive development.
Neuroscience of reasoning
The biological functioning of the brain is studied by neurophysiologists and neuropsychologists.
Research in this area includes research into the structure and function
of normally functioning brains, and of damaged or otherwise unusual
brains. In addition to carrying out research into reasoning, some
psychologists, for example, clinical psychologists and psychotherapists work to alter people's reasoning habits when they are unhelpful.
Computer science
Automated reasoning
In artificial intelligence and computer science, scientists study and use automated reasoning for diverse applications including automated theorem proving the formal semantics of programming languages, and formal specification in software engineering.
Meta-reasoning
Meta-reasoning is reasoning about reasoning. In computer science, a
system performs meta-reasoning when it is reasoning about its own
operation. This requires a programming language capable of reflection, the ability to observe and modify its own structure and behaviour.
Evolution of reason
A species could benefit greatly from better abilities to reason
about, predict and understand the world. French social and cognitive
scientists Dan Sperber
and Hugo Mercier argue that there could have been other forces driving
the evolution of reason. They point out that reasoning is very difficult
for humans to do effectively, and that it is hard for individuals to
doubt their own beliefs (confirmation bias). Reasoning is most effective when it is done as a collective – as demonstrated by the success of projects like science. They suggest that there are not just individual, but group selection
pressures at play. Any group that managed to find ways of reasoning
effectively would reap benefits for all its members, increasing their fitness.
This could also help explain why humans, according to Sperber, are not
optimized to reason effectively alone. Their argumentative theory of
reasoning claims that reason may have more to do with winning arguments
than with the search for the truth.