Original cover, with detail from the painting The Expectant Valley by the zoologist Desmond Morris
| |
Author | Richard Dawkins |
---|---|
Country | United Kingdom |
Language | English |
Subject | Evolutionary biology |
Publisher | Oxford University Press |
Publication date
|
|
Media type | |
Pages | 224 |
ISBN | 0-19-857519-X |
OCLC | 2681149 |
Followed by | The Extended Phenotype |
The Selfish Gene is a 1976 book on evolution by the biologist Richard Dawkins, in which the author builds upon the principal theory of George C. Williams's Adaptation and Natural Selection (1966). Dawkins uses the term "selfish gene" as a way of expressing the gene-centred view of evolution (as opposed to the views focused on the organism and the group), popularising ideas developed during the 1960s by W. D. Hamilton
and others. From the gene-centred view, it follows that the more two
individuals are genetically related, the more sense (at the level of the
genes) it makes for them to behave selflessly with each other.
A lineage is expected to evolve to maximise its inclusive fitness—the
number of copies of its genes passed on globally (rather than by a
particular individual). As a result, populations will tend towards an evolutionarily stable strategy. The book also introduces the term meme for a unit of human cultural evolution analogous to the gene, suggesting that such "selfish" replication may also model human culture, in a different sense. Memetics
has become the subject of many studies since the publication of the
book. In raising awareness of Hamilton's ideas, as well as making its
own valuable contributions to the field, the book has also stimulated
research on human inclusive fitness.
In the foreword to the book's 30th-anniversary edition, Dawkins
said he "can readily see that [the book's title] might give an
inadequate impression of its contents" and in retrospect thinks he
should have taken Tom Maschler's advice and called the book The Immortal Gene.
In July 2017 a poll to celebrate the 30th anniversary of the Royal Society science book prize listed The Selfish Gene as the most influential science book of all time.
Background
Dawkins builds upon George C. Williams's book Adaptation and Natural Selection (1966), which argued that altruism is not based upon group benefit per se, but is a result of selection that occurs "at the level of the gene mediated by the phenotype" and any selection at the group level occurred only under rare circumstances. This approach was developed further during the 1960s by W. D. Hamilton and others who opposed group selection and selection aimed directly at benefit to the individual organism:
Despite the principle of 'survival of the fittest' the ultimate criterion which determines whether [a gene] G will spread is not whether the behavior is to the benefit of the behaver, but whether it is to the benefit of the gene G ...With altruism this will happen only if the affected individual is a relative of the altruist, therefore having an increased chance of carrying the gene.
- — W. D. Hamilton, The Evolution of Altruistic Behavior, pp. 354–355
An extended discussion of Dawkins' views and his book The Selfish Gene is provided by Wilkins and Hull.
Book
Contents
Dawkins begins by discussing the altruism that people display, indicating that he will argue it is explained by gene selfishness, and attacking group selection as an explanation. He considers the origin of life with the arrival of molecules able to replicate themselves. From there, he looks at DNA's role in evolution, and its organisation into chromosomes and genes, which in his view behave selfishly. He describes organisms as apparently purposive but fundamentally simple survival machines, which use negative feedback to achieve control. This extends, he argues, to the brain's ability to simulate the world with subjective consciousness, and signalling between species. He then introduces the idea of the evolutionarily stable strategy, and uses it to explain why alternative competitive strategies like bullying and retaliating exist. This allows him to consider what selfishness in a gene might actually mean, describing W. D. Hamilton's argument for kin selection, that genes for behaviour
that improves the survival chances of close relatives can spread in a
population, because those relatives carry the same genes.
