First edition cover
| |
Author | Richard Dawkins |
---|---|
Country | United Kingdom |
Language | English |
Subject | Evolutionary biology |
Publisher | Norton & Company, Inc |
Publication date
| 1986 |
Media type | |
ISBN | 0-393-31570-3 |
OCLC | 35648431 |
576.8/2 21 | |
LC Class | QH366.2 .D37 1996 |
Preceded by | The Extended Phenotype |
Followed by | River Out of Eden |
The Blind Watchmaker: Why the Evidence of Evolution Reveals a Universe without Design is a 1986 book by Richard Dawkins, in which the author presents an explanation of, and argument for, the theory of evolution by means of natural selection. He also presents arguments to refute certain criticisms made on his first book, The Selfish Gene. (Both books espouse the gene-centric view of evolution.) An unabridged audiobook edition was released in 2011, narrated by Richard Dawkins and Lalla Ward.
Overview
In his choice of the title for this book, Dawkins refers to the watchmaker analogy made famous by William Paley in his 1802 book Natural Theology. Paley, writing long before Charles Darwin published On the Origin of Species in 1859, held that the complexity of living organisms was evidence of the existence of a divine creator
by drawing a parallel with the way in which the existence of a watch
compels belief in an intelligent watchmaker. Dawkins, in contrasting the
differences between human design and its potential for planning with
the workings of natural selection, therefore dubbed evolutionary
processes as analogous to a blind watchmaker.
To dispel the idea that complexity cannot arise without the
intervention of a "creator", Dawkins uses the example of the eye.
Beginning with a simple organism, capable only of distinguishing between
light and dark, in only the crudest fashion, he takes the reader
through a series of minor modifications, which build in sophistication
until we arrive at the elegant and complex mammalian eye. In making this
journey, he points to several creatures whose various seeing apparatus
are, whilst still useful, living examples of intermediate levels of
complexity.
In developing his argument that natural selection can explain the
complex adaptations of organisms, Dawkins' first concern is to
illustrate the difference between the potential for the development of
complexity as a result of pure randomness, as opposed to that of
randomness coupled with cumulative selection. He demonstrates this by
the example of the weasel program. Dawkins then describes his experiences with a more sophisticated computer model of artificial selection implemented in a program also called The Blind Watchmaker, which was sold separately as a teaching aid.
The program displayed a two-dimensional shape (a "biomorph") made
up of straight black lines, the length, position, and angle of which
were defined by a simple set of rules and instructions (analogous to a
genome). Adding new lines (or removing them) based on these rules
offered a discrete set of possible new shapes (mutations), which were
displayed on screen so that the user could choose between them. The
chosen mutation would then be the basis for another generation of
biomorph mutants to be chosen from, and so on. Thus, the user, by
selection, could steer the evolution of biomorphs. This process often
produced images which were reminiscent of real organisms for instance beetles, bats, or trees.
Dawkins speculated that the unnatural selection role played by the user
in this program could be replaced by a more natural agent if, for
example, colourful biomorphs could be selected by butterflies or other
insects, via a touch-sensitive display set up in a garden.
In an appendix to a later edition of the book (1996), Dawkins
explains how his experiences with computer models led him to a greater
appreciation of the role of embryological
constraints on natural selection. In particular, he recognised that
certain patterns of embryological development could lead to the success
of a related group of species in filling varied ecological niches, though he emphasised that this should not be confused with group selection. He dubbed this insight the evolution of evolvability.
After arguing that evolution is capable of explaining the origin
of complexity, near the end of the book Dawkins uses this to argue
against the existence of God: "a deity capable of engineering all the
organized complexity in the world, either instantaneously or by guiding
evolution ... must already have been vastly complex in the first place
..." He calls this "postulating organized complexity without offering an
explanation."
In the preface, Dawkins states that he wrote the book "to persuade the reader, not just that the Darwinian world-view happens to be true, but that it is the only known theory that could, in principle, solve the mystery of our existence."
Reception
Tim Radford, writing in The Guardian,
noted that despite Dawkins's "combative secular humanism", he had
written "a patient, often beautiful book from 1986 that begins in a
generous mood and sustains its generosity to the end." 30 years on,
people still read the book, Radford argues, because it is "one of the
best books ever to address, patiently and persuasively, the question
that has baffled bishops and disconcerted dissenters alike: how did
nature achieve its astonishing complexity and variety?"
The philosopher and historian of biology, Michael T. Ghiselin, writing in The New York Times,
comments that Dawkins "succeeds admirably in showing how natural
selection allows biologists to dispense with such notions as purpose and
design". He notes that analogies with computer programs have their
limitations, but are still useful. Ghiselin observes that Dawkins is
"NOT content with rebutting creationists" but goes on to press home his
arguments against alternative theories to neo-Darwinism.
He thinks the book fills the need to know more about evolution "that
others [creationists] would conceal from them." He concludes that
"Readers who are not outraged will be delighted."
The American philosopher of religion Dallas Willard,
reflecting on the book, denies the connection of evolution to the
validity of arguments from design to God: whereas, he asserts, Dawkins
seems to consider the arguments to rest entirely on that basis. Willard
argues that Chapter 6, "Origins and Miracles", attempts the "hard task"
of making not just a blind watchmaker but "a blind watchmaker
watchmaker", which he comments would have made an "honest" title for the
book. He notes that Dawkins demolishes several "weak" arguments, such
as the argument from personal incredulity. He denies that Dawkins's
computer "exercises" and arguments from gradual change show that complex
forms of life could have evolved. Willard concludes by arguing that in
writing this book, Dawkins is not functioning as a scientist "in the
line of Darwin", but as "just a naturalist metaphysician".
Influence
The engineer Theo Jansen read the book in 1986 and became fascinated by evolution and natural selection. Since 1990 he has been building kinetic sculptures, the Strandbeest, capable of walking when impelled by the wind.
The journalist Dick Pountain described Sean B. Carroll's 2005 account of evolutionary developmental biology, Endless Forms Most Beautiful, as the most important popular science book since The Blind Watchmaker, "and in effect a sequel [to it]."