Dawkins examines childbearing and raising children as
evolutionary strategies. He attacks the idea of group selection for the
good of the species as proposed by V. C. Wynne-Edwards,
arguing instead that each parent necessarily behaves selfishly. A
question is whether parents should invest in their offspring equally or
should favour some of them, and explains that what is best for the
survival of the parents' genes is not always best for individual
children. Similarly, Dawkins argues, there are conflicts of interest
between males and females, but he notes that R. A. Fisher showed that the optimal sex ratio is 50:50. He explains that this is true even in an extreme case like the harem-keeping elephant seal,
where 4% of the males get 88% of copulations. In that case, the
strategy of having a female offspring is safe, as she'll have a pup, but
the strategy of having a male can bring a large return (dozens of
pups), even though many males live out their lives as bachelors. Amotz Zahavi's theory of honest signalling explains stotting
as a selfish act, he argues, improving the springbok's chances of
escaping from a predator by indicating how difficult the chase would be.
Dawkins discusses why many species live in groups, achieving mutual benefits through mechanisms such as Hamilton's selfish herd model: each individual behaves selfishly but the result is herd behaviour. Altruism too can evolve, as in the social insects such as ants and bees, where workers give up the right to reproduce in favour of a sister, the queen; in their case, the unusual (haplodiploid) system of sex determination may have helped to bring this about, as females in a nest are exceptionally closely related.
The final chapter of the first edition introduced the idea of the meme, a culturally-transmitted
entity such as a hummable tune, by analogy to genetic transmission.
Dawkins describes God as an old idea which probably arose many times,
and which has sufficient psychological appeal to survive effectively in
the meme pool. The second edition (1989) added two more chapters.
Themes
"Selfish" genes
In describing genes as being "selfish", Dawkins states unequivocally
that he does not intend to imply that they are driven by any motives or will, but merely that their effects can be metaphorically and pedagogically described as if they were. His contention is that the genes that are passed on are the ones whose evolutionary consequences serve their own implicit interest (to continue the anthropomorphism)
in being replicated, not necessarily those of the organism. In later
work, Dawkins brings evolutionary "selfishness" down to creation of a
widely proliferated extended phenotype.
For some, the metaphor of "selfishness" is entirely clear, while
to others it is confusing, misleading, or simply silly to ascribe mental
attributes to something that is mindless. For example, Andrew Brown has written:
- ""Selfish", when applied to genes, doesn't mean "selfish" at all. It means, instead, an extremely important quality for which there is no good word in the English language: "the quality of being copied by a Darwinian selection process." This is a complicated mouthful. There ought to be a better, shorter word—but "selfish" isn't it."
Donald Symons
also finds it inappropriate to use anthropomorphism in conveying
scientific meaning in general, and particularly for the present
instance. He writes in The Evolution of Human Sexuality (1979):
- "In summary, the rhetoric of The Selfish Gene exactly reverses the real situation: through [the use of] metaphor genes are endowed with properties only sentient beings can possess, such as selfishness, while sentient beings are stripped of these properties and called machines...The anthropomorphism of genes...obscures the deepest mystery in the life sciences: the origin and nature of mind."
"Replicators"
Dawkins proposes the idea of the "replicator":
- "It is finally time to return to the problem with which we
started, to the tension between individual organism and gene as rival
candidates for the central role in natural selection...One way of
sorting this whole matter out is to use the terms ‘replicator’ and
‘vehicle’. The fundamental units of natural selection, the basic things
that survive or fail to survive, that form lineages of identical copies
with occasional random mutations, are called replicators. DNA molecules
are replicators. They generally, for reasons that we shall come to, gang
together into large communal survival machines or 'vehicles'."
- — Richard Dawkins, The Selfish Gene, p. 253 (Anniversary Edition)
The original replicator (Dawkins' Replicator) was the initial molecule which first managed to reproduce itself and thus gained an advantage over other molecules within the primordial soup.
As replicating molecules became more complex, Dawkins postulates, the
replicators became the genes within organisms, with each organism's body
serving the purpose of a 'survival machine' for its genes.
Dawkins writes that gene combinations which help an organism to
survive and reproduce tend to also improve the gene's own chances of
being replicated, and, as a result, "successful" genes frequently
provide a benefit to the organism. An example of this might be a gene
that protects the organism against a disease. This helps the gene
spread, and also helps the organism.
Genes vs organisms
There are other times when the implicit interests of the vehicle and
replicator are in conflict, such as the genes behind certain male
spiders' instinctive mating behaviour, which increase the organism's inclusive fitness by allowing it to reproduce, but shorten its life by exposing it to the risk of being eaten by the cannibalistic female. Another example is the existence of segregation distorter genes that are detrimental to their host, but nonetheless propagate themselves at its expense. Likewise, the persistence of junk DNA
that [Dawkins believed at that time] provides no benefit to its host
can be explained on the basis that it is not subject to selection. These
unselected for but transmitted DNA variations connect the individual
genetically to its parents, but confer no survival benefit.
These examples might suggest that there is a power struggle
between genes and their interactor. In fact, the claim is that there
isn't much of a struggle because the genes usually win without a fight.
However, the claim is made that if the organism becomes intelligent
enough to understand its own interests, as distinct from those of its
genes, there can be true conflict.
An example of such a conflict might be a person using birth
control to prevent fertilisation, thereby inhibiting the replication of
his or her genes. But this action might not be a conflict of the
'self-interest' of the organism with his or her genes, since a person
using birth control might also be enhancing the survival chances of
their genes by limiting family size to conform with available resources,
thus avoiding extinction as predicted under the Malthusian model of population growth.
Altruism
Dawkins says that his "purpose" in writing The Selfish Gene is
"to examine the biology of selfishness and altruism." He does this by
supporting the claim that "gene selfishness will usually give rise to
selfishness in individual behaviour. However, as we shall see, there are
special circumstances in which a gene can achieve its own selfish goals
best by fostering a limited form of altruism at the level of individual animals." Gene selection provides one explanation for kin selection and eusociality,
where organisms act altruistically, against their individual interests
(in the sense of health, safety or personal reproduction), namely the
argument that by helping related organisms reproduce, a gene succeeds in
"helping" copies of themselves (or sequences with the same phenotypic effect)
in other bodies to replicate. The claim is made that these "selfish"
actions of genes lead to unselfish actions by organisms. A requirement
upon this claim, supported by Dawkins in Chapter 10: "You scratch my
back, I'll ride on yours" by examples from nature, is the need to
explain how genes achieve kin recognition, or manage to orchestrate mutualism and coevolution.
Although Dawkins (and biologists in general) recognize these phenomena
result in more copies of a gene, evidence is inconclusive whether this
success is selected for at a group or individual level. In fact, Dawkins
has proposed that it is at the level of the extended phenotype:
- "We agree [referring to Wilson and Sober's book Unto others: The evolution and psychology of unselfish behavior]
that genes are replicators, organisms and groups are not. We agree that
the group selection controversy ought to be a controversy about groups
as vehicles, and we could easily agree to differ on the answer...I
coined the [term] vehicle not to praise it but to bury it....Darwinism
can work on replicators whose phenotypic effects (interactors) are too
diffuse, too multi-levelled, too incoherent to deserve the accolade of
vehicle...Extended phenotypes can include inanimate artifacts like
beaver dams...But the vehicle is not something fundamental...Ask rather
'Is there a vehicle in this situation and, if so, why?'"
- —Richard Dawkins, Burying the Vehicle
Although Dawkins agrees that groups can assist survival, they rank as
a "vehicle" for survival only if the group activity is replicated in
descendants, recorded in the gene, the gene being the only true
replicator. An improvement in the survival lottery for the group must
improve that for the gene for sufficient replication to occur. Dawkins
argues qualitatively that the lottery for the gene is based upon a very
long and broad record of events, and group advantages are usually too
specific, too brief, and too fortuitous to change the gene lottery.
-
- "We can now see that the organism and the group of organisms are true rivals for the vehicle role in the story, but neither of them is even a candidate for the replicator role. The controversy between ‘individual selection’ and ‘group selection’ is a real controversy between alternative vehicles...As it happens the outcome, in my view, is a decisive victory for the individual organism. The group is too wishy-washy an entity."
- —Richard Dawkins, The Selfish Gene, pp. 254-255
Prior to the 1960s, it was common for altruism to be explained in terms of group selection,
where the benefits to the organism or even population were supposed to
account for the popularity of the genes responsible for the tendency
towards that behaviour. Modern versions of "multilevel selection" claim to have overcome the original objections,
namely, that at that time no known form of group selection led to an
evolutionarily stable strategy. The claim still is made by some that it
would take only a single individual with a tendency towards more selfish
behaviour to undermine a population otherwise filled only with the gene
for altruism towards non-kin.
Reception
The Selfish Gene was extremely popular when first published, causing "a silent and almost immediate revolution in biology", and it continues to be widely read. It has sold over a million copies, and has been translated into more than 25 languages.
Proponents argue that the central point, that replicating the gene is
the object of selection, usefully completes and extends the explanation
of evolution given by Charles Darwin before the basic mechanisms of genetics were understood.
According to the ethologist Alan Grafen,
acceptance of adaptionist theories is hampered by a lack of a
mathematical unifying theory and a belief that anything in words alone
must be suspect.
According to Grafen, these difficulties along with an initial conflict
with population genetics models at the time of its introduction
"explains why within biology the considerable scientific contributions
it [The Selfish Gene] makes are seriously underestimated, and why it is viewed mainly as a work of exposition."
According to comparative psychologist Nicky Hayes, "Dawkins presented a
version of sociobiology that rested heavily on metaphors drawn from
animal behavior, and extrapolated these...One of the weaknesses of the
sociological approach is that it tends only to seek confirmatory
examples from among the huge diversity of animal behavior. Dawkins did
not deviate from this tradition." More generally, critics argue that The Selfish Gene oversimplifies the relationship between genes and the organism. (As an example, see Thompson.)
The Selfish Gene further popularised sociobiology in Japan after its translation in 1980.
With the addition of Dawkins's book to the country's
consciousness, the term "meme" entered popular culture. Yuzuru Tanaka of
Hokkaido University wrote a book, Meme Media and Meme Market Architectures, while the psychologist Susan Blackmore wrote The Meme Machine (2000), with a foreword by Dawkins. The information scientist Osamu Sakura has published a book in Japanese and several papers in English on the topic. Nippon Animation produced an educational television program titled The Many Journeys of Meme.
In 1976, the ecologist Arthur Cain,
one of Dawkins's tutors at Oxford in the 1960s, called it a "young
man's book" (which Dawkins points out was a deliberate quote of a
commentator on the New College, Oxford philosopher A. J. Ayer's Language, Truth, and Logic
(1936)). Dawkins noted that he had been "flattered by the comparison,
[but] knew that Ayer had recanted much of his first book and [he] could
hardly miss Cain's pointed implication that [he] should, in the fullness
of time, do the same." This point also was made by the philosopher Mary Midgley: "The same thing happened to AJ Ayer, she says, but he spent the rest of his career taking back what he'd written in Language, Truth and Logic. "This hasn't occurred to Dawkins", she says. "He goes on saying the same thing."" However, according to Wilkins and Hull, Dawkins' thinking has developed, although perhaps not defusing this criticism:
- "In Dawkins' early writings, replicators and vehicles played
different but complementary and equally important roles in selection,
but as Dawkins honed his view of the evolutionary process, vehicles
became less and less fundamental... In later writings Dawkins goes even
further and argues that phenotypic traits are what really matter in
selection and that they can be treated independently of their being
organized into vehicles....Thus, it comes as no surprise when Dawkins
proclaims that he "coined the term ‘vehicle’ not to praise it but to
bury it."
As prevalent as organisms might be, as determinate as the causal roles
that they play in selection are, reference to them can and must be
omitted from any perspicuous characterization of selection in the
evolutionary process. Dawkins is far from a genetic determinist, but he is certainly a genetic reductionist."
- — John S Wilkins, David Hull, Dawkins on Replicators and Vehicles, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
Units of selection
As to the unit of selection:
"One internally consistent logical picture is that the unit of
replication is the gene,...and the organism is one kind of ...entity on
which selection acts directly."
Dawkins proposed the matter without a distinction between 'unit of
replication' and 'unit of selection' that he made elsewhere: "the
fundamental unit of selection, and therefore of self-interest, is not
the species, nor the group, nor even strictly the individual. It is the
gene, the unit of heredity." However, he continues in a later chapter:
- "On any sensible view of the matter Darwinian selection does not
work on genes directly. ...The important differences between genes
emerge only in their effects. The technical word phenotype
is used for the bodily manifestation of a gene, the effect that a gene
has on the body...Natural selection favours some genes rather than
others not because of the nature of the genes themselves, but because of
their consequences—their phenotypic effects...But we shall now see that
the phenotypic effects of a gene need to be thought of as all the effects that it has on the world.
...The phenotypic effects of a gene are the tools by which it levers
itself into the next generation. All I am going to add is that the tools
may reach outside the individual body wall...Examples that spring to
mind are artefacts like beaver dams, bird nests, and caddis houses."
- — Richard Dawkins, The Selfish Gene, Chapter 13, pp. 234, 235, 238
Dawkins' later formulation is in his book The Extended Phenotype (1982), where the process of selection is taken to involve every possible phenotypical effect of a gene.
Stephen Jay Gould finds Dawkins' position tries to have it both ways:
- "Dawkins claims to prefer genes and to find greater insight in
this formulation. But he allows that you or I might prefer organisms—and
it really doesn't matter."
- — Stephen Jay Gould, The Structure of Evolutionary Theory, pp. 640-641
The view of The Selfish Gene is that selection based upon
groups and populations is rare compared to selection on individuals.
Although supported by Dawkins and by many others, this claim continues
to be disputed. While naïve versions of group selectionism
have been disproved, more sophisticated formulations make accurate
predictions in some cases while positing selection at higher levels.
Both sides agree that very favourable genes are likely to prosper and
replicate if they arise and both sides agree that living in groups can
be an advantage to the group members. The conflict arises in part over
defining concepts:
- "Cultural evolutionary theory, however, has suffered from an overemphasis on the experiences and behaviors of individuals at the expense of acknowledging complex group organization...Many important behaviors related to the success and function of human societies are only properly defined at the level of groups".
In The Social Conquest of Earth (2012), the entomologist E. O. Wilson
contends that although the selfish-gene approach was accepted "until
2010 [when] Martin Nowak, Corina Tarnita, and I demonstrated that
inclusive fitness theory, often called kin selection theory, is both
mathematically and biologically incorrect." Chapter 18 of The Social Conquest of Earth
describes the deficiencies of kin selection and outlines group
selection, which Wilson argues is a more realistic model of social
evolution. He criticises earlier approaches to social evolution, saying:
"...unwarranted faith in the central role of kinship in social
evolution has led to the reversal of the usual order in which biological
research is conducted. The proven best way in evolutionary biology, as
in most of science, is to define a problem arising during empirical
research, then select or devise the theory that is needed to solve it.
Almost all research in inclusive-fitness theory has been the opposite:
hypothesize the key roles of kinship and kin selection, then look for
evidence to test that hypothesis." According to Wilson: "People must
have a tribe...Experiments conducted over many years by social
psychologists have revealed how swiftly and decisively people divide
into groups, and then discriminate in favor of the one to which they
belong." (pp. 57, 59) According to Wilson: "Different parts of the brain
have evolved by group selection to create groupishness." (p. 61)
Some authors consider facets of this debate between Dawkins and his critics about the level of selection to be blather:
- "The particularly frustrating aspects of these constantly
renewed debates is that, even though they seemed to be sparked by rival
theories about how evolution works, in fact they often involve only
rival metaphors for the very same evolutionary logic and [the debates
over these aspects] are thus empirically empty."
- — Laurent Keller, Levels of Selection in Evolution, p.4
Other authors say Dawkins has failed to make some critical
distinctions, in particular, the difference between group selection for
group advantage and group selection conveying individual advantage.
Choice of words
A good deal of objection to The Selfish Gene stemmed from its
failure to be always clear about "selection" and "replication". Dawkins
says the gene is the fundamental unit of selection, and then points out
that selection doesn't act directly upon the gene, but upon "vehicles"
or '"extended phenotypes". Stephen Jay Gould took exception to calling the gene a 'unit of selection' because selection acted only upon phenotypes. Summarizing the Dawkins-Gould difference of view, Sterelny says:
- "Gould thinks gene differences do not cause evolutionary changes in populations, they register those changes."
- —Kim Sterelny: Dawkins vs. Gould, p. 83
The word "cause" here is somewhat tricky: does a change in lottery
rules (for example, inheriting a defective gene "responsible" for a
disorder) "cause" differences in outcome that might or might not occur?
It certainly alters the likelihood of events, but a concatenation of
contingencies decides what actually occurs. Dawkins thinks the use of
"cause" as a statistical weighting is acceptable in common usage. Like Gould, Gabriel Dover in criticizing The Selfish Gene says:
- "It is illegitimate to give 'powers' to genes, as Dawkins would
have it, to control the outcome of selection...There are no genes for
interactions, as such: rather, each unique set of inherited genes
contributes interactively to one unique phenotype...the true
determinants of selection".
- — Gabriel Dover: Dear Mr. Darwin, p. 56
However, from a comparison with Dawkins' discussion of this very same
point, it would seem both Gould's and Dover's comments are more a
critique of his sloppy usage than a difference of views. Hull suggested a resolution based upon a distinction between replicators and interactors. The term "replicator" includes genes as the most fundamental replicators but possibly other agents, and interactor includes organisms but maybe other agents, much as do Dawkins' 'vehicles'. The distinction is as follows:
- replicator: an entity that passes on its structure largely intact in successive replications.
- interactor: an entity that interacts as a cohesive whole with its environment in such a way that this interaction causes replication to be differential.
- selection: a process in which the differential extinction or proliferation of interactors causes the differential perpetuation of the replicators that produced them.
Hull suggests that, despite some similarities, Dawkins takes too
narrow a view of these terms, engendering some of the objections to his
views. According to Godfrey-Smith, this more careful vocabulary has
cleared up "misunderstandings in the "units of selection" debates."
Enactive arguments
Behavioural genetics entertains the view:
- "that genes are dynamic contributors to behavioral organization
and are sensitive to feedback systems from the internal and external
environments." "Technically behavior is not inherited; only DNA
molecules are inherited. From that point on behavioral formation is a
problem of constant interplay between genetic potential and
environmental shaping."
- —D.D. Thiessen, Mechanism specific approaches in behavior genetics, p. 91
This view from 1970 is still espoused today,
and conflicts with Dawkins' view of "the gene as a form of "information
[that] passes through bodies and affects them, but is not affected by
them on its way through"". The philosophical/biological field of enactivism
stresses the interaction of the living agent with its environment and
the relation of probing the environment to cognition and adaptation. Gene activation
depends upon the cellular milieu. An extended discussion of the
contrasts between enactivism and Dawkins' views, and with their support
by Dennett, is provided by Thompson.
In Mind in Life, the philosopher Evan Thompson has assembled a multi-sourced objection to the "selfish gene" idea. Thompson takes issue with Dawkin's reduction of "life" to "genes" and "information":
- "Life is just bytes and bytes and bytes of digital information"[50]
-
- — Richard Dawkins: River out of Eden: A Darwinian View of Life, p. 19
-
- "On the bank of the Oxford canal...is a large willow tree, and it is pumping downy seeds into the air...It is raining instructions out there; it's raining programs; it's raining tree-growing, fluff-spreading algorithms. That is not a metaphor, it is the plain truth"
-
- — Richard Dawkins: The Blind Watchmaker, p. 111
Thompson objects that the gene cannot operate by itself, since it
requires an environment such as a cell, and life is "the creative
outcome of highly structured contingencies". Thompson quotes Sarkar:
- "there is no clear technical notion of "information" in
molecular biology. It is little more than a metaphor that masquerades as
a theoretical concept and ...leads to a misleading picture of the
nature of possible explanations in molecular biology."
- — Sahotra Sarkar Biological information: a skeptical look at some central dogmas of molecular biology, p. 187
Thompson follows with a detailed examination of the concept of DNA as a look-up-table and the role of the cell in orchestrating the DNA-to-RNA transcription,
indicating that by anyone's account the DNA is hardly the whole story.
Thompson goes on to suggest that the cell-environment interrelationship
has much to do with reproduction and inheritance, and a focus on the
gene as a form of "information [that] passes through bodies and affects
them, but is not affected by them on its way through"
is tantamount to adoption of a form of material-informational dualism
that has no explanatory value and no scientific basis. (Thomson, p. 187)
The enactivist
view, however, is that information results from the probing and
experimentation of the agent with the agent's environment subject to the
limitations of the agent's abilities to probe and process the result of
probing, and DNA is simply one mechanism the agent brings to bear upon
its activity.
Moral arguments
Another criticism of the book is its treatment of morality, and more
particularly altruism, as existing only as a form of selfishness:
- "It is important to realize that the above definitions of altruism and selfishness are behavioural,
not subjective. I am not concerned here with the psychology of
motives...My definition is concerned only with whether the effect of an
act is to lower or raise the survival prospects of the presumed altruist
and the survival prospects of the presumed beneficiary."
- — Richard Dawkins, The Selfish Gene, p. 12
- "We can even discuss ways of cultivating and nurturing pure,
disinterested altruism, something that has no place in nature, something
that has never existed before in the whole history of the world."
- — Richard Dawkins, The Selfish Gene, p. 179
The philosopher Mary Midgley has suggested this position is a variant of Hobbes' explanation of altruism as enlightened self-interest,
and that Dawkins goes a step further to suggest that our genetic
programming can be overcome by what amounts to an extreme version of free will. Part of Mary Midgley's concern is that Richard Dawkins' account of The Selfish Gene
serves as a moral and ideological justification for selfishness to be
adopted by modern human societies as simply following "nature",
providing an excuse for behavior with bad consequences for future human
society.
Dawkins' major concluding theme, that humanity is finally gaining
power over the "selfish replicators" by virtue of their intelligence,
is criticized also by primatologist Frans de Waal, who refers to it as an example of a "veneer theory" (the idea that morality is not fundamental, but is laid over a brutal foundation). Dawkins claims he merely describes how things are under evolution, and makes no moral arguments. On BBC-2 TV, Dawkins pointed to evidence for a "Tit-for-Tat" strategy (shown to be successful in game theory) as the most common, simple, and profitable choice.
More generally, the objection has been made that The Selfish Gene discusses philosophical and moral questions that go beyond biological arguments, relying upon anthropomorphisms and careless analogies.
Publication
The Selfish Gene was first published by Oxford University Press in 1976 in eleven chapters with a preface by the author and a foreword by Robert Trivers.
A second edition was published in 1989. This edition added two extra
chapters, and substantial endnotes to the preceding chapters, reflecting
new findings and thoughts. It also added a second preface by the
author, but the original foreword by Trivers was dropped. The book
contains no illustrations.
The book has been translated into at least 23 languages including Arabic, Thai and Turkish.
In 2006, a 30th-anniversary edition was published with the Trivers foreword and a new introduction by the author. It was accompanied by a festschrift entitled Richard Dawkins: How a Scientist Changed the Way We Think (2006). In March 2006, a special event entitled The Selfish Gene: Thirty Years On was held at the London School of Economics. In March 2011, Audible Inc published an audiobook edition narrated by Richard Dawkins and Lalla Ward.
In 2016, Oxford University Press published a 40th anniversary
edition with a new epilogue, in which Dawkins describes the continued
relevance of the gene's eye view of evolution and states that it, along with coalescence analysis "illuminates the deep past in ways of which I had no inkling when I first wrote The Selfish Gene...."